SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 14–10154
_________________
STEPHEN L. VOISINE and WILLIAM E. ARMSTRONG,
III, PETITIONERS
v. UNITED STATES
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the first circuit
[June 27, 2016]
Justice Thomas, with whom Justice Sotomayor
joins as to Parts I and II, dissenting.
Federal law makes it a crime for anyone
previously convicted of a “misdemeanor crime of domestic violence”
to possess a firearm “in or affecting commerce.” 18
U. S. C. §922(g)(9). A “misdemeanor crime of domestic
violence” includes “an offense that . . . has, as an
element, the use or attempted use of physical force . . .
committed by [certain close family members] of the victim.”
§921(a)(33)(A)(ii). In this case, petitioners were convicted under
§922(g)(9) because they possessed firearms and had prior
convictions for assault under Maine’s statute prohibiting
“intention-ally, knowingly or recklessly caus[ing] bodily injury or
offen-sive physical contact to another person.” Me. Rev. Stat.
Ann., Tit. 17–A, §207(1)(A) (2006). The question presented is
whether a prior conviction under §207 has, as anelement, the “use
of physical force,” such that the conviction can strip someone of
his right to possess a firearm. In my view, §207 does not qualify
as such an offense, and the majority errs in holding otherwise. I
respectfully dissent.
I
To qualify as a “ ‘misdemeanor crime of
domestic violence,’ ” the Maine assault statute must have as
an element the “use of physical force.” §921(a)(33)(A)(ii). Because
mere recklessness is sufficient to sustain a conviction under §207,
a conviction does not necessarily involve the “use” of physical
force, and thus, does not trigger §922(g)(9)’s prohibition on
firearm possession.
A
Three features of §921(a)(33)(A)(ii) establish
that the “use of physical force” requires intentional conduct.
First, the word “use” in that provision is best read to require
intentional conduct. As the majority recognizes, the noun “use”
means “the ‘act of employing’ something.”
Ante, at 5
(quoting dictionaries). A “use” is “[t]he act of employing a thing
for any . . . purpose.” 19 Oxford English Dictionary 350
(2d ed. 1989). To “use” something, in other words, is to employ the
thing for its instrumental value,
i.e., to employ the thing
to accomplish a further goal. See
United States v.
Castleman, 572 U. S. ___, ___ (2014) (slip op., at 13).
A “use,” therefore, is an inherently intentional act—that is, an
act done for the purpose of causing certain consequences or at
least with knowledge that those consequences will ensue. See
Restatement (Second) of Torts §8A, p. 15 (1965) (defining
intentional acts).
We have routinely defined “use” in ways that
make clear that the conduct must be intentional. In
Bailey
v.
United States, 516 U. S. 137 (1995) , for example,
we held that the phrase “[use of] a firearm” required “active
employment” of the firearm, such as “brandishing, displaying,
bartering, striking with, and, most obviously, firing or attempting
to fire a firearm.”
Id., at 143, 148 (emphasis deleted). We
have similarly held that the use of force requires more than
“negligent or merely accidental conduct.”
Leocal v.
Ashcroft, 543 U. S. 1, 9 (2004) . We concluded that
“[w]hile one may, in theory, actively employ
something in an
accidental manner, it is much less natural to say that a person
actively employs physical force against another person by
accident.”
Ibid. Thus, shooting a gun would be using a
firearm in relation to a crime.
Bailey,
supra, at
148. Recklessly leaving a loaded gun in one’s trunk, which then
discharges after being jostled during the car ride, would not. The
person who placed that gun in the trunk might have acted recklessly
or negligently, but he did not actively employ the gun in a
crime.
Second, especially in a legal context, “force”
generally connotes the use of violence against another. Black’s Law
Dictionary, for example, defines “force” to mean “[p]ower,
violence, or pressure directed against a person or thing.” Black’s
Law Dictionary 656 (7th ed. 1999). Other dictionaries offer similar
definitions.
