NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the
United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter
of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Washington,
D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in
order that corrections may be made before the preliminary print
goes to press.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 16–349
_________________
RICKY HENSON, et al., PETITIONERS
v. SANTANDER CONSUMER USA INC.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fourth circuit
[June 12, 2017]
Justice Gorsuch delivered the opinion of the
Court.
Disruptive dinnertime calls, downright deceit,
and more besides drew Congress’s eye to the debt collection
industry. From that scrutiny emerged the Fair Debt Collection
Practices Act, a statute that authorizes private lawsuits and
weighty fines designed to deter wayward collection practices. So
perhaps it comes as little surprise that we now face a question
about who exactly qualifies as a “debt collector” subject to the
Act’s rigors. Everyone agrees that the term embraces the repo
man—someone hired by a creditor to collect an outstanding debt. But
what if you purchase a debt and then try to collect it for
yourself—does that make you a “debt collector” too? That’s the nub
of the dispute now before us.
The parties approach the question from common
ground. The complaint alleges that CitiFinancial Auto loaned money
to petitioners seeking to buy cars; that petitioners defaulted on
those loans; that respondent Santander then purchased the defaulted
loans from CitiFinancial; and that Santander sought to collect in
ways petitioners believe troublesome under the Act. The parties
agree, too, that in deciding whether Santander’s conduct falls
within the Act’s ambit we should look to statutory language
defining the term “debt collector” to embrace anyone who “regularly
collects or attempts to collect . . . debts owed or due
. . . another.” 15 U. S. C. §1692a(6).
Even when it comes to that question, the parties
agree on at least part of an answer. Both sides accept that third
party debt collection agents generally qualify as “debt collectors”
under the relevant statutory language, while those who seek only to
collect for themselves loans they originated generally do not.
These results follow, the parties tell us, because debt collection
agents seek to collect debts “owed . . . another,” while
loan originators acting on their own account aim only to collect
debts owed to themselves. All that remains in dispute is how to
classify individuals and entities who regularly purchase debts
originated by someone else and then seek to collect those debts for
their own account. Does the Act treat the debt purchaser in that
scenario more like the repo man or the loan originator?
For their part, the district court and Fourth
Circuit sided with Santander. They held that the company didn’t
qualify as a debt collector because it didn’t regularly seek to
collect debts “owed . . . another” but sought instead
only to collect debts that it purchased and owned. At the same
time, the Fourth Circuit acknowledged that some circuits faced with
the same question have ruled otherwise—and it is to resolve this
conflict that we took the case. Compare 817 F. 3d 131,
133–134, 137–138 (2016) (case below); Davidson v. Capital
One Bank (USA), N. A., 797 F. 3d 1309, 1315–1316
(CA11 2015), with McKinney v. Caldeway Properties,
Inc., 548 F. 3d 496, 501 (CA7 2008); FTC v.
Check Investors, Inc., 502 F. 3d 159, 173–174 (CA3
2007).
Before attending to that job, though, we pause
to note two related questions we do not attempt to answer today.
First, petitioners suggest that Santander can qualify as a debt
collector not only because it regularly seeks to collect for its
own account debts that it has purchased, but also because it
regularly acts as a third party collection agent for debts owed to
others. Petitioners did not, however, raise the latter theory in
their petition for certiorari and neither did we agree to review
it. Second, the parties briefly allude to another statutory
definition of the term “debt collector”—one that encompasses those
engaged “in any business the principal purpose of which is the
collection of any debts.” §1692a(6). But the parties haven’t much
litigated that alternative definition and in granting certiorari we
didn’t agree to address it either.
With these preliminaries by the board, we can
turn to the much narrowed question properly before us. In doing so,
we begin, as we must, with a careful examination of the statutory
text. And there we find it hard to disagree with the Fourth
Circuit’s interpretive handiwork. After all, the Act defines debt
collectors to include those who regularly seek to collect debts
“owed . . . another.” And by its plain terms this
language seems to focus our attention on third party collection
agents working for a debt owner—not on a debt owner seeking to
collect debts for itself. Neither does this language appear to
suggest that we should care how a debt owner came to be a debt
owner—whether the owner originated the debt or came by it only
through a later purchase. All that matters is whether the target of
the lawsuit regularly seeks to collect debts for its own account or
does so for “another.” And given that, it would seem a debt
purchaser like Santander may indeed collect debts for its own
account without triggering the statutory definition in dispute,
just as the Fourth Circuit explained.
