SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
Nos. 11–393, 11–398 and 11–400
_________________
NATIONAL FEDERATION OF INDEPENDENT
BUSINESS, et al., PETITIONERS
11–393
v.
KATHLEEN SEBELIUS, SECRETARY OF HEALTH
AND HUMAN SERVICES, et al.
DEPARTMENT OF HEALTH AND HUMAN SERVICES,
et al., PETITIONERS
11–398
v.
FLORIDA et al.
FLORIDA, et al., PETITIONERS
11–400
v.
DEPARTMENT OF HEALTH AND HUMAN SERVICES
et al.
on writs of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the eleventh circuit
[June 28, 2012]
Justice Ginsburg, with whom Justice Sotomayor
joins, and with whom Justice Breyer and Justice Kagan join as to
Parts I, II, III, and IV, concurring in part, concurring in the
judgment in part, and dissenting in part.
I agree with The Chief Justice that the
Anti-Injunction Act does not bar the Court’s consideration of this
case, and that the minimum coverage provision is a proper exercise
of Congress’ taxing power. I therefore join Parts I, II, and III–C
of The Chief Justice’s opinion. Unlike The Chief Justice, however,
I would hold, alternatively, that the Commerce Clause authorizes
Congress to enact the minimum coverage provision. I would also hold
that the Spending Clause permits the Medicaid expansion exactly as
Congress enacted it.
I
The provision of health care is today a
concern of national dimension, just as the provision of old-age and
survivors’ benefits was in the 1930’s. In the Social Secu- rity
Act, Congress installed a federal system to provide monthly
benefits to retired wage earners and, eventually, to their
survivors. Beyond question, Congress could have adopted a similar
scheme for health care. Congress chose, instead, to preserve a
central role for private insurers and state governments. According
to The Chief Justice, the Commerce Clause does not permit that
preservation. This rigid reading of the Clause makes scant sense
and is stunningly retrogressive.
Since 1937, our precedent has recognized
Congress’ large authority to set the Nation’s course in the
economic and social welfare realm. See
United States v.
Darby,
312 U.S.
100, 115 (1941) (overruling
Hammer v.
Dagenhart,
247 U.S.
251 (1918), and recognizing that “regulations of commerce which
do not infringe some constitutional prohibi- tion are within the
plenary power conferred on Congress by the Commerce Clause”);
NLRB v.
Jones & Laughlin Steel Corp.,
301 U.S.
1, 37 (1937) (“[The commerce] power is plenary and may be
exerted to protect interstate commerce no matter what the source of
the dangers which threaten it.” (internal quotation marks
omitted)). The Chief Justice’s crabbed reading of the Commerce
Clause harks back to the era in which the Court routinely thwarted
Congress’ efforts to regulate the national economy in the interest
of those who labor to sustain it. See,
e.g.,
Railroad
Retirement Bd. v.
Alton R. Co.,
295
U.S. 330, 362, 368 (1935) (invalidating compulsory retirement
and pension plan for employees of carriers subject to the
Interstate Commerce Act; Court found law related essentially “to
the social welfare of the worker, and therefore remote from any
regulation of commerce as such”). It is a reading that should not
have staying power.
A
In enacting the Patient Protection and
Affordable Care Act (ACA), Congress comprehensively reformed the
national market for health-care products and services. By any
measure, that market is immense. Collectively, Americans spent $2.5
trillion on health care in 2009, accounting for 17.6% of our
Nation’s economy. 42 U. S. C. §18091(2)(B) (2006 ed.,
Supp. IV). Within the next decade, it is anticipated, spending on
health care will nearly double.
Ibid.
The health-care market’s size is not its only
distinctive feature. Unlike the market for almost any other product
or service, the market for medical care is one in which all
individuals inevitably participate. Virtually every person residing
in the United States, sooner or later, will visit a doctor or other
health-care professional. See Dept. of Health and Human Services,
National Center for Health Statistics, Summary Health Statistics
for U. S. Adults: National Health Interview Survey 2009, Ser.
10, No. 249, p. 124, Table 37 (Dec. 2010) (Over 99.5% of adults
above 65 have visited a health-care professional.). Most people
will do so repeatedly. See
id., at 115, Table 34 (In 2009
alone, 64% of adults made two or more visits to a doctor’s
office.).
When individuals make those visits, they face
another reality of the current market for medical care: its high
cost. In 2010, on average, an individual in the United States
incurred over $7,000 in health-care expenses. Dept. of Health and
Human Services, Centers for Medicare and Medicaid Services,
Historic National Health Expenditure Data, National Health
Expenditures: Se- lected Calendar Years 1960–2010 (Table 1). Over a
lifetime, costs mount to hundreds of thousands of dollars. See
Alemayahu & Warner, The Lifetime Distribution of Health Care
Costs, in 39 Health Service Research 627, 635 (June 2004). When a
person requires nonroutine care, the cost will generally exceed
what he or she can afford to pay. A single hospital stay, for
instance, typically costs upwards of $10,000. See Dept. of Health
and Human Services, Office of Health Policy, ASPE Research Brief:
The Value of Health Insurance 5 (May 2011). Treatments for many
serious, though not uncommon, conditions similarly cost a
substantial sum. Brief for Economic Scholars as
Amici Curiae
in No. 11–398, p. 10 (citing a study indicating that, in 1998, the
cost of treating a heart attack for the first 90 days exceeded
$20,000, while the annual cost of treating certain cancers was more
than $50,000).
Although every U. S. domiciliary will incur
significant medical expenses during his or her lifetime, the time
when care will be needed is often unpredictable. An accident, a
heart attack, or a cancer diagnosis commonly occurs without
warning. Inescapably, we are all at peril of needing medical care
without a moment’s notice. See,
e.g., Campbell, Down the
Insurance Rabbit Hole, N. Y. Times, Apr. 5, 2012, p. A23
(telling of an uninsured 32-year-old woman who, healthy one day,
became a quadriplegic the next due to an auto accident).
To manage the risks associated with medical
care— its high cost, its unpredictability, and its
inevitability—most people in the United States obtain health
insurance. Many (approximately 170 million in 2009) are insured by
private insurance companies. Others, including those over 65 and
certain poor and disabled persons, rely on government-funded
insurance programs, notably Medicare and Medicaid. Combined,
private health insurers and State and Federal Governments finance
almost 85% of the medical care administered to U. S.
residents. See Congressional Budget Office, CBO’s 2011 Long-Term
Budget Outlook 37 (June 2011).
Not all U. S. residents, however, have
health insurance. In 2009, approximately 50 million people were
uninsured, either by choice or, more likely, because they could not
afford private insurance and did not qualify for government aid.
See Dept. of Commerce, Census Bureau, C. DeNavas-Walt, B. Proctor,
& J. Smith, Income, Poverty, and Health Insurance Coverage in
the United States: 2009, p. 23, Table 8 (Sept. 2010). As a
group, uninsured individuals annually consume more than $100
billion in health- care services, nearly 5% of the Nation’s total.
Hidden Health Tax: Americans Pay a Premium 2 (2009), avail- able at
http://www.familiesusa.org (all Internet mate- rial as visited June
25, 2012, and included in Clerk of Court’s case file). Over 60% of
those without insurance visit a doctor’s office or emergency room
in a given year. See Dept. of Health and Human Services, National
Cen- ter for Health Statistics, Health—United States—2010,
p. 282, Table 79 (Feb. 2011).
B
The large number of individuals without health
insurance, Congress found, heavily burdens the national health-care
market. See 42 U. S. C. §18091(2). As just noted, the
cost of emergency care or treatment for a serious illness generally
exceeds what an individual can afford to pay on her own. Unlike
markets for most products, however, the inability to pay for care
does not mean that an uninsured individual will receive no care.
Federal and state law, as well as professional obligations and
embedded social norms, require hospitals and physicians to provide
care when it is most needed, regardless of the patient’s ability to
pay. See,
e.g., 42 U. S. C. §1395dd; Fla. Stat.
§395.1041(3)(f) (2010); Tex. Health & Safety Code Ann.
§§311.022(a) and (b) (West 2010); American Medical Association,
Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs, Code of Medical Ethics,
Current Opinions: Opinion 8.11—Neglect of Patient, p. 70
(1998–1999 ed.).
As a consequence, medical-care providers deliver
sig- nificant amounts of care to the uninsured for which the
providers receive no payment. In 2008, for example, hospi- tals,
physicians, and other health-care professionals received no
compensation for $43 billion worth of the $116 billion in care they
administered to those without insurance. 42 U. S. C.
§18091(2)(F) (2006 ed., Supp. IV).
Health-care providers do not absorb these bad
debts. Instead, they raise their prices, passing along the cost of
uncompensated care to those who do pay reliably: the government and
private insurance companies. In response, private insurers increase
their premiums, shifting the cost of the elevated bills from
providers onto those who carry insurance. The net result: Those
with health insurance subsidize the medical care of those without
it. As economists would describe what happens, the uninsured “free
ride” on those who pay for health insurance.
The size of this subsidy is considerable.
Congress found that the cost-shifting just described “increases
family [insurance] premiums by on average over $1,000 a year.”
Ibid. Higher premiums, in turn, render health insurance less
affordable, forcing more people to go without insurance and leading
to further cost-shifting.
And it is hardly just the currently sick or
injured among the uninsured who prompt elevation of the price of
health care and health insurance. Insurance companies and
health-care providers know that some percentage of healthy,
uninsured people will suffer sickness or injury each year and will
receive medical care despite their inability to pay. In
anticipation of this uncompensated care, health-care companies
raise their prices, and insurers their premiums. In other words,
because any uninsured person may need medical care at any moment
and because health-care companies must account for that risk, every
uninsured person impacts the market price of medical care and
medical insurance.
The failure of individuals to acquire insurance
has other deleterious effects on the health-care market. Because
those without insurance generally lack access to preventative care,
they do not receive treatment for conditions—like hypertension and
diabetes—that can be successfully and affordably treated if
diagnosed early on. See Institute of Medicine, National Academies,
Insuring America’s Health: Principles and Recommendations 43
(2004). When sickness finally drives the uninsured to seek care,
once treatable conditions have escalated into grave health
problems, requiring more costly and extensive intervention.
Id., at 43–44. The extra time and resources providers spend
serving the uninsured lessens the providers’ ability to care for
those who do have insurance. See Kliff, High Uninsured Rates Can
Kill You—Even if You Have Coverage, Washington Post (May 7, 2012)
(describing a study of California’s health-care market which found
that, when hospitals divert time and resources to provide
uncompensated care, the quality of care the hospitals deliver to
those with insurance drops significantly), availa- ble at
http://www.washingtonpost.com/blogs/ezra-klein/post/
high-uninsured-rates-can-kill-you-even-if-you-have-coverage/2012/
05/07/gIQALNHN8T_print.html.
C
States cannot resolve the problem of the
uninsured on their own. Like Social Security benefits, a universal
health-care system, if adopted by an individual State, would be
“bait to the needy and dependent elsewhere, encouraging them to
migrate and seek a haven of repose.”
Helvering v.
Davis,
301
U.S. 619, 644 (1937). See also Brief for Commonwealth of
Massachusetts as
Amicus Curiae in No. 11–398, p. 15
(noting that, in 2009, Massachusetts’ emergency rooms served
thousands of uninsured, out-of-state residents). An influx of
unhealthy individuals into a State with universal health care would
result in increased spending on medical services. To cover the
increased costs, a State would have to raise taxes, and private
health-insurance companies would have to increase premiums. Higher
taxes and increased insurance costs would, in turn, encourage
businesses and healthy individuals to leave the State.
