SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
KRISTINA BOX, COMMISSIONER, INDIANA DEPART-
MENT OF HEALTH, et al.
v. PLANNED PARENTHOOD OF INDIANA
AND KENTUCKY, INC., et al.
on petition for writ of certiorari to the
united states court of appeals for the seventh circuit
No. 18–483. Decided May 28, 2019
Justice Thomas, concurring.
Indiana law prohibits abortion providers from
treating the bodies of aborted children as “infectious waste” and
incinerating them alongside used needles, laboratory-animal
carcasses, and surgical byproducts. Ind. Code §16–41–16–4(d)
(2019); see §§16–41–16–2, 16–41–16–4, 16–41–16–5; Ind. Admin. Code,
tit. 410, §§35–1–3, 35–2–1(a)(2) (2019). A panel of the Seventh
Circuit held that this fetal-remains law was irrational, and thus
unconstitutional, under the doctrine of “substantive due process.”
That decision was manifestly inconsistent with our precedent, as
the Court holds.[
1] I would
have thought it could go without saying that nothing in the
Constitution or any decision of this Court prevents a State from
requiring abortion facilities to provide for the respectful
treatment of human remains.
I write separately to address the other aspect
of Indiana law at issue here—the “Sex Selective and Disability
Abortion Ban.” Ind. Code §16–34–4–1
et seq. This
statute makes it illegal for an abortion provider to perform an
abortion in Indiana when the provider knows that the mother is
seeking the abortion solely because of the child’s race, sex,
diagnosis of Down syndrome, disability, or related characteristics.
§§16–34–4–1 to 16–34–4–8; see §16–34–4–1(b) (excluding “lethal
fetal anomal[ies]” from the definition of disability). The law
requires that the mother be advised of this restriction and given
information about financial assistance and adoption alternatives,
but it imposes liability only on the provider. See
§§16–34–2–1.1(a)(1)(K), (2)(A)–(C), 16–34–4–9. Each of the
immutable characteristics protected by this law can be known
relatively early in a pregnancy, and the law prevents them from
becoming the sole criterion for deciding whether the child will
live or die. Put differently, this law and other laws like it
promote a State’s compelling interest in preventing abortion from
becoming a tool of modern-day eugenics.[
2]
The use of abortion to achieve eugenic goals is
not merely hypothetical. The foundations for legalizing abortion in
America were laid during the early 20th-century birth-control
movement. That movement developed alongside the American eugenics
movement. And significantly, Planned Parenthood founder Margaret
Sanger recognized the eugenic potential of her cause. She
emphasized and embraced the notion that birth control “opens the
way to the eugenist.” Sanger, Birth Control and Racial Betterment,
Birth Control Rev., Feb. 1919, p. 12 (Racial Betterment). As a
means of reducing the “ever increasing, unceasingly spawning class
of human beings who never should have been born at all,” Sanger
argued that “Birth Control . . . is really the greatest
and most truly eugenic method” of “human generation.” M. Sanger,
Pivot of Civilization 187, 189 (1922) (Pivot of Civilization). In
her view, birth control had been “accepted by the most clear
thinking and far seeing of the Eugenists themselves as the most
constructive and necessary of the means to racial health.”
Id., at 189.
It is true that Sanger was not referring to
abortion when she made these statements, at least not directly. She
recognized a moral difference between “contraceptives” and other,
more “extreme” ways for “women to limit their families,” such as
“the horrors of abortion and infanticide.” M. Sanger, Woman and the
New Race 25, 5 (1920) (Woman and the New Race). But Sanger’s
arguments about the eugenic value of birth control in securing “the
elimination of the unfit,” Racial Betterment 11, apply with even
greater force to abortion, making it significantly more effective
as a tool of eugenics. Whereas Sanger believed that birth control
could prevent “unfit” people from reproducing, abortion can prevent
them from being born in the first place. Many eugenicists therefore
supported legalizing abortion, and abortion advocates—including
future Planned Parenthood President Alan Guttmacher—endorsed the
use of abortion for eugenic reasons. Technological advances have
only heightened the eugenic potential for abortion, as abortion can
now be used to eliminate children with unwanted characteristics,
such as a particular sex or disability.