Petitioners reply that this seemingly
straightforward reading overlooks an important question of tense.
They observe that the word “owed” is the past participle of
the verb “to owe.” And this, they suggest, means the statute’s
definition of debt collector captures anyone who regularly seeks to
collect debts previously “owed . . . another.” So
it is that, on petitioners’ account, the statute excludes from its
compass loan originators (for they never seek to collect debts
previously owed someone else) but embraces many debt purchasers
like Santander (for in collecting purchased debts they necessarily
seek to collect debts previously owed another). If Congress wanted
to exempt all present debt owners from its debt collector
definition, petitioners submit, it would have used the
present participle “owing.” That would have better sufficed
to do the job—to make clear that you must collect debts
currently “owing . . . another” before implicating
the Act.
But this much doesn’t follow even as a matter of
good grammar, let alone ordinary meaning. Past participles like
“owed” are routinely used as adjectives to describe the present
state of a thing—so, for example, burnt toast is inedible, a
fallen branch blocks the path, and (equally) a debt
owed to a current owner may be collected by him or her. See
P. Peters, The Cambridge Guide to English Usage 409 (2004)
(explaining that the term “past participle” is a “misnomer[ ],
since” it “can occur in what is technically a present
. . . tense”). Just imagine if you told a friend that you
were seeking to “collect a debt owed to Steve.” Doesn’t it seem
likely your friend would understand you as speaking about a debt
currently owed to Steve, not a debt Steve used to own
and that’s now actually yours? In the end, even petitioners find
themselves forced to admit that past participles can and regularly
do work just this way, as adjectives to describe the present state
of the nouns they modify. See Brief for Petitioners 28; see also B.
Garner, Modern English Usage 666 (4th ed. 2016) (while
“owing . . . is an old and established usage
. . . the more logical course is simply to write
owed”).
Widening our view to take in the statutory
phrase in which the word “owed” appears—“owed or due
. . . another”—serves to underscore the point.
Petitioners acknowledge that the word “due” describes a debt
currently due at the time of collection and not a debt that
was due only in some previous period. Brief for Petitioners
26–28. So to rule for them we would have to suppose Congress set
two words cheek by jowl in the same phrase but meant them to speak
to entirely different periods of time. All without leaving any
clue. We would have to read the phrase not as referring to “debts
that are owed or due another” but as describing “debts that
were owed or are due another.” And supposing such a
surreptitious subphrasal shift in time seems to us a bit much.
Neither are we alone in that assessment, for even petitioners
acknowledge that theirs “may not be the most natural interpretation
of the phrase standing in isolation.” Id., at 26–27.
Given that, you might wonder whether extending
our gaze from the narrow statutory provision at issue to take in
the larger statutory landscape might offer petitioners a better
perspective. But it does not. Looking to other neighboring
provisions in the Act, it quickly comes clear that Congress
routinely used the word “owed” to refer to present (not past) debt
relationships. For example, in one nearby subsection, Congress
defined a creditor as someone “to whom a debt is owed.” 15
U. S. C. §1692a(4). In another subsection, too, Congress
required a debt collector to identify “the creditor to whom the
debt is owed.” §1692g(a)(2). Yet petitioners offer us no persuasive
reason why the word “owed” should bear a different meaning here, in
the subsection before us, or why we should abandon our usual
presumption that “identical words used in different parts of the
same statute” carry “the same meaning.” IBP, Inc. v.
Alvarez, 546 U. S. 21, 34 (2005) .
Still other contextual clues add to petitioners’
problems. While they suggest that the statutory definition before
us implicitly distinguishes between loan originators and debt
purchasers, a pass through the statute shows that when Congress
wished to distinguish between originators and purchasers it left
little doubt in the matter. In the very definitional section where
we now find ourselves working, Congress expressly differentiated
between a person “who offers” credit (the originator) and a person
“to whom a debt is owed” (the present debt owner). §1692a(4).
Elsewhere, Congress recognized the distinction between a debt
“originated by” the collector and a debt “owed or due” another.