States that undertake health-care reforms on
their own thus risk “placing themselves in a position of economic
disadvantage as compared with neighbors or competitors.”
Davis, 301 U. S., at 644. See also Brief for Health
Care for All, Inc., et al. as
Amici Curiae in No.
11–398, p. 4 (“[O]ut-of-state residents continue to seek and
receive millions of dollars in uncompensated care in Massachusetts
hospitals, limiting the State’s efforts to improve its health care
system through the elimination of uncompensated care.”). Facing
that risk, individual States are unlikely to take the initiative in
addressing the problem of the uninsured, even though solving that
problem is in all States’ best interests. Congress’ intervention
was needed to overcome this collective- action impasse.
D
Aware that a national solution was required,
Congress could have taken over the health-insurance market by
establishing a tax-and-spend federal program like Social Security.
Such a program, commonly referred to as a single-payer system
(where the sole payer is the Federal Government), would have left
little, if any, room for private enterprise or the States. Instead
of going this route, Congress enacted the ACA, a solution that
retains a robust role for private insurers and state governments.
To make its chosen approach work, however, Congress had to use some
new tools, including a requirement that most individuals obtain
private health insurance coverage. See 26 U. S. C. §5000A
(2006 ed., Supp. IV) (the minimum coverage provision). As explained
below, by employing these tools, Congress was able to achieve a
practical, alto- gether reasonable, solution.
A central aim of the ACA is to reduce the number
of uninsured U. S. residents. See 42 U. S. C.
§18091(2)(C) and (I) (2006 ed., Supp. IV). The minimum coverage
provision advances this objective by giving potential recipients of
health care a financial incentive to acquire insurance. Per the
minimum coverage provision, an individual must either obtain
insurance or pay a toll constructed as a tax penalty. See 26
U. S. C. §5000A.
The minimum coverage provision serves a further
purpose vital to Congress’ plan to reduce the number of uninsured.
Congress knew that encouraging individuals to purchase insurance
would not suffice to solve the problem, because most of the
uninsured are not uninsured by choice.[
1] Of particular concern to Congress were people who,
though desperately in need of insurance, often cannot acquire it:
persons who suffer from preexisting medical conditions.
Before the ACA’s enactment, private insurance
companies took an applicant’s medical history into account when
setting insurance rates or deciding whether to insure an
individual. Because individuals with preexisting med- ical
conditions cost insurance companies significantly more than those
without such conditions, insurers routinely re- fused to insure
these individuals, charged them substantially higher premiums, or
offered only limited coverage that did not include the preexisting
illness. See Dept. of Health and Human Services, Coverage Denied:
How the Current Health Insurance System Leaves Millions Behind 1
(2009) (Over the past three years, 12.6 million non- elderly adults
were denied insurance coverage or charged higher premiums due to a
preexisting condition.).
To ensure that individuals with medical
histories have access to affordable insurance, Congress devised a
three-part solution. First, Congress imposed a “guaranteed is- sue”
requirement, which bars insurers from denying coverage to any
person on account of that person’s medical condition or history.
See 42 U. S. C. §§300gg–1, 300gg–3, 300gg–4(a) (2006 ed.,
Supp. IV). Second, Congress required insurers to use “community
rating” to price their insurance policies. See §300gg. Community
rating, in effect, bars insurance companies from charging higher
premiums to those with preexisting conditions.
But these two provisions, Congress comprehended,
could not work effectively unless individuals were given a powerful
incentive to obtain insurance. See Hearings before the House Ways
and Means Committee, 111th Cong., 1st Sess., 10, 13 (2009)
(statement of Uwe Reinhardt) (“[I]m- position of
community-rated
premiums and
guaranteed issue on a market of competing
private health insurers will inexorably drive that market into
extinction, unless these two features are coupled with
. . .
a mandate on individual[s] to be insured.”
(emphasis in original)).
In the 1990’s, several States—including New
York, New Jersey, Washington, Kentucky, Maine, New Hampshire, and
Vermont—enacted guaranteed-issue and community-rating laws without
requiring universal acquisition of insurance coverage. The results
were disastrous. “All seven states suffered from skyrocketing
insurance pre- mium costs, reductions in individuals with coverage,
and reductions in insurance products and providers.” Brief for
American Association of People with Disabilities et al. as
Amici Curiae in No. 11–398, p. 9 (hereinafter AAPD
Brief). See also Brief for Governor of Washington Christine
Gregoire as
Amicus Curiae in No. 11–398, pp. 11–14
(describing the “death spiral” in the insurance market Washington
experienced when the State passed a law requiring coverage for
preexisting conditions).
Congress comprehended that guaranteed-issue and
community-rating laws alone will not work. When insurance companies
are required to insure the sick at affordable prices, individuals
can wait until they become ill to buy insurance. Pretty soon, those
in need of immediate medical care—
i.e., those who cost
insurers the most—become the insurance companies’ main customers.
This “adverse selection” problem leaves insurers with two choices:
They can either raise premiums dramatically to cover their
ever-increasing costs or they can exit the market. In the seven
States that tried guaranteed-issue and community-rating
requirements without a minimum coverage provision, that is
precisely what insurance companies did. See,
e.g., AAPD
Brief 10 (“[In Maine,] [m]any insurance providers doubled their
premiums in just three years or less.”);
id., at 12 (“Like
New York, Vermont saw substantial increases in premiums after its
. . . insurance reform measures took effect in 1993.”);
Hall, An Evaluation of New York’s Reform Law, 25 J. Health Pol.
Pol’y & L. 71, 91–92 (2000) (Guaranteed-issue and
community-rating laws resulted in a “dramatic exodus of indemnity
insurers from New York’s individual [insurance] market.”); Brief
for Barry Friedman et al. as
Amici Curiae in No.
11–398, p. 17 (“In Kentucky, all but two insurers (one
State-run) abandoned the State.”).
Massachusetts, Congress was told, cracked the
adverse selection problem. By requiring most residents to obtain
insurance, see Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 111M, §2 (West 2011), the
Commonwealth ensured that insurers would not be left with only the
sick as customers. As a result, federal lawmakers observed,
Massachusetts succeeded where other States had failed. See Brief
for Commonwealth of Massachusetts as
Amicus Curiae in No.
11–398, p. 3 (noting that the Commonwealth’s reforms reduced
the number of uninsured residents to less than 2%, the lowest rate
in the Nation, and cut the amount of uncompensated care by a
third); 42 U. S. C. §18091(2)(D) (2006 ed., Supp. IV)
(noting the success of Massachusetts’ reforms).[
2] In coupling the minimum coverage provision with
guaranteed-issue and community-rating prescriptions, Congress
followed Massachusetts’ lead.
* * *
In sum, Congress passed the minimum coverage
provision as a key component of the ACA to address an economic and
social problem that has plagued the Nation for decades: the large
number of U. S. residents who are unable or unwilling to
obtain health insurance. Whatever one thinks of the policy decision
Congress made, it was Congress’ prerogative to make it. Reviewed
with appropriate deference, the minimum coverage provision, allied
to the guaranteed-issue and community-rating prescriptions, should
survive measurement under the Commerce and Necessary and Proper
Clauses.
II
A
The Commerce Clause, it is widely
acknowledged, “was the Framers’ response to the central problem
that gave rise to the Constitution itself.”
EEOC v.
Wyoming,
460 U.S.
226, 244, 245, n. 1 (1983) (Stevens, J., concurring)
(citing sources). Under the Articles of Confederation, the
Constitution’s precursor, the regulation of commerce was left to
the States. This scheme proved unworkable, because the individual
States, understandably focused on their own economic interests,
often failed to take actions critical to the success of the Nation
as a whole. See Vices of the Political System of the United States,
in James Madison: Writings 69, 71, ¶5 (J. Rakove ed. 1999) (As a
result of the “want of concert in matters where common interest
requires it,” the “national dignity, interest, and reve- nue [have]
suffered.”).[
3]
What was needed was a “national Government
. . . armed with a positive & compleat authority in
all cases where uniform measures are necessary.” See Letter from
James Madison to Edmund Randolph (Apr. 8, 1787), in 9 Papers of
James Madison 368, 370 (R. Rutland ed. 1975). See also Letter from
George Washington to James Madison (Nov. 30, 1785), in 8
id., at 428, 429 (“We are either a United people, or we are
not. If the former, let us, in all matters of general concern act
as a nation, which ha[s] national objects to promote, and a
national character to support.”). The Framers’ solution was the
Commerce Clause, which, as they perceived it, granted Congress the
authority to enact economic legislation “in all Cases for the
general Interests of the Union, and also in those Cases to which
the States are separately incompetent.” 2 Records of the Federal
Convention of 1787, pp. 131–132, ¶8 (M. Farrand rev. 1966). See
also
North American Co. v.
SEC,
327 U.S.
686, 705 (1946) (“[The commerce power] is an affirmative power
commensurate with the national needs.”).
The Framers understood that the “general
Interests of the Union” would change over time, in ways they could
not anticipate. Accordingly, they recognized that the Constitution
was of necessity a “great outlin[e],” not a detailed blueprint, see
McCulloch v.
Maryland, 4 Wheat. 316, 407 (1819), and
that its provisions included broad concepts, to be “explained by
the context or by the facts of the case,” Letter from James Madison
to N. P. Trist (Dec. 1831), in 9 Writings of James Madison 471, 475
(G. Hunt ed. 1910). “Nothing . . . can be more
fallacious,” Alexander Hamilton emphasized, “than to infer the
extent of any power, proper to be lodged in the national
government, from . . . its immediate necessities. There
ought to be a capacity to provide for future contingencies[,] as
they may happen; and as these are illimitable in their nature, it
is impossible safely to limit that capacity.” The Federalist No.
34, pp. 205, 206 (John Harvard Library ed. 2009). See also
McCulloch, 4 Wheat., at 415 (The Necessary and Proper Clause
is lodged “in a constitution[,] intended to endure for ages to
come, and consequently, to be adapted to the various
crises
of human affairs.”).
B
Consistent with the Framers’ intent, we have
repeatedly emphasized that Congress’ authority under the Commerce
Clause is dependent upon “practical” considerations, including
“actual experience.”
Jones & Laughlin Steel Corp., 301
U. S., at 41–42; see
Wickard v.
Filburn,
317 U.S.
111, 122 (1942);
United States v.
Lopez,
514 U.S.
549, 573 (1995) (Kennedy, J., concurring) (emphasizing “the
Court’s definitive commitment to the practical conception of the
commerce power”). See also
North American Co., 327
U. S., at 705 (“Commerce itself is an intensely practical
matter. To deal with it effectively, Congress must be able to act
in terms of economic and financial realities.” (citation omitted)).
We afford Congress the leeway “to undertake to solve national
problems directly and realistically.”
American Power & Light
Co. v.
SEC,
329 U.S.
90, 103 (1946).
Until today, this Court’s pragmatic approach to
judging whether Congress validly exercised its commerce power was
guided by two familiar principles. First, Congress has the power to
regulate economic activities “that substantially affect interstate
commerce.”
Gonzales v.
Raich,
545 U.S.
1, 17 (2005). This capacious power extends even to local
activities that, viewed in the aggregate, have a substantial impact
on interstate commerce. See
ibid. See also
Wickard,
317 U. S., at 125 (“[E]ven if appellee’s activ- ity be local
and though it may not be regarded as commerce, it may still,
whatever its nature, be reached by Congress if it exerts a
substantial economic effect on interstate commerce.” (emphasis
added));
Jones & Laughlin Steel Corp., 301 U. S.,
at 37.
Second, we owe a large measure of respect to
Congress when it frames and enacts economic and social legislation.