Given the potential for abortion to become a
tool of eugenic manipulation, the Court will soon need to confront
the constitutionality of laws like Indiana’s. But because further
percolation may assist our review of this issue of first
impression, I join the Court in declining to take up the issue
now.
I
The term “eugenics” was coined in 1883 by
Francis Galton, a British statistician and half-cousin of Charles
Darwin. See S. Caron, Who Chooses?: American Reproductive History
Since 1830, p. 49 (2008); A. Cohen, Imbeciles: The Supreme
Court, American Eugenics, and the Sterilization of Carrie Buck 46
(2016) (Imbeciles). Galton described eugenics as “the science of
improving stock” through “all influences that tend in however
remote a degree to give to the more suitable races or strains of
blood a better chance of prevailing speedily over the less suit-
able than they otherwise would have.” F. Galton, Inquiries Into
Human Faculty and Its Development 25, n. 1 (1883). Eugenics
thus rests on the assumption that “man’s natural abilities are
derived by inheritance, under exactly the same limitations as are
the form and physical features of the whole organic world.” F.
Galton, Hereditary Genius: An Inquiry Into Its Laws and
Consequences 1 (1869) (Hereditary Genius); see Imbeciles 46–47. As
a social theory, eugenics is rooted in social
Darwinism—
i.e., the application of the “survival of the
fittest” principle to human society. Caron,
supra, at 49;
Imbeciles 45. Galton argued that by promoting reproduction between
people with desirable qualities and inhibiting reproduction of the
unfit, man could improve society by “do[ing] providently, quickly,
and kindly” “[w]hat Nature does blindly, slowly, and ruthlessly.”
F. Galton, Eugenics: Its Definition, Scope and Aims, in Essays in
Eugenics 42 (1909).
By the 1920s, eugenics had become a
“full-fledged intellectual craze” in the United States,
particularly among progressives, professionals, and intellectual
elites. Imbeciles 2; see
id., at 2–4, 55–57; Cohen,
Harvard’s Eugenics Era, Harvard Magazine, pp. 48–52 (Mar.–Apr.
2016) (Harvard’s Eugenics Era). Leaders in the eugenics movement
held prominent positions at Harvard, Stanford, and Yale, among
other schools, and eugenics was taught at 376 universities and
colleges. Imbeciles 4; see also Harvard’s Eugenics Era 48. Although
eugenics was widely embraced, Harvard was “more central to American
eugenics than any other university,” with administrators, faculty
members, and alumni “founding eugenics organizations, writing
academic and popular eugenics articles, and lobbying government to
enact eugenics laws.”
Ibid.; see
id., at 49–52. One
Harvard faculty member even published a leading textbook on the
subject through the Harvard University Press, Genetics and
Eugenics.
Id., at 49.
Many eugenicists believed that the distinction
between the fit and the unfit could be drawn along racial lines, a
distinction they justified by pointing to anecdotal and statistical
evidence of disparities between the races. Galton, for example,
purported to show as a scientific matter that “the average
intellectual standard of the negro race is some two grades below”
that of the Anglo-Saxon, and that “the number among the negroes of
those whom we should call half-witted men, is very large.”
Hereditary Genius 338–339. Other eugenicists similarly concluded
that “the Negro . . . is in the large eugenically
inferior to the white” based on “the relative achievements
of the race” and statistical disparities in educational outcomes
and life expectancy in North America, among other factors. P.
Popenoe & R. Johnson, Applied Eugenics 285 (1920) (Applied
Eugenics); see
id., at 280–297 (elaborating on this view);
see also,
e.g., R. Gates, Heredity and Eugenics 234 (1923)
(citing disparities between white and black people and concluding
that “the negro’s mental status is thus undoubtedly more primitive
than that of the white man”); Hunt, Hand, Pettis, & Russell,
Abstract, Family Stock Values in White-Negro Crosses: A Note on
Miscegenation, 8 Eugenical News 67 (1923) (“Experiments, as well as
general experience, indicate that the average inborn intelligence
of the white man is considerably higher than that of the
negro”).
Building on similar assumptions, eugenicist
Lothrop Stoddard argued that the “prodigious birth-rate” of the
nonwhite races was bringing the world to a racial tipping point. L.