§1692a(6)(F)(ii). And elsewhere still, Congress drew a line between
the “original” and “current” creditor. §1692g(a)(5). Yet no similar
distinction can be found in the language now before us. To the
contrary, the statutory text at issue speaks not at all about
originators and current debt owners but only about whether the
defendant seeks to collect on behalf of itself or “another.” And,
usually at least, when we’re engaged in the business of
interpreting statutes we presume differences in language like this
convey differences in meaning. See, e.g., Loughrin v.
United States, 573 U. S. ___, ___ (2014).
Even what may be petitioners’ best piece of
contextual evidence ultimately proves unhelpful to their cause.
Petitioners point out that the Act exempts from the definition of
“debt collector” certain individuals who have “obtained” particular
kinds of debt—for example, debts not yet in default or debts
connected to secured commercial credit transactions.
§§1692a(6)(F)(iii) and (F)(iv). And because these exemptions
contemplate the possibility that someone might “obtain” a debt
“owed or due . . . another,” petitioners submit, the word
“owed” must refer only to a previous owner. Ibid.
This conclusion, they say, necessarily follows because, once you
have “obtained” a debt, that same debt just cannot be
currently “owed or due” another.
This last and quite essential premise of the
argument, however, misses its mark. As a matter of ordinary
English, the word “obtained” can (and often does) refer to taking
possession of a piece of property without also taking ownership—so,
for example, you might obtain a rental car or a hotel room or an
apartment. See, e.g., 10 Oxford English Dictionary 669 (2d
ed. 1989) (defining “obtain” to mean, among other things, “[t]o
come into the possession or enjoyment of (something) by one’s own
effort or by request”); Kirtsaeng v. John Wiley &
Sons, Inc., 568 U. S. 519 –533 (2013) (distinguishing
between ownership and obtaining possession). And it’s easy enough
to see how you might also come to possess (obtain) a debt without
taking ownership of it. You might, for example, take possession of
a debt for servicing and collection even while the debt formally
remains owed another. Or as a secured party you might take
possession of a debt as collateral, again without taking full
ownership of it. See, e.g., U. C. C. §9–207, 3 U.
L. A. 197 (2010). So it simply isn’t the case that the
statute’s exclusions imply that the phrase “owed . . .
another” must refer to debts previously owed to another.
By this point petitioners find themselves in
retreat. Unable to show that debt purchasers regularly collecting
for their own account always qualify as debt collectors, they now
suggest that purchasers sometimes qualify as debt collectors. On
their view, debt purchasers surely qualify as collectors at least
when they regularly purchase and seek to collect defaulted
debts—just as Santander allegedly did here. In support of this
narrower and more particular understanding of the Act, petitioners
point again to the fact that the statute excludes from the
definition of “debt collector” certain persons who obtain debts
before default. 15 U. S. C. §1692a(6)(F)(iii). This
exclusion, petitioners now suggest, implies that the term “debt
collector” must embrace those who regularly seek to collect debts
obtained after default. Others aligned with petitioners also
suggest that the Act treats everyone who attempts to collect a debt
as either a “debt collector” or a “creditor,” but not both. And
because the statutory definition of the term “creditor” excludes
those who seek to collect a debt obtained “in default,” §1692a(4),
they contend it again follows as a matter of necessary inference
that these persons must qualify as debt collectors.
But these alternative lines of inferential
argument bear their own problems. For while the statute surely
excludes from the debt collector definition certain persons who
acquire a debt before default, it doesn’t necessarily follow that
the definition must include anyone who regularly collects debts
acquired after default. After all and again, under the definition
at issue before us you have to attempt to collect debts owed
another before you can ever qualify as a debt collector. And
petitioners’ argument simply does not fully confront this plain and
implacable textual prerequisite. Likewise, even spotting (without
granting) the premise that a person cannot be both a creditor and a
debt collector with respect to a particular debt, we don’t see why
a defaulted debt purchaser like Santander couldn’t qualify as a
creditor. For while the creditor definition excludes persons who
“receive an assignment or transfer of a debt in default,” it does
so only (and yet again) when the debt is assigned or transferred
“solely for the purpose of facilitating collection of such
debt for another.” Ibid. (emphasis added). So
a company collecting purchased defaulted debt for its own
account—like Santander—would hardly seem to be barred from
qualifying as a creditor under the statute’s plain terms.