See
Raich, 545 U. S., at 17. See also
Pension
Benefit Guaranty Corporation v.
R. A. Gray &
Co.,
467 U.S.
717, 729 (1984) (“[S]trong deference [is] accorded legislation
in the field of national economic policy.”);
Hodel v.
Indiana,
452 U.S.
314, 326 (1981) (“This [C]ourt will certainly not substitute
its judgment for that of Congress unless the relation of the
subject to interstate commerce and its ef- fect upon it are clearly
non-existent.” (internal quotation marks omitted)). When appraising
such legislation, we ask only (1) whether Congress had a “rational
basis” for concluding that the regulated activity substantially
affects interstate commerce, and (2) whether there is a “reasonable
connection between the regulatory means selected and the asserted
ends.”
Id., at 323–324. See also
Raich, 545
U. S., at 22;
Lopez, 514 U. S., at 557;
Hodel v.
Virginia Surface Mining & Reclamation Assn.,
Inc.,
452 U.S.
264, 277 (1981);
Katzenbach v.
McClung,
379 U.S.
294, 303 (1964);
Heart of Atlanta Motel, Inc. v.
United States,
379 U.S.
241, 258 (1964);
United States v.
Carolene Products
Co.,
304 U.S.
144, 152–153 (1938). In answering these questions, we presume
the statute under review is constitutional and may strike it down
only on a “plain showing” that Congress acted irrationally.
United States v.
Morrison,
529
U.S. 598, 607 (2000).
C
Straightforward application of these
principles would require the Court to hold that the minimum
coverage provision is proper Commerce Clause legislation. Beyond
dispute, Congress had a rational basis for concluding that the
uninsured, as a class, substantially affect interstate commerce.
Those without insurance consume billions of dollars of health-care
products and services each year. See
supra, at 5. Those
goods are produced, sold, and delivered largely by national and
regional companies who routinely transact business across state
lines. The uninsured also cross state lines to receive care. Some
have medical emergencies while away from home. Others, when sick,
go to a neighboring State that provides better care for those who
have not prepaid for care. See
supra, at 7–8.
Not only do those without insurance consume a
large amount of health care each year; critically, as earlier
explained, their inability to pay for a significant portion of that
consumption drives up market prices, foists costs on other
consumers, and reduces market efficiency and stability. See
supra, at 5–7. Given these far-reaching effects on
interstate commerce, the decision to forgo insurance is hardly
inconsequential or equivalent to “doing nothing,”
ante, at
20; it is, instead, an economic decision Congress has the authority
to address under the Commerce Clause. See
supra, at 14–16.
See also
Wickard, 317 U. S., at 128 (“It is well
established by decisions of this Court that the power to regulate
commerce includes the power to regulate the prices at which
commodities in that commerce are dealt in and
practices
affecting such prices.” (emphasis added)).
The minimum coverage provision, furthermore,
bears a “reasonable connection” to Congress’ goal of protecting the
health-care market from the disruption caused by individuals who
fail to obtain insurance. By requiring those who do not carry
insurance to pay a toll, the minimum coverage provision gives
individuals a strong incentive to insure. This incentive, Congress
had good reason to believe, would reduce the number of uninsured
and, correspondingly, mitigate the adverse impact the uninsured
have on the national health-care market.
Congress also acted reasonably in requiring
uninsured individuals, whether sick or healthy, either to obtain
insurance or to pay the specified penalty. As earlier observed,
because every person is at risk of needing care at any moment, all
those who lack insurance, regardless of their current health
status, adversely affect the price of health care and health
insurance. See
supra, at 6–7. Moreover, an
insurance-purchase requirement limited to those in need of
immediate care simply could not work. Insurance companies would
either charge these individuals prohibitively expensive premiums,
or, if community-rating regulations were in place, close up shop.
See
supra, at 9–11. See also Brief for State of Maryland and
10 Other States et al. as
Amici Curiae in No. 11–398,
p. 28 (hereinafter Maryland Brief) (“No insurance regime can
survive if people can opt out when the risk insured against is only
a risk, but opt in when the risk materializes.”).
“[W]here we find that the legislators
. . . have a rational basis for finding a chosen
regulatory scheme necessary to the protection of commerce, our
investigation is at an end.”
Katzenbach, 379 U. S., at
303–304. Congress’ enactment of the minimum coverage provision,
which addresses a specific interstate problem in a practical,
experience-informed manner, easily meets this criterion.
D
Rather than evaluating the constitutionality
of the minimum coverage provision in the manner established by our
precedents, The Chief Justice relies on a newly minted
constitutional doctrine. The commerce power does not, The Chief
Justice announces, permit Congress to “compe[l] individuals to
become active in commerce by purchasing a product.”
Ante, at
20 (emphasis deleted).
1
a
The Chief Justice’s novel constraint on
Congress’ commerce power gains no force from our precedent and for
that reason alone warrants disapprobation. See
infra, at
23–27. But even assuming, for the moment, that Congress lacks
authority under the Commerce Clause to “compel individuals not
engaged in commerce to purchase an unwanted product,”
ante,
at 18, such a limitation would be inapplicable here. Everyone will,
at some point, consume health-care products and services. See
supra, at 3. Thus, if The Chief Justice is correct that an
insurance-purchase requirement can be applied only to those who
“actively” consume health care, the minimum coverage provision fits
the bill.
The Chief Justice does not dispute that all
U. S. residents participate in the market for health services
over the course of their lives. See
ante, at 16 (“Everyone
will eventually need health care at a time and to an extent they
cannot predict.”). But, The Chief Justice insists, the uninsured
cannot be considered active in the market for health care, because
“[t]he proximity and degree of connection between the [uninsured
today] and [their] subsequent commercial activity is too lacking.”
Ante, at 27.
This argument has multiple flaws. First, more
than 60% of those without insurance visit a hospital or doctor’s
office each year. See
supra, at 5. Nearly 90% will within
five years.[
4] An uninsured’s
consumption of health care is thus quite proximate: It is virtually
certain to occur in the next five years and more likely than not to
occur this year.
Equally evident, Congress has no way of
separating those uninsured individuals who will need emergency
medi- cal care today (surely their consumption of medical care is
sufficiently imminent) from those who will not need medical
services for years to come. No one knows when an emergency will
occur, yet emergencies involving the uninsured arise daily. To
capture individuals who unexpect- edly will obtain medical care in
the very near future, then, Congress needed to include individuals
who will not go to a doctor anytime soon. Congress, our decisions
instruct, has authority to cast its net that wide. See
Perez
v.
United States,
402 U.S.
146, 154 (1971) (“[W]hen it is necessary in order to prevent an
evil to make the law embrace more than the precise thing to be
prevented it may do so.” (internal quotation marks
omitted)).[
5]
Second, it is Congress’ role, not the Court’s,
to delineate the boundaries of the market the Legislature seeks to
regulate. The Chief Justice defines the health-care mar- ket as
including only those transactions that will occur either in the
next instant or within some (unspecified) proximity to the next
instant. But Congress could reasonably have viewed the market from
a long-term perspective, encompassing all transactions virtually
certain to occur over the next decade, see
supra, at 19, not
just those occurring here and now.
Third, contrary to The Chief Justice’s
contention, our precedent does indeed support “[t]he proposition
that Congress may dictate the conduct of an individual today
because of prophesied future activity.”
Ante, at 26. In
Wickard, the Court upheld a penalty the Federal Government
imposed on a farmer who grew more wheat than he was permitted to
grow under the Agricultural Adjustment Act of 1938 (AAA). 317
U. S., at 114–115. He could not be penalized, the farmer
argued, as he was growing the wheat for home consumption, not for
sale on the open market.
Id., at 119. The Court rejected
this argument.
Id., at 127–129. Wheat intended for home
consumption, the Court noted, “overhangs the market, and if induced
by rising prices, tends to flow into the market and check price
increases [intended by the AAA].”
Id., at 128.
Similar reasoning supported the Court’s judgment
in
Raich, which upheld Congress’ authority to regulate
marijuana grown for personal use. 545 U. S., at 19. Homegrown
marijuana substantially affects the interstate mar- ket for
marijuana, we observed, for “the high demand in the interstate
market will [likely] draw such marijuana into that market.”
Ibid.
Our decisions thus acknowledge Congress’
authority, under the Commerce Clause, to direct the conduct of an
individual today (the farmer in
Wickard, stopped from
growing excess wheat; the plaintiff in
Raich, ordered to
cease cultivating marijuana) because of a prophesied future
transaction (the eventual sale of that wheat or marijuana in the
interstate market). Congress’ actions are even more rational in
this case, where the future activity (the consumption of medical
care) is certain to occur, the sole uncertainty being the time the
activity will take place.
Maintaining that the uninsured are not active in
the health-care market, The Chief Justice draws an analogy to the
car market. An individual “is not ‘active in the car
market,’ ” The Chief Justice observes, simply because he or
she may someday buy a car.
Ante, at 25. The analogy is
inapt. The inevitable yet unpredictable need for medical care and
the guarantee that emergency care will be provided when required
are conditions nonexistent in other markets. That is so of the
market for cars, and of the market for broccoli as well. Although
an individual
might buy a car or a crown of broccoli one
day, there is no certainty she will ever do so. And if she
eventually wants a car or has a craving for broccoli, she will be
obliged to pay at the counter before receiving the vehicle or
nourishment. She will get no free ride or food, at the expense of
another consumer forced to pay an inflated price. See
Thomas
More Law Center v.
Obama, 651 F.3d 529, 565 (CA6 2011)
(Sutton, J., concurring in part) (“Regulating how citizens pay for
what they already receive (health care), never quite know when they
will need, and in the case of severe illnesses or emergencies
generally will not be able to afford, has few (if any) parallels in
modern life.”). Upholding the minimum coverage provision on the
ground that all are participants or will be participants in the
health-care market would therefore carry no implication that
Congress may justify under the Commerce Clause a mandate to buy
other products and services.
Nor is it accurate to say that the minimum
coverage provision “compel[s] individuals . . . to
purchase an unwanted product,”
ante, at 18, or “suite of
products,”
post, at 11, n. 2 (joint opinion of Scalia,
Kennedy, Thomas, and Alito, JJ.). If unwanted today, medical
service secured by insurance may be desperately needed tomorrow.
Virtually everyone, I reiterate, consumes health care at some point
in his or her life. See
supra, at 3. Health insurance is a
means of paying for this care, nothing more. In requiring
individuals to obtain insurance, Congress is therefore not
mandating the purchase of a discrete, unwanted product. Rather,
Congress is merely defining the terms on which individuals pay for
an interstate good they consume: Persons subject to the mandate
must now pay for medical care in advance (instead of at the point
of service) and through insurance (instead of out of pocket).
Establishing payment terms for goods in or affecting interstate
commerce is quintessential economic regulation well within
Congress’ domain. See,
e.g., United States v.
Wrightwood Dairy Co.,
315 U.S.
110, 118 (1942). Cf.
post, at 13 (joint opinion of
Scalia, Kennedy, Thomas, and Alito, JJ.) (recognizing that “the
Federal Government can prescribe [a commodity’s] quality
. . . and even [its price]”).
The Chief Justice also calls the minimum
coverage provision an illegitimate effort to make young, healthy
individuals subsidize insurance premiums paid by the less hale and
hardy. See
ante, at 17, 25–26. This complaint, too, is
spurious. Under the current health-care system, healthy persons who
lack insurance receive a benefit for which they do not pay: They
are assured that, if they need it, emergency medical care will be
available, although they cannot afford it. See
supra, at
5–6. Those who have insurance bear the cost of this guarantee. See
ibid. By requiring the healthy uninsured to obtain insurance
or pay a penalty structured as a tax, the minimum coverage
provision ends the free ride these individuals currently enjoy.