Stoddard, The Rising Tide of Color Against White World-Supremacy
8–9 (1920). Stoddard feared that without “artificial barriers,” the
races “will increasingly mingle, and the inevitable result will be
the supplanting or absorption of the higher by the lower types.”
Id., at 302. Allowing the white race to be overtaken by
inferior races, according to Stoddard, would be a tragedy of his-
toric proportions:
“[T]hat would mean that the race obviously
endowed with the greatest creative ability, the race which had
achieved most in the past and which gave the richer promise for the
future, had passed away, carrying with it to the grave those
potencies upon which the realization of man’s highest hopes
depends. A million years of human evolution might go uncrowned, and
earth’s supreme life-product, man, might never fulfil his potential
destiny. This is why we today face ‘The Crisis of the Ages.’ ”
Id., at 304.
Eugenic arguments like these helped precipitate
the Immigration Act of 1924, which significantly reduced
immigration from outside of Western and Northern Europe.
§§11(a)–(b), 43Stat. 159; Imbeciles 126–135; see also
id.,
at 135 (discussing the difficulties the Act created for many Jews
seeking to flee Nazism). The perceived superiority of the white
race also led to calls for race consciousness in marital and
reproductive decisions, including through antimiscegenation laws.
Applied Eugenics 296 (“We hold that it is to the interests of the
United States . . . to prevent further Negro-white
amalgamation”).
Although race was relevant, eugenicists did not
define a person’s “fitness” exclusively by race. A typical list of
dysgenic individuals would also include some combination of the
“feeble-minded,” “insane,” “criminalistic,” “deformed,” “crippled,”
“epileptic,” “inebriate,” “diseased,” “blind,” “deaf,” and
“dependent (including orphans and paupers).” Imbeciles 139; see
Applied Eugenics 176–183; cf. G. Chesterton, Eugenics and Other
Evils 61 (1922) (“[F]eeble-mindedness is a new phrase under which
you might segregate anybody” because “this phrase conveys nothing
fixed and outside opinion”). Immigration policy was insufficient to
address these “danger[s] from within,” Imbeciles 4, so eugenicists
turned to other solutions. Many States adopted laws prohibiting
marriages between certain feebleminded, epileptic, or other “unfit”
individuals, but forced sterilization emerged as the preferred
solution for many classes of dysgenic individuals.
Id., at
63, 66. Indiana enacted the first eugenic sterilization law in
1907, and a number of other States followed suit.
Id., at
70.
This Court threw its prestige behind the
eugenics movement in its 1927 decision upholding the
constitutionality of Virginia’s forced-sterilization law,
Buck v.
Bell,
274 U.S.
200. The plaintiff, Carrie Buck, had been found to be “a feeble
minded white woman” who was “the daughter of a feeble minded mother
. . . and the mother of an illegitimate feeble minded
child.”
Id., at 205.[
3]
In an opinion written by Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., and
joined by seven other Justices, the Court offered a full-throated
defense of forced sterilization:
“We have seen more than once that the
public welfare may call upon the best citizens for their lives. It
would be strange if it could not call upon those who already sap
the strength of the State for these lesser sacrifices, often not
felt to be such by those concerned, in order to prevent our being
swamped with incompetence. It is better for all the world, if
instead of waiting to execute degenerate offspring for crime, or to
let them starve for their imbecility, society can prevent those who
are manifestly unfit from continuing their kind. The principle that
sustains compulsory vaccination is broad enough to cover cutting
the Fallopian tubes. Three generations of imbeciles are enough.”
Id., at 207 (citation omitted).
The Court’s decision gave the eugenics movement
added legitimacy and considerable momentum; by 1931, 28 of the
Nation’s 48 States had adopted eugenic sterilization laws.
Imbeciles 299–300. Buck was one of more than 60,000 people who were
involuntarily sterilized between 1907 and 1983.
Id., at
319.
Support for eugenics waned considerably by the
1940s as Americans became familiar with the eugenics of the Nazis
and scientific literature undermined the assumptions on which the
eugenics movement was built. But even today, the Court continues to
attribute legal significance to the same types of racial-disparity
evidence that were used to justify race-based eugenics. See T.