Faced with so many obstacles in the text and
structure of the Act, petitioners ask us to move quickly on to
policy. Indeed, from the beginning that is the field on which they
seem most eager to pitch battle. Petitioners assert that Congress
passed the Act in large measure to add new incentives for
independent debt collectors to treat consumers well. In their view,
Congress excluded loan originators from the Act’s demands because
it thought they already faced sufficient economic and legal
incentives to good behavior. But, on petitioners’ account, Congress
never had the chance to consider what should be done about those in
the business of purchasing defaulted debt. That’s because,
petitioners tell us, the “advent” of the market for defaulted debt
represents “ ‘one of the most significant changes’ ” to
the debt market generally since the Act’s passage in 1977. Brief
for Petitioners 8 (quoting Consumer Financial Protection Bureau,
Fair Debt Collection Practices Act: CFPB Annual Report 2014, p. 7
(2014)). Had Congress known this new industry would blossom, they
say, it surely would have judged defaulted debt purchasers more
like (and in need of the same special rules as) independent debt
collectors. Indeed, petitioners contend that no other result would
be consistent with the overarching congressional goal of deterring
untoward debt collection practices.
All this seems to us quite a lot of speculation.
And while it is of course our job to apply faithfully the law
Congress has written, it is never our job to rewrite a
constitutionally valid statutory text under the banner of
speculation about what Congress might have done had it faced a
question that, on everyone’s account, it never faced. See
Magwood v. Patterson, 561 U. S. 320, 334 (2010)
(“We cannot replace the actual text with speculation as to
Congress’ intent”). Indeed, it is quite mistaken to assume, as
petitioners would have us, that “whatever” might appear to
“further[ ] the statute’s primary objective must be the law.”
Rodriguez v. United States, 480 U. S. 522, 526
(1987) (per curiam) (emphasis deleted). Legislation is,
after all, the art of compromise, the limitations expressed in
statutory terms often the price of passage, and no statute yet
known “pursues its [stated] purpose[ ] at all costs.”
Id., at 525–526. For these reasons and more besides we will
not presume with petitioners that any result consistent with their
account of the statute’s overarching goal must be the law but will
presume more modestly instead “that [the] legislature says
. . . what it means and means . . . what it
says.” Dodd v. United States, 545 U. S. 353, 357
(2005) (internal quotation marks omitted; brackets in
original).
Even taken on its own terms, too, the
speculation petitioners urge upon us is far from unassailable.
After all, is it really impossible to imagine that reasonable
legislators might contend both ways on the question whether
defaulted debt purchasers should be treated more like loan
originators than independent debt collection agencies? About
whether other existing incentives (in the form of common law
duties, other statutory and regulatory obligations, economic
incentives, or otherwise) suffice to deter debt purchasers from
engaging in certain undesirable collection activities? Couldn’t a
reasonable legislator endorsing the Act as written wonder whether a
large financial institution like Santander is any more or less
likely to engage in abusive conduct than another large financial
institution like CitiFinancial Auto? Especially where (as here) the
institution says that its primary business is loan origination and
not the purchase of defaulted debt? We do not profess sure answers
to any of these questions, but observe only that the parties and
their amici manage to present many and colorable arguments
both ways on them all, a fact that suggests to us for certain but
one thing: that these are matters for Congress, not this Court, to
resolve.
In the end, reasonable people can disagree with
how Congress balanced the various social costs and benefits in this
area. We have no difficulty imagining, for example, a statute that
applies the Act’s demands to anyone collecting any debts, anyone
collecting debts originated by another, or to some other class of
persons still. Neither do we doubt that the evolution of the debt
collection business might invite reasonable disagreements on
whether Congress should reenter the field and alter the judgments
it made in the past. After all, it’s hardly unknown for new
business models to emerge in response to regulation, and for
regulation in turn to address new business models. Constant
competition between constable and quarry, regulator and regulated,
can come as no surprise in our changing world. But neither should
the proper role of the judiciary in that process—to apply, not
amend, the work of the People’s representatives.
The judgment of the Court of Appeals is
Affirmed.