In the fullness of time, moreover, today’s young
and healthy will become society’s old and infirm. Viewed over a
lifespan, the costs and benefits even out: The young who pay more
than their fair share currently will pay less than their fair share
when they become senior citizens. And even if, as undoubtedly will
be the case, some individuals, over their lifespans, will pay more
for health insurance than they receive in health services, they
have little to complain about, for that is how insurance works.
Every insured person receives protection against a catastrophic
loss, even though only a subset of the covered class will
ultimately need that protection.
b
In any event, The Chief Justice’s limitation
of the commerce power to the regulation of those actively engaged
in commerce finds no home in the text of the Constitution or our
decisions. Article I, §8, of the Constitution grants Congress the
power “[t]o regulate Commerce . . . among the several
States.” Nothing in this language im- plies that Congress’ commerce
power is limited to regu- lating those actively engaged in
commercial transactions. Indeed, as the D. C. Circuit
observed, “[a]t the time the Constitution was [framed], to
‘regulate’ meant,” among other things, “to require action.” See
Seven-Sky v.
Holder, 661 F.3d 1, 16 (2011).
Arguing to the contrary, The Chief Justice notes
that “the Constitution gives Congress the power to ‘coin Money,’ in
addition to the power to ‘regulate the Value thereof,’ ” and
similarly “gives Congress the power to ‘raise and support Armies’
and to ‘provide and maintain a Navy,’ in addition to the power to
‘make Rules for the Government and Regulation of the land and naval
Forces.’ ”
Ante, at 18–19 (citing Art. I, §8, cls.
5, 12–14). In separating the power to regulate from the power to
bring the subject of the regulation into existence, The Chief
Justice asserts, “[t]he language of the Constitution reflects the
natural understanding that the power to regulate assumes there is
already something to be regulated.”
Ante, at 19.
This argument is difficult to fathom. Requiring
individuals to obtain insurance unquestionably regulates the inter-
state health-insurance and health-care markets, both of them in
existence well before the enactment of the ACA. See
Wickard,
317 U. S., at 128 (“The stimulation of commerce is a use of
the regulatory function quite as definitely as prohibitions or
restrictions thereon.”). Thus, the “something to be regulated” was
surely there when Congress created the minimum coverage
provision.[
6]
Nor does our case law toe the activity versus
inactiv- ity line. In
Wickard, for example, we upheld the
penalty imposed on a farmer who grew too much wheat, even though
the regulation had the effect of compelling farmers to purchase
wheat in the open market.
Id., at 127–129. “[F]orcing some
farmers into the market to buy what they could provide for
themselves” was, the Court held, a valid means of regulating
commerce.
Id., at 128–129. In an- other context, this Court
similarly upheld Congress’ authority under the commerce power to
compel an “inactive” land- holder to submit to an unwanted sale.
See
Monongahela Nav. Co. v.
United States,
148 U.S.
312, 335–337 (1893) (“[U]pon
the [great] power to regulate
commerce[,]” Congress has the authority to mandate the sale of
real prop- erty to the Government, where the sale is essential to
the improvement of a navigable waterway (emphasis added));
Cherokee Nation v.
Southern Kansas R. Co.,
135 U.S.
641, 657–659 (1890) (similar reliance on the commerce power
regarding mandated sale of private property for railroad
construction).
In concluding that the Commerce Clause does not
permit Congress to regulate commercial “inactivity,” and there-
fore does not allow Congress to adopt the practical solution it
devised for the health-care problem, The Chief Justice views the
Clause as a “technical legal conception,” precisely what our case
law tells us not to do.
Wickard, 317 U. S., at 122
(internal quotation marks omitted). See also
supra, at
14–16. This Court’s former endeavors to impose categorical limits
on the commerce power have not fared well. In several pre-New Deal
cases, the Court attempted to cabin Congress’ Commerce Clause
authority by distinguishing “commerce” from activity once conceived
to be noncommercial, notably, “production,” “mining,” and
“manufacturing.” See,
e.g., United States v.
E. C. Knight
Co.,
156 U.S.
1, 12 (1895) (“Commerce succeeds to manufacture, and is not a
part of it.”);
Carter v.
Carter Coal Co.,
298 U.S.
238, 304 (1936) (“Mining brings the subject matter of commerce
into existence. Commerce disposes of it.”). The Court also sought
to distinguish activities having a “direct” effect on interstate
commerce, and for that reason, subject to federal regulation, from
those having only an “indirect” effect, and therefore not amenable
to federal control. See,
e.g., A. L. A. Schechter Poultry
Corp. v.
United States,
295 U.S.
495, 548 (1935) (“[T]he dis- tinction between direct and
indirect effects of intrastate transactions upon interstate
commerce must be recognized as a fundamental one.”).
These line-drawing exercises were untenable, and
the Court long ago abandoned them. “[Q]uestions of the power of
Congress [under the Commerce Clause],” we held in
Wickard,
“are not to be decided by reference to any for- mula which would
give controlling force to nomenclature such as ‘production’ and
‘indirect’ and foreclose consideration of the actual effects of the
activity in question upon interstate commerce.” 317 U. S., at
120. See also
Morrison, 529 U. S., at 641–644 (Souter,
J., dissenting) (recounting the Court’s “nearly disastrous
experiment” with formalistic limits on Congress’ commerce power).
Failing to learn from this history, The Chief Justice plows ahead
with his formalistic distinction between those who are “active in
commerce,”
ante, at 20, and those who are not.
It is not hard to show the difficulty courts
(and Congress) would encounter in distinguishing statutes that reg-
ulate “activity” from those that regulate “inactivity.” As Judge
Easterbrook noted, “it is possible to restate most actions as
corresponding inactions with the same effect.”
Archie v.
Racine, 847 F.2d 1211, 1213 (CA7 1988) (en banc). Take this
case as an example. An individual who opts not to purchase
insurance from a private insurer can be seen as actively selecting
another form of insurance: self-insurance. See
Thomas More Law
Center, 651 F. 3d, at 561 (Sutton, J., concurring in part)
(“No one is in- active when deciding how to pay for health care, as
self-insurance and private insurance are two forms of action for
addressing the same risk.”). The minimum coverage provision could
therefore be described as regulating activists in the
self-insurance market.[
7]
Wickard is another example. Did the statute there at issue
target activity (the growing of too much wheat) or inactivity (the
farmer’s failure to purchase wheat in the marketplace)? If
anything, the Court’s analysis suggested the latter. See 317
U. S., at 127–129.
At bottom, The Chief Justice’s and the joint
dissenters’ “view that an individual cannot be subject to Commerce
Clause regulation absent voluntary, affirmative acts that enter him
or her into, or affect, the interstate mar- ket expresses a concern
for individual liberty that [is] more redolent of Due Process
Clause arguments.”
Seven-Sky, 661 F. 3d, at 19. See
also
Troxel v.
Granville,
530 U.S.
57, 65 (2000) (plurality opinion) (“The [Due Process] Clause
also includes a substantive component that provides heightened
protection against government interference with certain fundamental
rights and liberty interests.” (internal quotation marks omitted)).
Plaintiffs have abandoned any argument pinned to substantive due
process, however, see 648 F.3d 1235, 1291, n. 93 (CA11 2011), and
now concede that the provisions here at issue do not offend the Due
Process Clause.[
8]
2
Underlying The Chief Justice’s view that the
Commerce Clause must be confined to the regulation of active
participants in a commercial market is a fear that the commerce
power would otherwise know no limits. See,
e.g., ante, at 23
(Allowing Congress to compel an individ- ual not engaged in
commerce to purchase a product would “permi[t] Congress to reach
beyond the natural extent of its authority, everywhere extending
the sphere of its activity, and drawing all power into its
impetuous vortex.” (internal quotation marks omitted)). The joint
dissenters express a similar apprehension. See
post, at 8
(If the minimum coverage provision is upheld under the commerce
power then “the Commerce Clause becomes a font of unlimited power,
. . . the hideous monster whose devouring jaws
. . . spare neither sex nor age, nor high nor low, nor
sacred nor profane.” (internal quotation marks omitted)). This
concern is unfounded.
First, The Chief Justice could certainly uphold
the individual mandate without giving Congress
carte blanche
to enact any and all purchase mandates. As several times noted, the
unique attributes of the health-care market render everyone active
in that market and give rise to a significant free-riding problem
that does not occur in other markets. See
supra, at 3–7,
16–18, 21.
Nor would the commerce power be unbridled,
absent The Chief Justice’s “activity” limitation. Congress would
remain unable to regulate noneconomic conduct that has only an
attenuated effect on interstate commerce and is traditionally left
to state law. See
Lopez, 514 U. S., at 567;
Morrison, 529 U. S., at 617–619. In
Lopez, for
example, the Court held that the Federal Government lacked power,
under the Commerce Clause, to criminalize the possession of a gun
in a local school zone. Possessing a gun near a school, the Court
reasoned, “is in no sense an economic activity that might, through
repetition elsewhere, substantially affect any sort of interstate
commerce.” 514 U. S., at 567;
ibid. (noting that the
Court would have “to pile inference upon inference” to conclude
that gun possession has a substantial effect on commerce). Relying
on similar logic, the Court concluded in
Morrison that
Congress could not regulate gender-motivated violence, which the
Court deemed to have too “attenuated [an] effect upon interstate
commerce.” 529 U. S., at 615.
An individual’s decision to self-insure, I have
explained, is an economic act with the requisite connection to
interstate commerce. See
supra, at 16–17. Other choices
individuals make are unlikely to fit the same or similar
description. As an example of the type of regulation he fears, The
Chief Justice cites a Government mandate to purchase green
vegetables.
Ante, at 22–23. One could call this concern “the
broccoli horrible.” Congress, The Chief Justice posits, might adopt
such a mandate, reasoning that an individual’s failure to eat a
healthy diet, like the failure to purchase health insurance,
imposes costs on others. See
ibid.
Consider the chain of inferences the Court would
have to accept to conclude that a vegetable-purchase mandate was
likely to have a substantial effect on the health-care costs borne
by lithe Americans. The Court would have to believe that
individuals forced to buy vegetables would then eat them (instead
of throwing or giving them away), would prepare the vegetables in a
healthy way (steamed or raw, not deep-fried), would cut back on
unhealthy foods, and would not allow other factors (such as lack of
exercise or little sleep) to trump the improved diet.[
9] Such “pil[ing of] inference upon
inference” is just what the Court refused to do in
Lopez and
Morrison.
Other provisions of the Constitution also check
congressional overreaching. A mandate to purchase a particu- lar
product would be unconstitutional if, for example, the edict
impermissibly abridged the freedom of speech, interfered with the
free exercise of religion, or infringed on a liberty interest
protected by the Due Process Clause.
Supplementing these legal restraints is a
formidable check on congressional power: the democratic process.
See
Raich, 545 U. S., at 33;
Wickard, 317
U. S., at 120 (repeating Chief Justice Marshall’s “warning
that effective restraints on [the commerce power’s] exercise must
proceed from political rather than judicial processes” (citing
Gibbons v.
Ogden, 9 Wheat. 1, 197 (1824)). As the
controversy surrounding the passage of the Affordable Care Act
attests, purchase mandates are likely to engender political
resistance. This prospect is borne out by the behavior of state
legislators. Despite their possession of unquestioned authority to
impose mandates, state governments have rarely done so. See Hall,
Commerce Clause Challenges to Health Care Reform, 159 U. Pa.