Sowell, Discrimination and Disparities 5–6 (rev. ed. 2019)
(Sowell).[
4] And support for
the goal of reducing undesirable populations through selective
reproduction has by no means vanished.
II
This case highlights the fact that abortion is
an act rife with the potential for eugenic manipulation. From the
beginning, birth control and abortion were promoted as means of
effectuating eugenics. Planned Parenthood founder Margaret Sanger
was particularly open about the fact that birth control could be
used for eugenic purposes. These arguments about the eugenic
potential for birth control apply with even greater force to
abortion, which can be used to target specific children with
unwanted characteristics. Even after World War II, future Planned
Parenthood President Alan Guttmacher and other abortion advocates
endorsed abortion for eugenic reasons and promoted it as a means of
controlling the population and improving its quality. As explained
below, a growing body of evidence suggests that eugenic goals are
already being realized through abortion.
A
Like many elites of her day, Sanger accepted
that eugenics was “the most adequate and thorough avenue to the
solution of racial, political and social problems.” Sanger, The
Eugenic Value of Birth Control Propaganda, Birth Control Rev., Oct.
1921, p. 5 (Propaganda). She agreed with eugenicists that “the
unbalance between the birth rate of the ‘unfit’ and the
‘fit’ ” was “the greatest present menace to civilization.”
Ibid. Particularly “in a democracy like that of the United
States,” where “[e]quality of political power has . . .
been bestowed upon the lowest elements of our population,” Sanger
worried that “reckless spawning carries with it the seeds of
destruction.” Pivot of Civilization 177–178.
Although Sanger believed that society was
“indebted” to “the Eugenists” for diagnosing these problems, she
did not believe that they had “show[n] much power in suggesting
practical and feasible remedies.”
Id., at 178
. “As an
advocate of Birth Control,” Sanger attempted to fill the gap by
showing that birth control had “eugenic and civilizational value.”
Propaganda 5. In her view, birth-control advocates and eugenicists
were “seeking a single end”—“to assist the race toward the
elimination of the unfit.” Racial Betterment 11. But Sanger
believed that the focus should be “upon stopping not only the
reproduction of the unfit but upon stopping
all reproduction
when there is not economic means of providing proper care for those
who are born in health.”
Ibid. (emphasis added). Thus, for
Sanger, forced sterilization did “not go to the bottom of the
matter” because it did not “touc[h] the great problem of unlimited
reproduction” of “those great masses, who through economic pressure
populate the slums and there produce in their helplessness other
helpless, diseased and incompetent masses, who overwhelm all that
eugenics can do among those whose economic condition is better.”
Id., at 12. In Sanger’s view, frequent reproduction among
“the majority of wage workers” would lead to “the contributing of
morons, feeble-minded, insane and various criminal types to the
already tremendous social burden constituted by these unfit.”
Ibid.
Sanger believed that birth control was an
important part of the solution to these societal ills. She
explained, “Birth Control . . . is really the greatest
and most truly eugenic method” of “human generation,” “and its
adoption as part of the program of Eugenics would immediately give
a concrete and realistic power to that science.” Pivot of
Civilization 189. Sanger even argued that “eugenists and others who
are laboring for racial betterment” could not “succeed” unless they
“first clear[ed] the way for Birth Control.” Racial Betterment 11.
If “the masses” were given “practical education in Birth
Control”—for which there was “almost universal demand”—then the
“Eugenic educator” could use “Birth Control propaganda” to “direct
a thorough education in Eugenics” and influence the reproductive
decisions of the unfit. Propaganda 5. In this way, “the campaign
for Birth Control [was] not merely of eugenic value, but [was]
practically identical in ideal with the final aims of Eugenics.”
Ibid.
Sanger herself campaigned for birth control in
black communities. In 1930, she opened a birth-control clinic in
Harlem. See Birth Control or Race Control? Sanger and the Negro
Project, Margaret Sanger Papers Project Newsletter #28 (2001),
http://www.nyu.edu/projects/sanger/ articles/bc_or_race_control.php
(all Internet materials as last visited May 24, 2019). Then, in
1939, Sanger initiated the “Negro Project,” an effort to promote
birth control in poor, Southern black communities.