E.g., Random House Dictionary of the English
Language 748 (def. 5) (2d ed. 1987) (“force,” when used in law,
means “unlawful violence threatened or committed against persons or
property”); 6 Oxford English Dictionary 34 (def. I(5)(c))
(“Unlawful violence offered to persons or things”). And “violence,”
when used in a legal context, also implies an intentional act. See
Black’s Law Dictionary 1564 (“violence” is the “[u]njust or
unwarranted use of force, usu. accompanied by fury, vehemence, or
outrage; physical force unlawfully exercised with the intent to
harm”).[
1] When a person talks
about “using force” against another, one thinks of intentional
acts—punching, kicking, shoving, or using a weapon. Conversely, one
would not naturally call a car acci-dent a “use of force,” even if
people were injured by the force of the accident. As Justice Holmes
observed, “[E]ven a dog distinguishes between being stumbled over
and being kicked.” O. Holmes, The Common Law 3 (1881).
Third, context confirms that “use of physical
force” connotes an intentional act. Section 921(a)(33)(A)(ii)’s
prohibitions also include “the threatened use of a deadly weapon.”
In that neighboring prohibition, “use” most naturally means active
employment of the weapon. And it would be odd to say that “use” in
that provision refers to active employment (an intentional act)
when threatening someone with a weapon, but “use” here is satisfied
by merely reckless conduct. See
Sorenson v.
Secretary of
Treasury, 475 U. S. 851, 860 (1986) (the same words in a
statute presumptively have the same meaning). Thus, the “use of
physical force” against a family member refers to intentional acts
of violence against a family member.
B
On this interpretation, Maine’s assault
statute likely does not qualify as a “misdemeanor crime of domestic
violence” and thus does not trigger the prohibition on possessing
firearms, §922(g)(9). The Maine statute appears to lack, as a
required element, the “use or attempted use of physical force.”
Maine’s statute punishes at least some conduct that does not
involve the “use of physical force.” Section 207 criminalizes
“recklessly caus[ing] bodily injury or offensive physical contact
to another person.” By criminalizing all reckless conduct, the
Maine statute captures conduct such as recklessly injuring a
passenger by texting while driving resulting in a crash.
Petitioners’ charging documents generically recited the statutory
language; they did not charge intentional, knowing, and reckless
harm as alternative counts. Accordingly, Maine’s statute appears to
treat “intentionally, knowingly, or recklessly” causing bodily
injury or an offensive touching as a single, indivisible offense
that is satisfied by recklessness. See
Mathis v.
United
States, ante, at 14–15. So petitioners’ prior assault
convictions do not necessarily have as an element the use of
physical force against a family member. These prior convictions,
therefore, do not qualify as a misdemeanor crime involving domestic
violence under federal law, and petitioners’ convictions
accordingly should be reversed. At the very least, to the extent
there remains uncertainty over whether Maine’s assault statute is
divisible, the Court should vacate and remand for the First Circuit
to determine that statutory interpretation question in the first
instance.
II
To illustrate where I part ways with the
majority, consider different mental states with which a person
could create and apply force.[
2] First, a person can create force intentionally or
recklessly.[
3] For example, a
person can intentionally throw a punch or a person can crash his
car by driving recklessly. Second, a person can intentionally or
recklessly harm a particular person or object as a result of that
force. For example, a person could throw a punch at a particular
person (thereby intentionally applying force to that person) or a
person could swing a baseball bat too close to someone (thereby
recklessly applying force to that person).
These different mental states give rise to three
relevant categories of conduct. A person might intentionally create
force and intentionally apply that force against an object
(
e.g., punching a punching bag). A person might also
intentionally create force but recklessly apply that force against
an object (
e.g., practicing a kick in the air, but
recklessly hitting a piece of furniture). Or a person could
recklessly create force that results in damage, such as the car
crash example.