L. Rev. 1825, 1838 (2011).
When contemplated in its extreme, almost any
power looks dangerous. The commerce power, hypothetically, would
enable Congress to prohibit the purchase and home production of all
meat, fish, and dairy goods, effectively compelling Americans to
eat only vegetables. Cf.
Raich, 545 U. S., at 9;
Wickard, 317 U. S., at 127–129. Yet no one would offer
the “hypothetical and unreal possibilit[y],”
Pullman Co. v.
Knott,
235 U.S.
23, 26 (1914), of a vegetarian state as a credible reason to
deny Congress the authority ever to ban the possession and sale of
goods. The Chief Justice accepts just such specious logic when he
cites the broccoli horrible as a reason to deny Congress the power
to pass the individual mandate. Cf. R. Bork, The Tempting of
America 169 (1990) (“Judges and lawyers live on the slippery slope
of analogies; they are not supposed to ski it to the bottom.”). But
see,
e.g., post, at 3 (joint opinion of Scalia, Kennedy,
Thomas, and Alito, JJ.) (asserting, outlandishly, that if the
minimum coverage provision is sustained, then Congress could make
“breathing in and out the basis for federal prescription”).
3
To bolster his argument that the minimum
coverage provision is not valid Commerce Clause legislation, The
Chief Justice emphasizes the provision’s novelty. See
ante,
at 18 (asserting that “sometimes the most telling indication of [a]
severe constitutional problem . . . is the lack of
historical precedent for Congress’s action” (internal quotation
marks omitted)). While an insurance-purchase mandate may be novel,
The Chief Justice’s argument certainly is not. “[I]n almost every
instance of the exer- cise of the [commerce] power differences are
asserted from previous exercises of it and made a ground of
attack.”
Hoke v.
United States,
227 U.S.
308, 320 (1913). See,
e.g., Brief for Petitioner in
Perez v.
United States, O. T. 1970, No. 600,
p. 5 (“unprecedented exercise of power”); Sup- plemental Brief
for Appellees in
Katzenbach v.
McClung, O. T.
1964, No. 543, p. 40 (“novel assertion of federal power”);
Brief for Appellee in
Wickard v.
Filburn, O. T.
1941, No. 59, p. 6 (“complete departure”). For decades, the
Court has declined to override legislation because of its novelty,
and for good reason. As our national economy grows and changes, we
have recognized, Congress must adapt to the changing “economic and
financial realities.” See
supra, at 14–15. Hindering
Congress’ ability to do so is shortsighted; if history is any
guide, today’s constriction of the Commerce Clause will not endure.
See
supra, at 25–26.
III
A
For the reasons explained above, the minimum
coverage provision is valid Commerce Clause legislation. See
supra, Part II. When viewed as a component of the entire
ACA, the provision’s constitutionality becomes even plainer.
The Necessary and Proper Clause “empowers
Congress to enact laws in effectuation of its [commerce] powe[r]
that are not within its authority to enact in isolation.”
Raich, 545 U. S., at 39 (Scalia, J., concurring in
judgment). Hence, “[a] complex regulatory program . . .
can survive a Commerce Clause challenge without a showing that
every single facet of the program is independently and directly
related to a valid congressional goal.”
Indiana, 452
U. S., at 329, n. 17. “It is enough that the challenged
provisions are an integral part of the regulatory program and that
the regulatory scheme when considered as a whole satisfies this
test.”
Ibid. (collecting cases). See also
Raich, 545
U. S., at 24–25 (A challenged statutory provision fits within
Congress’ commerce authority if it is an “essential par[t] of a
larger regulation of economic activity,” such that, in the absence
of the provision, “the regulatory scheme could be undercut.”
(quoting
Lopez, 514 U. S., at 561));
Raich, 545
U. S., at 37 (Scalia, J., concurring in judgment) (“Congress
may regulate even noneconomic local activity if that regulation is
a necessary part of a more general regulation of interstate
commerce. The relevant question is simply whether the means chosen
are ‘reasonably adapted’ to the attainment of a legitimate end
under the commerce power.” (citation omitted)).
Recall that one of Congress’ goals in enacting
the Affordable Care Act was to eliminate the insurance industry’s
practice of charging higher prices or denying coverage to
individuals with preexisting medical conditions. See
supra,
at 9–10. The commerce power allows Congress to ban this practice, a
point no one disputes. See
United States v.
South-Eastern
Underwriters Assn.,
322 U.S.
533, 545, 552–553 (1944) (Congress may regulate “the methods by
which interstate insurance companies do business.”).
Congress knew, however, that simply barring
insurance companies from relying on an applicant’s medical history
would not work in practice. Without the individual mandate,
Congress learned, guaranteed-issue and community-rating
requirements would trigger an adverse-selection death-spiral in the
health-insurance market: Insurance premiums would skyrocket, the
number of uninsured would increase, and insurance companies would
exit the market. See
supra, at 10–11
. When
complemented by an insurance mandate, on the other hand, guaranteed
issue and community rating would work as intended, increasing
access to insurance and reducing uncompensated care. See
supra, at 11–12. The minimum coverage provision is thus an
“essential par[t] of a larger regulation of economic activity”;
without the provision, “the regulatory scheme [w]ould be undercut.”
Raich, 545 U. S., at 24–25 (inter- nal quotation marks
omitted). Put differently, the minimum coverage provision, together
with the guaranteed-issue and community-rating requirements, is
“ ‘reasonably adapted’ to the attainment of a legitimate end
under the commerce power”: the elimination of pricing and sales
practices that take an applicant’s medical history into account.
See
id., at 37 (Scalia, J., concurring in judgment).
B
Asserting that the Necessary and Proper Clause
does not authorize the minimum coverage provision, The Chief
Justice focuses on the word “proper.” A mandate to purchase health
insurance is not “proper” legislation, The Chief Justice urges,
because the command “undermine[s] the structure of government
established by the Constitution.”
Ante, at 28. If long on
rhetoric, The Chief Justice’s argument is short on substance.
The Chief Justice cites only two cases in which
this Court concluded that a federal statute impermissibly
transgressed the Constitution’s boundary between state and federal
authority:
Printz v.
United States,
521 U.S.
898 (1997), and
New York v.
United States,
505 U.S.
144 (1992). See
ante, at 29. The statutes at issue in
both cases, however, compelled
state officials to act on the
Federal Government’s behalf. 521 U. S., at 925–933 (holding
unconstitutional a statute obligating state law enforcement
officers to implement a federal gun-control law);
New York,
505 U. S., at 176–177 (striking down a statute requiring state
legislators to pass regulations pursuant to Congress’
instructions). “[Federal] laws conscripting state officers,” the
Court reasoned, “violate state sovereignty and are thus not in
accord with the Constitution.”
Printz, 521 U. S., at
925, 935;
New York, 505 U. S., at 176.
The minimum coverage provision, in contrast,
acts “directly upon individuals, without employing the States as
intermediaries.”
New York, 505 U. S., at 164. The
provision is thus entirely consistent with the Consti- tution’s
design. See
Printz, 521 U. S., at 920 (“[T]he Framers
explicitly chose a Constitution that confers upon Congress the
power to regulate individuals, not States.” (internal quotation
marks omitted)).
Lacking case law support for his holding, The
Chief Justice nevertheless declares the minimum coverage provision
not “proper” because it is less “narrow in scope” than other laws
this Court has upheld under the Necessary and Proper Clause.
Ante, at 29 (citing
United States v.
Comstock,
560 U. S. ___ (2010);
Sabri v.
United States,
541 U.S.
600 (2004);
Jinks v.
Richland County,
538 U.S.
456 (2003)). The Chief Justice’s reliance on cases in which
this Court has
affirmed Congress’ “broad authority to enact
federal legislation” under the Necessary and Proper Clause,
Comstock, 560 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 5), is
underwhelming.
Nor does The Chief Justice pause to explain
why the power to direct either the purchase of health
insurance or, alternatively, the payment of a penalty collectible
as a tax is more far-reaching than other implied powers this Court
has found meet under the Necessary and Proper Clause. These powers
include the power to enact criminal laws, see,
e.g., United
States v.
Fox,
95 U.S.
670, 672 (1878); the power to imprison, including civil
imprisonment, see,
e.g., Comstock, 560 U. S., at ___
(slip op., at 1); and the power to create a national bank, see
McCulloch, 4 Wheat., at 425. See also
Jinks, 538
U. S., at 463 (affirming Congress’ power to alter the way a
state law is applied in state court, where the alteration “promotes
fair and efficient operation of the federal courts”).[
10]
In failing to explain why the individual mandate
threatens our constitutional order, The Chief Justice disserves
future courts. How is a judge to decide, when ruling on the
constitutionality of a federal statute, whether Congress employed
an “independent power,”
ante, at 28, or merely a
“derivative” one,
ante, at 29. Whether the power used is
“substantive,”
ante, at 30, or just “incidental,”
ante, at 29? The instruction The Chief Justice, in effect,
provides lower courts: You will know it when you see it.
It is more than exaggeration to suggest that the
minimum coverage provision improperly intrudes on “essential
attributes of state sovereignty.”
Ibid. (internal quotation
marks omitted). First, the Affordable Care Act does not operate “in
[an] are[a] such as criminal law enforcement or education where
States historically have been sovereign.”
Lopez, 514
U. S., at 564. As evidenced by Medicare, Medicaid, the
Employee Retirement Income Security Act of 1974 (ERISA), and the
Health Insurance Portability and Accountability Act of 1996
(HIPAA), the Federal Government plays a lead role in the
health-care sector, both as a direct payer and as a regulator.
Second, and perhaps most important, the minimum
coverage provision, along with other provisions of the ACA,
addresses the very sort of interstate problem that made the
commerce power essential in our federal system. See
supra,
at 12–14. The crisis created by the large number of U. S.
residents who lack health insurance is one of national dimension
that States are “separately incompetent” to handle. See
supra, at 7–8, 13. See also Maryland Brief 15–26 (describing
“the impediments to effective state policymaking that flow from the
interconnectedness of each state’s healthcare economy” and
emphasizing that “state-level reforms cannot fully address the
problems associated with uncompensated care”). Far from trampling
on States’ sovereignty, the ACA attempts a federal solution for the
very reason that the States, acting separately, cannot meet the
need. Notably, the ACA serves the general welfare of the people of
the United States while retaining a prominent role for the States.
See
id., at 31–36 (explaining and illustrating how the ACA
affords States wide latitude in implementing key elements of the
Act’s reforms).[
11]
IV
In the early 20th century, this Court
regularly struck down economic regulation enacted by the peoples’
representatives in both the States and the Federal Government. See,
e.g., Carter Coal Co., 298 U. S., at 303–304, 309–310;
Dagenhart, 247 U. S., at 276–277;
Lochner v.
New York,
198 U.S.
45, 64 (1905). The Chief Justice’s Commerce Clause opinion, and
even more so the joint dissenters’ reasoning, see
post, at
4–16, bear a disquieting resemblance to those long-overruled
decisions.
Ultimately, the Court upholds the individual
mandate as a proper exercise of Congress’ power to tax and spend
“for the . . . general Welfare of the United States.”