Ibid.
Noting that blacks were “ ‘notoriously underprivileged and
handicapped to a large measure by a “caste” system,’ ” she
argued in a fundraising letter that “ ‘birth control knowledge
brought to this group, is the most direct, constructive aid that
can be given them to improve their immediate situation.’ ”
Ibid. In a report titled “Birth Control and the Negro,”
Sanger and her coauthors identified blacks as “ ‘the great
problem of the South’ ”—“the group with ‘the greatest
economic, health, and social problems’ ”—and developed a
birth-control program geared toward this population.
Ibid.
She later emphasized that black ministers should be involved in the
program, noting, “ ‘We do not want word to go out that we want
to exterminate the Negro population, and the minister is the man
who can straighten out that idea if it ever occurs to any of their
more rebellious members.’ ”
Ibid.
Defenders of Sanger point out that W. E. B.
DuBois and other black leaders supported the Negro Project and
argue that her writings should not be read to imply a racial bias.
Ibid.; see Planned Parenthood, Opposition Claims About
Margaret Sanger (2016), https://www.
plannedparenthood.org/uploads/filer_public/37/ fd / 37fdc7b6-
de5f-4d22 - 8c05 - 9568268e92d8 / sanger_opposition_claims_
fact_sheet_2016.pdf. But Sanger’s motives are immaterial to the
point relevant here: that “Birth Control” has long been understood
to “ope[n] the way to the eugenist.” Racial Betterment 12.
B
To be sure, Sanger distinguished between birth
control and abortion. Woman and the New Race 128–129; see,
e.g., Sanger, Birth Control or Abortion? Birth Control Rev.,
Dec. 1918, pp. 3–4. For Sanger, “[t]he one means health and
happiness—a stronger, better race,” while “[t]he other means
disease, suffering, [and] death.” Woman and the New Race 129.
Sanger argued that “nothing short of contraceptives can put an end
to the horrors of abortion and infanticide,”
id., at 25, and
she questioned whether “we want the precious, tender qualities of
womanhood, so much needed for our racial development, to perish in
[the] sordid, abnormal experiences” of abortions,
id., at
29. In short, unlike contraceptives, Sanger regarded “the hundreds
of thousands of abortions performed in America each year [as] a
disgrace to civilization.”
Id., at 126.
Although Sanger was undoubtedly correct in
recognizing a moral difference between birth control and abortion,
the eugenic arguments that she made in support of birth control
apply with even greater force to abortion. Others were well aware
that abortion could be used as a “metho[d] of eugenics,” 6 H.
Ellis, Studies in the Psychology of Sex 617 (1910), and they were
enthusiastic about that possibility. Indeed, some eugenicists
believed that abortion should be legal for the very
purpose
of promoting eugenics. See Harris, Abortion in Soviet Russia: Has
the Time Come To Legalize It Elsewhere? 25 Eugenics Rev. 22 (1933)
(“[W]e are being increasingly compelled to consider legalized
abortion as well as birth control and sterilization as possible
means of influencing the fitness and happiness and quality of the
race”); Aims and Objects of the Eugenics Society, 26 Eugenics Rev.
135 (1934) (“The
Society advocates the provision of
legalized facilities for voluntarily terminating pregnancy in cases
of persons for whom sterilization is regarded as appropriate”).
Support for abortion can therefore be found throughout the
literature on eugenics.
E.g., Population Control: Dr. Binnie
Dunlop’s Address to the Eugenics Society, 25 Eugenics Rev. 251
(1934) (lamenting “the relatively high birth-rate of the poorest
third of the population” and “the serious rate of racial
deterioration which it implied,” and arguing that “this birth-rate
. . . would fall rapidly if artificial abortion were made
legal”); Williams, The Legalization of Medical Abortion, 56
Eugenics Rev. 24–25 (1964) (“I need hardly stress the eugenic
argument for extending family planning”—including “voluntary
sterilization” and “abortion”—to “all groups, not merely to those
who are the most intelligent and socially responsible”).