Art. I, §8, cl. 1;
ante, at 43–44. I concur in
that determination, which makes The Chief Justice’s Commerce Clause
essay all the more puzzling. Why should The Chief Justice strive so
mightily to hem in Congress’ capacity to meet the new problems
arising constantly in our ever-developing modern economy? I find no
satisfying response to that question in his opinion.[
12]
V
Through Medicaid, Congress has offered the
States an opportunity to furnish health care to the poor with the
aid of federal financing. To receive federal Medicaid funds, States
must provide health benefits to specified categories of needy
persons, including pregnant women, children, parents, and adults
with disabilities. Guaranteed eligibility varies by category: for
some it is tied to the federal poverty level (incomes up to 100% or
133%); for others it depends on criteria such as eligibility for
designated state or federal assistance programs. The ACA enlarges
the population of needy people States must cover to include adults
under age 65 with incomes up to 133% of the fed- eral poverty
level. The spending power conferred by the Constitution, the Court
has never doubted, permits Congress to define the contours of
programs financed with federal funds. See,
e.g., Pennhurst State
School and Hospital v.
Halderman,
451 U.S.
1, 17 (1981). And to expand coverage, Congress could have
recalled the existing legislation, and replaced it with a new law
making Medicaid as embracive of the poor as Congress chose.
The question posed by the 2010 Medicaid
expansion, then, is essentially this: To cover a notably larger
population, must Congress take the repeal/reenact route, or may it
achieve the same result by amending existing law? The answer should
be that Congress may expand by amendment the classes of needy
persons entitled to Medicaid benefits. A ritualistic requirement
that Congress repeal and reenact spending legislation in order to
enlarge the population served by a federally funded program would
advance no constitutional principle and would scarcely serve the
interests of federalism. To the contrary, such a requirement would
rigidify Congress’ efforts to empower States by partnering with
them in the implementation of federal programs.
Medicaid is a prototypical example of
federal-state cooperation in serving the Nation’s general welfare.
Rather than authorizing a federal agency to administer a uni- form
national health-care system for the poor, Con- gress offered States
the opportunity to tailor Medicaid grants to their particular
needs, so long as they remain within bounds set by federal law. In
shaping Medicaid, Congress did not endeavor to fix permanently the
terms participating states must meet; instead, Congress reserved
the “right to alter, amend, or repeal” any provision of the
Medicaid Act. 42 U. S. C. §1304. States, for their part,
agreed to amend their own Medicaid plans consistent with changes
from time to time made in the federal law. See 42 CFR §430.12(c)(i)
(2011). And from 1965 to the present, States have regularly
conformed to Congress’ alterations of the Medicaid Act.
The Chief Justice acknowledges that Congress may
“condition the receipt of [federal] funds on the States’ complying
with restrictions on the use of those funds,”
ante, at 50,
but nevertheless concludes that the 2010 expansion is unduly
coercive. His conclusion rests on three premises, each of them
essential to his theory. First, the Medicaid expansion is, in The
Chief Justice’s view, a new grant program, not an addition to the
Medicaid program existing before the ACA’s enactment. Congress, The
Chief Justice maintains, has threatened States with the loss of
funds from an old program in an effort to get them to adopt a new
one. Second, the expansion was unforeseeable by the States when
they first signed on to Medicaid. Third, the threatened loss of
funding is so large that the States have no real choice but to
participate in the Medicaid expansion. The Chief Justice
therefore—
for the first time ever—finds an exercise of
Congress’ spending power unconstitutionally coercive.
Medicaid, as amended by the ACA, however, is not
two spending programs; it is a single program with a constant
aim—to enable poor persons to receive basic health care when they
need it. Given past expansions, plus express statutory warning that
Congress may change the requirements participating States must
meet, there can be no tenable claim that the ACA fails for lack of
notice. Moreover, States have no entitlement to receive any
Medicaid funds; they enjoy only the opportunity to accept funds on
Congress’ terms. Future Congresses are not bound by their
predecessors’ dispositions; they have authority to spend federal
revenue as they see fit. The Federal Government, therefore, is not,
as The Chief Justice charges, threatening States with the loss of
“existing” funds from one spending program in order to induce them
to opt into another program. Congress is simply requiring States to
do what States have long been required to do to receive Medicaid
funding: comply with the conditions Congress prescribes for
participation.
A majority of the Court, however, buys the
argument that prospective withholding of funds formerly available
exceeds Congress’ spending power. Given that holding, I entirely
agree with The Chief Justice as to the appropriate remedy. It is to
bar the withholding found impermissible—not, as the joint
dissenters would have it, to scrap the expansion altogether, see
post, at 46–48. The dissenters’ view that the ACA must fall
in its entirety is a radical departure from the Court’s normal
course. When a constitutional infirmity mars a statute, the Court
ordinarily removes the infirmity. It undertakes a salvage
operation; it does not demolish the legislation. See,
e.g.,
Brockett v.
Spokane Arcades, Inc.,
472 U.S.
491, 504 (1985) (Court’s normal course is to declare a statute
invalid “to the extent that it reaches too far, but otherwise [to
leave the statute] intact”). That course is plainly in order where,
as in this case, Congress has expressly instructed courts to leave
untouched every provision not found invalid. See 42
U. S. C. §1303. Because The Chief Justice finds the
withholding—not the granting—of federal funds incom- patible with
the Spending Clause, Congress’ extension of Medicaid remains
available to any State that affirms its willingness to
participate.
A
Expansion has been characteristic of the
Medicaid program. Akin to the ACA in 2010, the Medicaid Act as
passed in 1965 augmented existing federal grant programs jointly
administered with the States.[
13] States were not required to participate in Medicaid.
But if they did, the Federal Government paid at least half the
costs. To qual- ify for these grants, States had to offer a minimum
level of health coverage to beneficiaries of four federally funded,
state-administered welfare programs: Aid to Families with Dependent
Children; Old Age Assistance; Aid to the Blind; and Aid to the
Permanently and Totally Disabled. See Social Security Amendments of
1965, §121(a), 79Stat. 343;
Schweiker v.
Gray
Panthers,
453 U.S.
34, 37 (1981). At their option, States could enroll additional
“medically needy” individuals; these costs, too, were partially
borne by the Federal Government at the same, at least 50%, rate.
Ibid.
Since 1965, Congress has amended the Medicaid
program on more than 50 occasions, sometimes quite sizably. Most
relevant here, between 1988 and 1990, Congress required
participating States to include among their beneficiaries pregnant
women with family incomes up to 133% of the federal poverty level,
children up to age 6 at the same income levels, and children ages 6
to 18 with family incomes up to 100% of the poverty level. See 42
U. S. C. §§1396a(a)(10)(A)(i), 1396a(
l); Medicare
Catastrophic Cov- erage Act of 1988, §302, 102Stat. 750; Omnibus
Budget Reconciliation Act of 1989, §6401, 103Stat. 2258; Om- nibus
Budget Reconciliation Act of 1990, §4601, 104Stat. 1388–166. These
amendments added millions to the Medicaid-eligible population.
Dubay & Kenney, Lessons from the Medicaid Expansions for
Children and Pregnant Women 5 (Apr. 1997).
Between 1966 and 1990, annual federal Medicaid
spending grew from $631.6 million to $42.6 billion; state spending
rose to $31 billion over the same period. See Dept. of Health and
Human Services, National Health Expenditures by Type of Service and
Source of Funds: Calendar Years 1960 to 2010 (table).[
14] And between 1990 and 2010,
federal spending increased to $269.5 billion.
Ibid.
Enlargement of the population and services covered by Medicaid, in
short, has been the trend.
Compared to past alterations, the ACA is notable
for the extent to which the Federal Government will pick up the
tab. Medicaid’s 2010 expansion is financed largely by federal
outlays. In 2014, federal funds will cover 100% of the costs for
newly eligible beneficiaries; that rate will gradually decrease
before settling at 90% in 2020. 42 U. S. C. §1396d(y)
(2006 ed., Supp. IV). By comparison, federal contributions toward
the care of beneficiaries eligible pre-ACA range from 50% to 83%,
and averaged 57% between 2005 and 2008. §1396d(b) (2006 ed., Supp.
IV); Dept. of Health and Human Services, Centers for Medicare and
Medicaid Services, C. Truffer et al., 2010 Actuarial Report on
the Financial Outlook for Medicaid, p. 20.
Nor will the expansion exorbitantly increase
state Medicaid spending. The Congressional Budget Office (CBO)
projects that States will spend 0.8% more than they would have,
absent the ACA. See CBO, Spending & Enrollment Detail for CBO’s
March 2009 Baseline. But see
ante, at 44–45 (“[T]he Act
dramatically increases state obligations under Medicaid.”);
post, at 45 (joint opinion of Scalia, Kennedy, Thomas, and
Alito, JJ.) (“[A]cceptance of the [ACA expansion] will impose very
substantial costs on participating States.”). Whatever the increase
in state obligations after the ACA, it will pale in comparison to
the increase in federal funding.[
15]
Finally, any fair appraisal of Medicaid would
require acknowledgment of the considerable autonomy States enjoy
under the Act. Far from “conscript[ing] state agencies into the
national bureaucratic army,”
ante, at 55 (citing
FERC
v.
Mississippi,
456 U.S.
742, 775 (1982) (O’Connor, J., concurring in judgment in part
and dissenting in part) (brackets in original and internal
quotation marks omitted)), Medicaid “is designed to advance
cooperative federalism.”
Wisconsin Dept. of Health and Family
Servs. v.
Blumer,
534 U.S.
473, 495 (2002) (citing
Harris v.
McRae,
448 U.S.
297, 308 (1980)). Subject to its basic requirements, the
Medicaid Act empowers States to “select dramatically different
levels of funding and coverage, alter and experiment with different
financing and delivery modes, and opt to cover (or not to cover) a
range of parti- cular procedures and therapies. States have
leveraged this policy discretion to generate a myriad of
dramatically different Medicaid programs over the past several
decades.” Ruger, Of Icebergs and Glaciers, 75 Law & Contemp.
Probs. 215, 233 (2012) (footnote omitted). The ACA does not
jettison this approach. States, as first-line administrators, will
continue to guide the distribution of substantial resources among
their needy populations.
The alternative to conditional federal spending,
it bears emphasis, is not state autonomy but state
marginalization.[
16] In
1965, Congress elected to nationalize health coverage for seniors
through Medicare. It could similarly have established Medicaid as
an exclusively federal program. Instead, Congress gave the States
the opportunity to partner in the program’s administration and
development. Absent from the nationalized model, of course, is the
state-level policy discretion and experimentation that is
Medicaid’s hallmark; undoubtedly the interests of federalism are
better served when States retain a meaning- ful role in the
implementation of a program of such importance. See Caminker, State
Sovereignty and Sub- ordinacy, 95 Colum. L. Rev. 1001,
1002–1003 (1995) (coopera- tive federalism can preserve “a
significant role for state discretion in achieving specified
federal goals, where the alternative is complete federal preemption
of any state regulatory role”); Rose-Ackerman, Cooperative
Federalism and Co-optation, 92 Yale L. J. 1344, 1346 (1983) (“If
the federal government begins to take full responsibility for
social welfare spending and preempts the states, the result is
likely to be weaker . . . state governments.”).[
17]
Although Congress “has no obligation to use its
Spending Clause power to disburse funds to the States,”
College
Savings Bank v.
Florida Prepaid Postsecondary Ed. Expense
Bd.,
527 U.S.
666, 686 (1999), it has provided Medicaid grants notable for
their generosity and flexibility. “[S]uch funds,” we once observed,
“are gifts,”
id., at 686–687, and so they have remained
through decades of expansion in their size and scope.
B
The Spending Clause authorizes Congress “to
pay the Debts and provide for the . . . general Welfare
of the United States.” Art. I, §8, cl. 1. To ensure that
federal funds granted to the States are spent “to ‘provide for the
. . . general Welfare’ in the manner Congress intended,”
ante, at 46, Congress must of course have authority to
impose limitations on the States’ use of the federal dollars. This
Court, time and again, has respected Congress’ prescription of
spending conditions, and has required States to abide by them. See,
e.g., Pennhurst, 451 U. S., at 17 (“[O]ur cases have long
recognized that Congress may fix the terms on which it shall
disburse federal money to the States.”). In particular, we have
recognized Congress’ prerogative to condition a State’s receipt of
Medicaid funding on compliance with the terms Congress set for
participation in the program. See,
e.g., Harris, 448
U. S., at 301 (“[O]nce a State elects to participate [in
Medicaid], it must comply with the requirements of [the Medicaid
Act].”);
Arkansas Dept. of Health and Human Servs. v.
Ahlborn,
547 U.S.
268, 275 (2006);
Frew v.
Hawkins, 540 U.S. 431,
433 (2004);
Atkins v.
Rivera,
477
U.S. 154, 156–157 (1986).
Congress’ authority to condition the use of
federal funds is not confined to spending programs as first
launched. The legislature may, and often does, amend the law,
imposing new conditions grant recipients henceforth must meet in
order to continue receiving funds. See
infra, at 54
(describing
Bennett v.
Kentucky Dept. of Ed.,
470
U.S. 656, 659–660 (1985) (enforcing restriction added five
years after adoption of educational program)).
Yes, there are federalism-based limits on the
use of Congress’ conditional spending power. In the leading
decision in this area,
South Dakota v.
Dole,
483 U.S.
203 (1987), the Court identified four criteria. The conditions
placed on federal grants to States must (a) promote the “general
welfare,” (b) “unambiguously” inform States what is demanded of
them, (c) be germane “to the federal interest in particular
national projects or programs,” and (d) not “induce the States to
engage in activities that would themselves be unconstitutional.”
Id., at 207–208, 210 (internal quotation marks
omitted).[
18]
The Court in
Dole mentioned, but did not
adopt, a further limitation, one hypothetically raised a
half-century earlier: In “some circumstances,” Congress might be
prohibited from offering a “financial inducement . . . so
coercive as to pass the point at which ‘pressure turns into
compulsion.’ ”
Id., at 211 (quoting
Steward Machine
Co. v.
Davis,
301 U.S.
548, 590 (1937)). Prior to today’s decision, however, the Court
has never ruled that the terms of any grant crossed the indistinct
line between temptation and coercion.
Dole involved the National Minimum
Drinking Age Act, 23 U. S. C. §158, enacted in 1984. That
Act directed the Secretary of Transportation to withhold 5% of the
federal highway funds otherwise payable to a State if the State
permitted purchase of alcoholic beverages by persons less than 21
years old. Drinking age was not within the authority of Congress to
regulate, South Dakota argued, because the Twenty-First Amendment
gave the States exclusive power to control the manufacture,
transportation, and consumption of alcoholic beverages. The small
percentage of highway-construction funds South Dakota stood to lose
by adhering to 19 as the age of eligibility to purchase 3.2% beer,
however, was not enough to qualify as coercion, the Court
concluded.
This case does not present the concerns that led
the Court in
Dole even to consider the prospect of coercion.
In
Dole, the condition—set 21 as the minimum drinking age—
did not tell the States how to use funds Congress pro- vided for
highway construction. Further, in view of the Twenty-First
Amendment, it was an open question whether Congress could directly
impose a national minimum drinking age.
The ACA, in contrast, relates solely to the
federally funded Medicaid program; if States choose not to comply,
Congress has not threatened to withhold funds earmarked for any
other program. Nor does the ACA use Medicaid funding to induce
States to take action Congress itself could not undertake. The
Federal Government undoubtedly could operate its own health-care
program for poor persons, just as it operates Medicare for seniors’
health care. See
supra, at 44.
That is what makes this such a simple case, and
the Court’s decision so unsettling. Congress, aiming to assist the
needy, has appropriated federal money to subsidize state
health-insurance programs that meet federal standards. The
principal standard the ACA sets is that the state program cover
adults earning no more than 133% of the federal poverty line.
Enforcing that prescription ensures that federal funds will be
spent on health care for the poor in furtherance of Congress’
present perception of the general welfare.
C
The Chief Justice asserts that the Medicaid
expan- sion creates a “new health care program.”
Ante, at
54. Moreover, States could “hardly anticipate” that Congress would
“transform [the program] so dramatically.”
Ante, at 55.
Therefore, The Chief Justice maintains, Congress’ threat to
withhold “old” Medicaid funds based on a State’s refusal to
participate in the “new” program is a “threa[t] to terminate
[an]other . . . independent gran[t].”
Ante, at 50,
52–53. And because the threat to withhold a large amount of funds
from one program “leaves the States with no real option but to
acquiesce [in a newly created program],” The Chief Justice
concludes, the Medicaid expansion is unconstitutionally coercive.
Ante, at 52.
1
The starting premise on which The Chief
Justice’s coercion analysis rests is that the ACA did not really
“extend” Medicaid; instead, Congress created an entirely new
program to co-exist with the old. The Chief Justice calls the ACA
new, but in truth, it simply reaches more of America’s poor than
Congress originally covered.
Medicaid was created to enable States to provide
medical assistance to “needy persons.” See S. Rep. No. 404, 89th
Cong., 1st Sess., pt. 1, p. 9 (1965). See also §121(a),
79Stat. 343 (The purpose of Medicaid is to enable States “to
furnish . . . medical assistance on behalf of [certain
persons] whose income and resources are insufficient to meet the
costs of necessary medical services.”). By bringing health care
within the reach of a larger population of Americans unable to
afford it, the Medicaid expansion is an extension of that basic
aim.
The Medicaid Act contains hundreds of provisions
governing operation of the program, setting conditions ranging from
“Limitation on payments to States for expend- itures attributable
to taxes,” 42 U. S. C. §1396a(t) (2006 ed.), to “Medical
assistance to aliens not lawfully admitted for permanent
residence,” §1396b(v) (2006 ed. and Supp. IV). The Medicaid
expansion leaves unchanged the vast majority of these provisions;
it adds beneficiaries to the existing program and specifies the
rate at which States will be reimbursed for services provided to
the added bene- ficiaries. See ACA §§2001(a)(1), (3), 124Stat.
271–272. The ACA does not describe operational aspects of the
program for these newly eligible persons; for that information, one
must read the existing Medicaid Act. See 42 U. S. C.
§§1396–1396v(b) (2006 ed. and Supp. IV).
Congress styled and clearly viewed the Medicaid
expansion as an amendment to the Medicaid Act, not as a “new”
health-care program. To the four categories of beneficiaries for
whom coverage became mandatory in 1965, and the three mandatory
classes added in the late 1980’s, see
supra, at 41–42, the
ACA adds an eighth: individuals under 65 with incomes not exceeding
133% of the federal poverty level. The expansion is effectuated by
§2001 of the ACA, aptly titled: “Medicaid Coverage for the Lowest
Income Populations.” 124Stat. 271. That section amends Title 42,
Chapter 7, Subchapter XIX: Grants to States for Medical Assistance
Programs. Commonly known as the Medicaid Act, Subchapter XIX filled
some 278 pages in 2006. Section 2001 of the ACA would add
approximately three pages.[
19]
Congress has broad authority to construct or
adjust spending programs to meet its contemporary understanding of
“the general Welfare.”
Helvering v.
Davis,
301 U.S.
619, 640–641 (1937). Courts owe a large measure of respect to
Congress’ characterization of the grant programs it establishes.
See
Steward Machine, 301 U. S., at 594. Even if courts were
inclined to second-guess Congress’ conception of the character of
its legislation, how would reviewing judges divine whether an Act
of Congress, purporting to amend a law, is in reality not an
amendment, but a new creation? At what point does an extension
become so large that it “transforms” the basic law?
Endeavoring to show that Congress created a new
program, The Chief Justice cites three aspects of the expansion.
First, he asserts that, in covering those earning no more than 133%
of the federal poverty line, the Medicaid expansion, unlike pre-ACA
Medicaid, does not “care for the neediest among us.”
Ante,
at 53. What makes that so? Single adults earning no more than
$14,856 per year—133% of the current federal poverty level—surely
rank among the Nation’s poor.
Second, according to The Chief Justice,
“Congress mandated that newly eligible persons receive a level of
coverage that is less comprehensive than the traditional Medicaid
benefit package.”
Ibid. That less comprehensive benefit
package, however, is not an innovation introduced by the ACA; since
2006, States have been free to use it for many of their Medicaid
beneficiaries.[
20] The level
of benefits offered therefore does not set apart post-ACA Medicaid
recipients from all those entitled to benefits pre-ACA.
Third, The Chief Justice correctly notes that
the reimbursement rate for participating States is differ- ent
regarding individuals who became Medicaid-eligible through the ACA.
Ibid. But the rate differs only in its generosity to
participating States. Under pre-ACA Medicaid, the Federal
Government pays up to 83% of the costs of coverage for current
enrollees, §1396d(b) (2006 ed. and Supp. IV); under the ACA, the
federal contribution starts at 100% and will eventually settle at
90%, §1396d(y). Even if one agreed that a change of as little as 7
percentage points carries constitutional significance, is it not
passing strange to suggest that the purported incursion on state
sovereignty might have been averted, or at least mitigated, had
Congress offered States
less money to carry out the same
obligations?
Consider also that Congress could have repealed
Medicaid. See
supra, at 38–39 (citing 42 U. S. C.
§1304); Brief for Petitioners in No. 11–400, p. 41.
Thereafter, Congress could have enacted Medicaid II, a new program
combin- ing the pre-2010 coverage with the expanded coverage
required by the ACA. By what right does a court stop Congress from
building up without first tearing down?
2
The Chief Justice finds the Medicaid expansion
vulnerable because it took participating States by surprise.
Ante, at 54. “A State could hardly anticipate that
Congres[s]” would endeavor to “transform [the Medicaid program] so
dramatically,” he states.
Ante, at 54–55. For the notion
that States must be able to foresee, when they sign up, alterations
Congress might make later on, The Chief Justice cites only one
case:
Pennhurst State School and Hospital v.
Halderman,
451 U.S.
1.
In
Pennhurst, residents of a state-run,
federally funded institution for the mentally disabled complained
of abusive treatment and inhumane conditions in alleged violation
of the Developmentally Disabled Assistance and Bill of Rights Act.
451 U. S., at 5–6. We held that the State was not answerable
in damages for violating conditions it did not “voluntarily and
knowingly accep[t].”
Id., at 17, 27. Inspecting the
statutory language and legislative his- tory, we found that the Act
did not “unambiguously” impose the requirement on which the
plaintiffs relied: that they receive appropriate treatment in the
least restrictive environment.
Id., at 17–18. Satisfied that
Congress had not clearly conditioned the States’ receipt of federal
funds on the States’ provision of such treatment, we declined to
read such a requirement into the Act. Congress’ spending power, we
concluded, “does not include surprising participating States with
postacceptance or ‘retroactive’ conditions.”
Id., at
24–25.
Pennhurst thus instructs that “if
Congress intends to impose a condition on the grant of federal
moneys, it must do so unambiguously.”
Ante, at 53 (quoting
Pennhurst, 451 U. S., at 17). That requirement is met
in this case. Section 2001 does not take effect until 2014. The ACA
makes perfectly clear what will be required of States that accept
Medicaid funding after that date: They must extend eligibility to
adults with incomes no more than 133% of the federal poverty line.
See 42 U. S. C. §1396a(a)(10)(A) (i)(VIII) (2006 ed. and
Supp. IV).
The Chief Justice appears to find in
Pennhurst a requirement that, when spending legislation is
first passed, or when States first enlist in the federal program,
Congress must provide clear notice of conditions it might later
impose. If I understand his point correctly, it was incumbent on
Congress, in 1965, to warn the States clearly of the size and shape
potential changes to Medicaid might take. And absent such notice,
sizable changes could not be made mandatory. Our decisions do not
support such a requirement.[
21]
In
Bennett v.