Abortion advocates were sometimes candid about
abortion’s eugenic possibilities. In 1959, for example, Guttmacher
explicitly endorsed eugenic reasons for abortion. A. Guttmacher,
Babies by Choice or by Chance 186–188 (1959). He explained that
“the quality of the parents must be taken into account,” including
“[f ]eeble-mindedness,” and believed that “it should be
permissible to abort any pregnancy . . . in which there
is a strong probability of an abnormal or malformed infant.”
Id., at 198. He added that the question whether to allow
abortion must be “separated from emotional, moral and religious
concepts” and “must have as its focus normal, healthy infants born
into homes peopled with parents who have healthy bodies and minds.”
Id., at 221. Similarly, legal scholar Glanville Williams
wrote that he was open to the possibility of eugenic infanticide,
at least in some situations, explaining that “an eugenic killing by
a mother, exactly paralleled by the bitch that kills her mis-
shapen puppies, cannot confidently be pronounced im- moral.” G.
Williams, Sanctity of Life and the Criminal Law 20 (1957). The
Court cited Williams’ book for a different proposition in
Roe v.
Wade,
410 U.S.
113, 130, n. 9 (1973).
But public aversion to eugenics after World War
II also led many to avoid explicit references to that term. The
American Eugenics Society, for example, changed the name of its
scholarly publication from “Eugenics Quarterly” to “Social
Biology.” See D. Paul, Controlling Human Heredity: 1865 to the
Present, p. 125 (1995). In explaining the name change, the
journal’s editor stated that it had become evident that eugenic
goals could be achieved “for reasons other than eugenics.”
Ibid. For example, “[b]irth control and abortion are turning
out to be great eugenic advances of our time. If they had been
advanced for eugenic reasons it would have retarded or stopped
their acceptance.”
Ibid. But whether they used the term
“eugenics” or not, abortion advocates echoed the arguments of early
20th-century eugenicists by describing abortion as a way to achieve
“population control” and to improve the “quality” of the
population. One journal declared that “abortion is the one mode of
population limitation which has demonstrated the speedy impact
which it can make upon a national problem.” Notes of the Quarter:
The Personal and the Universal, 53 Eugenics Rev. 186 (1962).
Planned Parenthood’s leaders echoed these themes. When exulting
over “ ‘fantastic . . . progress’ ” in
expanding abortion, for example, Guttmacher stated that “ ‘the
realization of the population problem has been responsible’ for the
change in attitudes. ‘We’re now concerned more with the quality of
population than the quantity.’ ” Abortion Reforms Termed
“Fantastic,” Hartford Courant, Mar. 21, 1970, p. 16.
Avoiding the word “eugenics” did not assuage
everyone’s fears. Some black groups saw “ ‘family planning’ as
a euphemism for race genocide” and believed that “black people
[were] taking the brunt of the ‘planning’ ” under Planned
Parenthood’s “ghetto approach” to distributing its services.
Dempsey, Dr. Guttmacher Is the Evangelist of Birth Control,
N. Y. Times Magazine, Feb. 9, 1969, p. 82. “The
Pittsburgh branch of the National Association for the Advancement
of Colored People,” for example, “criticized family planners as
bent on trying to keep the Negro birth rate as low as possible.”
Kaplan, Abortion and Sterilization Win Support of Planned
Parenthood, N. Y. Times, Nov. 14, 1968, p. L50, col.
1.
C
Today, notwithstanding Sanger’s views on
abortion, respondent Planned Parenthood promotes both birth control
and abortion as “reproductive health services” that can be used for
family planning. Brief in Opposition 1. And with today’s prenatal
screening tests and other technologies, abortion can easily be used
to eliminate children with unwanted characteristics. Indeed, the
individualized nature of abortion gives it even more eugenic
potential than birth control, which simply reduces the chance of
conceiving
any child. As petitioners and several
amicus
curiae briefs point out, moreover, abortion has proved to be a
disturbingly effective tool for implementing the discriminatory
preferences that undergird eugenics.
E.g., Pet. for Cert.
22–26; Brief for State of Wisconsin et al. as
Amici
Curiae 19–25; Brief for Ethics and Religious Liberty Commission
of the Southern Baptist Convention et al. as
Amici
Curiae 9–10.
In Iceland, the abortion rate for children
diagnosed with Down syndrome in utero approaches 100%. See Will,
The Down Syndrome Genocide, Washington Post, Mar. 15, 2018,
p. A23, col. 1. Other European countries have similarly high
rates, and the rate in the United States is approximately
two-thirds. See
ibid. (98% in Denmark, 90% in the United
Kingdom, 77% in France, and 67% in the United States); see also
Natoli, Ackerman, McDermott, & Edwards, Prenatal Diagnosis of
Down Syndrome: A Systematic Review of Termination Rates
(1995–2011), 32 Prenatal Diagnosis 142 (2012) (reviewing U. S.
studies).
In Asia, widespread sex-selective abortions have
led to as many as 160 million “missing” women—more than the entire
female population of the United States. See M. Hvistendahl,
Unnatural Selection: Choosing Boys Over Girls, and the Consequences
of a World Full of Men 5–6 (2011); see also Kalantry, How To Fix
India’s Sex-Selection Problem, N. Y. Times, Int’l ed., July
28, 2017, p. 9 (“Over the course of several decades, 300,000
to 700,000 female fetuses were selectively aborted in India each
year. Today there are about 50 million more men than women in the
country”). And recent evidence suggests that sex-selective
abortions of girls are common among certain populations in the
United States as well. See Almond & Sun, Son-Biased Sex Ratios
in 2010 U. S. Census and 2011–2013 U. S. Natality Data,
176 Soc. Sci. & Med. 21 (2017) (concluding that Chinese and
Asian-Indian families in the United States “show a tendency to
sex-select boys”); Almond & Edlund, Son-Biased Sex Ratios in
the 2000 United States Census, 105 Proc. Nat. Acad. of Sci. 5681
(2008) (similar).
Eight decades after Sanger’s “Negro Project,”
abortion in the United States is also marked by a considerable
racial disparity. The reported nationwide abortion ratio— the
number of abortions per 1,000 live births—among black women is
nearly 3.5 times the ratio for white women. Dept. of Health and
Human Services, Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, T.
Jatlaoui et al., Abortion Surveillance—United States, 2015, 67
Morbidity and Mortality Weekly Report, Surveillance Summaries, No.
SS–13, p. 35 (Nov. 23, 2018) (Table 13); see also Brief for
Restoration Project et al. as
Amici Curiae 5–6. And
there are areas of New York City in which black children are more
likely to be aborted than they are to be born alive—and are up to
eight times more likely to be aborted than white children in the
same area. See N. Y. Dept. of Health, Table 23: Induced
Abortion and Abortion Ratios by Race/Ethnicity and Resident County
New York State–2016,
https://www.health.ny.gov/statistics/vital_statistics/
2016/table23.htm. Whatever the reasons for these disparities, they
suggest that, insofar as abortion is viewed as a method of “family
planning,” black people do indeed “tak[e] the brunt of the
‘planning.’ ” Dempsey,
supra, at 82.
Some believe that the United States is already
experiencing the eugenic effects of abortion. According to one
economist, “
Roe v. Wade help[ed] trigger, a generation
later, the greatest crime drop in recorded history.” S. Levitt
& S. Dubner, Freakonomics 6 (2005); see
id., at 136–144
(elaborating on this theory). On this view, “it turns out that not
all children are born equal” in terms of criminal propensity.
Id., at 6
. And legalized abortion meant that the
children of “poor, unmarried, and teenage mothers” who were “much
more likely than average to become criminals” “weren’t being born.”
Ibid. (emphasis deleted). Whether accurate or not, these
observations echo the views articulated by the eugenicists and by
Sanger decades earlier: “Birth Control of itself . . .
will make a better race” and tend “toward the elimination of the
unfit.” Racial Betterment 11–12.
III
It was against this background that Indiana’s
Legislature, on the 100th anniversary of its 1907 sterilization
law, adopted a concurrent resolution formally “express[ing] its
regret over Indiana’s role in the eugenics movement in this country
and the injustices done under eugenic laws.” Ind. S. Res. 91, 115th
Gen. Assemb., 1st Sess., §1 (2007); see Brief for Pro-Life Legal
Defense Fund et al. as
Amici Curiae 6–8. Recognizing
that laws implementing eugenic goals “targeted the most vulnerable
among us, including the poor and racial minorities, . . .
for the claimed purpose of public health and the good of the
people,” Ind. S. Res. 91, at 2, the General Assembly “urge[d] the
citizens of Indiana to become familiar with the history of the
eugenics movement” and “repudiate the many laws passed in the name
of eugenics and reject any such laws in the future,”
id.,
§2.