New Jersey,
470 U.S.
632 (1985), the Secretary of Education sought to recoup Title I
funds[
22] based on the
State’s noncompliance, from 1970 to 1972, with a 1978 amendment to
Title I. Relying on
Pennhurst, we rejected the Secretary’s
attempt to recover funds based on the States’ alleged violation of
a rule that did not exist when the State accepted and spent the
funds. See 470 U. S.
, at 640 (“New Jersey[,] when it
applied for and received Title I funds for the years 1970–1972[,]
had no basis to believe that the propriety of the expenditures
would be judged by any standards other than the ones in effect
at the time.” (citing
Pennhurst, 451 U. S., at
17, 24–25; emphasis added)).
When amendment of an existing grant program has
no such retroactive effect, however, we have upheld Congress’
instruction. In
Bennett v.
Kentucky Dept. of Ed.,
470 U.S.
656 (1985), the Secretary sued to recapture Title I funds based
on the Commonwealth’s 1974 violation of a spending condition
Congress added to Title I in 1970. Rejecting Kentucky’s argument
pinned to
Pennhurst, we held that the Commonwealth suffered
no surprise after accepting the federal funds. Kentucky was
therefore obliged to re- turn the money. 470 U. S., at
665–666, 673–674. The conditions imposed were to be assessed as of
1974, in light of “the legal requirements in place when the grants
were made,”
id., at 670, not as of 1965, when Title I was
originally enacted.
As these decisions show,
Pennhurst’s rule
demands that conditions on federal funds be unambiguously clear at
the time a State receives and uses the money—not at the time,
perhaps years earlier, when Congress passed the law establishing
the program. See also
Dole, 483 U. S., at 208 (finding
Pennhurst satisfied based on the clarity of the Federal Aid
Highway Act as amended in 1984, without looking back to 1956, the
year of the Act’s adoption).
In any event, from the start, the Medicaid Act
put States on notice that the program could be changed: “The right
to alter, amend, or repeal any provision of [Medicaid],” the
statute has read since 1965, “is hereby reserved to the Congress.”
42 U. S. C. §1304. The “effect of these few simple words”
has long been settled. See
National Railroad Passenger
Corporation v.
Atchison, T. & S. F. R. Co.,
470 U.S.
451, 467–468, n. 22 (1985) (citing
Sinking Fund Cases,
99 U.S.
700, 720 (1879)). By reserving the right to “alter, amend, [or]
repeal” a spending program, Congress “has given special notice of
its intention to retain . . . full and complete power to
make such alterations and amendments . . . as come within
the just scope of legislative power.”
Id., at 720.
Our decision in
Bowen v.
Public
Agencies Opposed to Social Security Entrapment,
477 U.S.
41, 51–52 (1986), is guiding here. As enacted in 1935, the
Social Security Act did not cover state employees.
Id., at
44. In response to pressure from States that wanted coverage for
their employees, Congress, in 1950, amended the Act to allow States
to opt into the program.
Id., at 45. The statutory provision
giving States this option expressly permitted them to withdraw from
the program.
Ibid.
Beginning in the late 1970’s, States
increasingly exercised the option to withdraw.
Id., at 46.
Concerned that withdrawals were threatening the integrity of Social
Security, Congress repealed the termination provision. Congress
thereby changed Social Security from a program voluntary for the
States to one from which they could not escape.
Id., at 48.
California objected, arguing that the change impermissibly deprived
it of a right to withdraw from Social Security.
Id., at
49–50. We unanimously rejected California’s argument.
Id.,
at 51–53. By including in the Act “a clause expressly reserving to
it ‘[t]he right to alter, amend, or repeal any provision’ of the
Act,” we held, Congress put States on notice that the Act “created
no contractual rights.”
Id., at 51–52. The States therefore
had no law-based ground on which to complain about the amendment,
despite the significant character of the change.
The Chief Justice nevertheless would rewrite
§1304 to countenance only the “right to alter
somewhat,” or
“amend,
but not too much.” Congress, however, did not so
qualify §1304. Indeed, Congress retained discretion to “repeal”
Medicaid, wiping it out entirely. Cf.
Delta Air Lines, Inc.
v.
August,
450 U.S.
346, 368 (1981) (Rehnquist, J., dissenting) (invoking “the
common-sense maxim that the greater includes the lesser”). As
Bowen indicates, no State could reasonably have read §1304
as reserving to Congress authority to make adjustments only if
modestly sized.
In fact, no State proceeded on that
understanding. In com- pliance with Medicaid regulations, each
State expressly undertook to abide by future Medicaid changes. See
42 CFR §430.12(c)(1) (2011) (“The [state Medicaid] plan must
provide that it will be amended whenever necessary to reflect
. . . [c]hanges in Federal law, regulations, policy
interpretations, or court decisions.”). Whenever a State notifies
the Federal Government of a change in its own Medicaid program, the
State certifies both that it knows the federally set terms of
participation may change, and that it will abide by those changes
as a condition of continued participation. See,
e.g.,
Florida Agency for Health Care Admin., State Plan Under Title XIX
of the Social Security Act Medical Assistance Program §7.1, p. 86
(Oct. 6, 1992).
The Chief Justice insists that the most recent
expansion, in contrast to its predecessors, “accomplishes a shift
in kind, not merely degree.”
Ante, at 53. But why was
Medicaid altered only in degree, not in kind, when Congress
required States to cover millions of children and pregnant women?
See
supra, at 41–42. Congress did not “merely alte[r] and
expan[d] the boundaries of” the Aid to Families with Dependent
Children program. But see
ante, at 53–55. Rather, Congress
required participating States to provide coverage tied to the
federal poverty level (as it later did in the ACA), rather than to
the AFDC program. See Brief for National Health Law Program
et al. as
Amici Curiae 16–18. In short, given §1304,
this Court’s construction of §1304’s language in
Bowen, and
the enlargement of Medicaid in the years since 1965,[
23] a State would be hard put to complain
that it lacked fair notice when, in 2010, Congress altered Medicaid
to embrace a larger portion of the Nation’s poor.
3
The Chief Justice ultimately asks whether “the
financial inducement offered by Congress . . . pass[ed]
the point at which pressure turns into compulsion.”
Ante, at
50 (internal quotation marks omitted). The financial inducement
Congress employed here, he concludes, crosses that threshold: The
threatened withholding of “existing Medicaid funds” is “a gun to
the head” that forces States to acquiesce.
Ante, at 50–51
(citing 42 U. S. C. §1396c).[
24]
The Chief Justice sees no need to “fix the
outermost line,”
Steward Machine, 301 U. S., at 591,
“where persuasion gives way to coercion,”
ante, at 55.
Neither do the joint dissenters. See
post, at 36,
38.[
25] Notably, the
decision on which they rely,
Steward Machine, found the
statute at issue inside the line, “wherever the line may be.” 301
U. S., at 591.
When future Spending Clause challenges arrive,
as they likely will in the wake of today’s decision, how will
litigants and judges assess whether “a State has a legitimate
choice whether to accept the federal conditions in exchange for
federal funds”?
Ante, at 48. Are courts to measure the
number of dollars the Federal Government might withhold for
noncompliance? The portion of the State’s budget at stake? And
which State’s—or States’—budget is determinative: the lead
plaintiff, all challenging States (26 in this case, many with quite
different fiscal situations), or some national median?Does it
matter that Florida, unlike most States, imposes no state income
tax, and therefore might be able to replace foregone federal funds
with new state revenue?[
26]
Or that the coercion state officials in fact fear is punishment at
the ballot box for turning down a politically popular federal
grant?
The coercion inquiry, therefore, appears to
involve polit- ical judgments that defy judicial calculation. See
Baker v.
Carr,
369 U.S.
186, 217 (1962). Even commentators sympathetic to robust
enforcement of
Dole’s limitations, see
supra, at 46,
have concluded that conceptions of “impermissible coercion”
premised on States’ perceived inability to decline federal funds
“are just too amorphous to be judicially administrable.” Baker
& Berman, Getting off the
Dole, 78 Ind. L. J. 459,
521, 522, n. 307 (2003) (citing,
e.g., Scalia, The Rule of
Law as a Law of Rules, 56 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1175 (1989)).
At bottom, my colleagues’ position is that the
States’ reliance on federal funds limits Congress’ authority to
alter its spending programs. This gets things backwards: Congress,
not the States, is tasked with spending federal money in service of
the general welfare. And each successive Congress is empowered to
appropriate funds as it sees fit. When the 110th Congress reached a
conclusion about Medicaid funds that differed from its
predecessors’ view, it abridged no State’s right to “existing,” or
“pre-existing,” funds. But see
ante, at 51–52;
post,
at 47–48 (joint opinion of Scalia, Kennedy, Thomas, and Alito,
JJ.). For, in fact, there are no such funds. There is only money
States
anticipate receiving from future Congresses.
D
Congress has delegated to the Secretary of
Health and Human Services the authority to withhold, in whole or in
part, federal Medicaid funds from States that fail to comply with
the Medicaid Act as originally composed and as subsequently
amended. 42 U. S. C. §1396c.[
27] The Chief Justice, however, holds that the
Constitution precludes the Secretary from withholding “existing”
Medicaid funds based on States’ refusal to comply with the expanded
Medi- caid program.
Ante, at 55. For the foregoing reasons,
I disagree that any such withholding would violate the Spending
Clause. Accordingly, I would affirm the decision of the Court of
Appeals for the Eleventh Circuit in this regard.
But in view of The Chief Justice’s disposition,
I agree with him that the Medicaid Act’s severability clause
determines the appropriate remedy. That clause provides that “[i]f
any provision of [the Medicaid Act], or the application thereof to
any person or circumstance, is held in- valid, the remainder of the
chapter, and the application of such provision to other persons or
circumstances shall not be affected thereby.” 42 U. S. C.
§1303.
The Court does not strike down any provision of
the ACA. It prohibits only the “application” of the Secretary’s
authority to withhold Medicaid funds from States that decline to
conform their Medicaid plans to the ACA’s requirements. Thus the
ACA’s authorization of funds to finance the expansion remains
intact, and the Secretary’s authority to withhold funds for reasons
other than noncompliance with the expansion remains unaffected.
Even absent §1303’s command, we would have no
warrant to invalidate the Medicaid expansion, contra
post,
at 46–48 (joint opinion of Scalia, Kennedy, Thomas, and Alito,
JJ.), not to mention the entire ACA,
post, at 49–64 (same).
For when a court confronts an unconstitutional statute, its
endeavor must be to conserve, not destroy, the legislature’s
dominant objective. See,
e.g., Ayotte v.
Planned
Parenthood of Northern New Eng.,
546 U.S.
320, 328–330 (2006). In this case, that objective was to
increase access to health care for the poor by increasing the
States’ access to federal funds. The Chief Justice is undoubtedly
right to conclude that Congress may offer States funds “to expand
the availability of health care, and requir[e] that States
accepting such funds comply with the conditions on their use.”
Ante, at 55. I therefore concur in the judgment with respect
to Part IV–B of The Chief Justice’s opinion.
* * *
For the reasons stated, I agree with The Chief
Justice that, as to the validity of the minimum coverage provi-
sion, the judgment of the Court of Appeals for the Eleventh Circuit
should be reversed. In my view, the provision en- counters no
constitutional obstruction. Further, I would uphold the Eleventh
Circuit’s decision that the Medicaid expansion is within Congress’
spending power.