In March 2016, the Indiana Legislature passed by
wide margins the Sex-Selective and Disability Abortion Ban at issue
here. Respondent Planned Parenthood promptly filed a lawsuit to
block the law from going into effect, arguing that the Constitution
categorically protects a woman’s right to abort her child based
solely on the child’s race, sex, or disability. The District Court
agreed, granting a preliminary injunction on the eve of the law’s
effective date, followed by a permanent injunction. A panel of the
Seventh Circuit affirmed. Pointing to
Planned Parenthood of
Southeastern Pa. v.
Casey,
505 U.S.
833 (1992), both the District Court and the Seventh Circuit
held that this Court had already decided the matter:
“
Casey’s holding that a woman has the right to terminate her
pregnancy prior to viability is categorical.”
Planned Parenthood
of Indiana and Kentucky, Inc. v.
Commissioner of Indiana
State Dept. of Health, 888 F.3d 300, 305 (CA7 2018); see
Planned Parenthood of Indiana and Kentucky, Inc. v.
Commissioner,
Indiana State Dept. of Health, 265
F. Supp. 3d 859, 866 (SD Ind. 2017). In an opinion dissenting
from the denial of rehearing en banc, Judge Easterbrook expressed
skepticism as to this holding, explaining that “
Casey did
not consider the validity of an anti-eugenics law” and that
judicial opinions, unlike statutes, “resolve only the situations
presented for decision.”
Planned Parenthood of Indiana and
Kentucky, Inc. v.
Commissioner of Indiana State Dept. of
Health, 917 F.3d 532, 536 (CA7 2018).
Judge Easterbrook was correct. Whatever else
might be said about
Casey, it did not decide whether the
Constitution requires States to allow eugenic abortions. It
addressed the constitutionality of only “five provisions of the
Pennsylvania Abortion Control Act of 1982” that were said to burden
the supposed constitutional right to an abortion.
Casey,
supra, at 844. None of those provisions prohibited abortions
based solely on race, sex, or disability. In fact, the very first
paragraph of the respondents’ brief in
Casey made it clear
to the Court that Pennsylvania’s prohibition on sex-selective
abortions was “not [being] challenged,” Brief for Respondents in
Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v.
Casey, O.
T. 1991, Nos. 91–744, 91–902, p. 4. In light of the Court’s
denial of certiorari today, the constitutionality of other laws
like Indiana’s thus remains an open question.
The Court’s decision to allow further
percolation should not be interpreted as agreement with the
decisions below. Enshrining a constitutional right to an abortion
based solely on the race, sex, or disability of an unborn child, as
Planned Parenthood advocates, would constitutionalize the views of
the 20th-century eugenics movement. In other contexts, the Court
has been zealous in vindicating the rights of people even
potentially subjected to race, sex, and disability discrimination.
Cf.
Pena-Rodriguez v.
Colorado, 580 U. S. ___,
___ (2017) (slip op., at 15) (condemning “discrimination on the
basis of race” as “ ‘odious in all aspects’ ”);
United
States v.
Virginia,
518 U.S.
515, 532 (1996) (denouncing any “law or official policy [that]
denies to women, simply because they are women, . . .
equal opportunity to aspire, achieve, participate in and contribute
to society based on their individual talents and capacities”);
Tennessee v.
Lane,
541 U.S.
509, 522 (2004) (condemning “irrational disability
discrimination”).
Although the Court declines to wade into these
issues today, we cannot avoid them forever. Having created the
constitutional right to an abortion, this Court is dutybound to
address its scope. In that regard, it is easy to understand why the
District Court and the Seventh Circuit looked to
Casey to
resolve a question it did not address. Where else could they turn?
The Constitution itself is silent on abortion.
With these observations, I join the opinion of
the Court.