The question before us is what mental state
suffices for a “use of physical force” against a family member. In
my view, a “use of physical force” most naturally refers to cases
where a person intentionally creates force and intentionally
applies that force against a family member. It also includes (at
least some) cases where a person intentionally creates force but
recklessly applies it to a family member. But I part ways with the
majority’s conclusion that purely reckless conduct—meaning, where a
person recklessly creates force—constitutes a “use of physical
force.” In my view, it does not, and therefore, the “use of
physical force” is narrower than most state assault statutes, which
punish anyone who recklessly causes physical injury.
A
To identify the scope of the “use of physical
force,” consider three different types of intentional and reckless
force resulting in physical injury.
1
The paradigmatic case of battery: A person
intentionally unleashes force and intends that the force will harm
a particular person. This might include, for example, punching or
kicking someone. Both the majority and I agree that these cases
constitute a “use of physical force” under §921(a)(33)(A)(ii).
This first category includes all cases where a
person intentionally creates force and desires or knows with a
practical certainty that that force will cause harm. This is
because the law traditionally treats conduct as intended in two
circumstances. First, conduct is intentional when the actor desires
to produce a specific result. 1 W. LaFave, Substantive Criminal Law
§5.2(a), pp. 340–342 (2d ed. 2003). But conduct is also
traditionally deemed inten-tional when a person acts “knowingly”:
that is, he knows with practical certainty that a result will
follow from his conduct.
Ibid.; see also Restatement
(Second) of Torts §8A, Comment
b, at 15 (“If the actor knows
that the consequences are certain, or substantially certain, to
result from his act, and still goes ahead, he is treated by the law
as if he had in fact desired to produce the result”).
To illustrate, suppose a person strikes his
friend for the purpose of demonstrating a karate move. The person
has no desire to injure his friend, but he knows that the move is
so dangerous that he is practically certain his friend will be
injured. Under the common law, the person intended to injure his
friend, even though he acted only with knowledge that his friend
would be injured rather than the desire to harm him. Thus, even
when a person acts knowingly rather than purposefully, this type of
conduct is still a “use of physical force.”
2
The second category involves a person who
intentionally unleashes force that recklessly causes injury. The
major-ity gives two examples:
1. The Angry Plate Thrower: “[A] person throws
a plate in anger against the wall near where his wife is standing.”
Ante, at 6. The plate shatters, and a shard injures her.
Ibid.
2. The Door Slammer: “[A person] slams the door
shut with his girlfriend following close behind” with the effect of
“catch[ing] her fingers in the jamb.”
Ibid.
The Angry Plate Thrower and the Door Slammer
both intentionally unleashed physical force, but they did not
intend to direct that force at those whom they harmed. Thus, they
intentionally employed force, but
recklessly caused
physical injury with that force. The majority believes that these
cases also constitute a “use of physical force,” and I agree. The
Angry Plate Thrower has used force against the plate, and the Door
Slammer has used force against the door.
The more difficult question is whether this “use
of physical force” comes within §921(a)(33)(A)(ii), which requires
that the “use of physical force” be committed by someone having a
familial relationship with the victim. The natural reading of that
provision is that the use of physical force must be against a
family member. In some cases, the law readily transfers the intent
to use force from the object to the actual victim. Take the Angry
Plate Thrower: If a husband throws a plate at the wall near his
wife to scare her, that is assault. If the plate breaks and cuts
her, it becomes a battery, regardless of whether he intended the
plate to make contact with her person. See W. Keeton, D. Dobbs, R.
Keeton, & D. Owens, Prosser and Keeton on Law of Torts §9, pp.
39–42 (5th ed. 1984) (Prosser and Keeton). Similarly, “if one
person intends to harm a second person but instead unintentionally
harms a third, the first person’s criminal or tortious intent
toward the second applies to the third as well.” Black’s Law
Dictionary 1504 (defining transferred-intent doctrine); see also 1
LaFave,
supra, §5.2(c)(4), at 349–350. Thus, where a person
acts in a violent and patently unjustified manner, the law will
often impute that the actor intended to cause the injury resulting
from his conduct, even if he actually intended to direct his use of
force elsewhere. Because we presume that Congress legislates
against the backdrop of the common law, see
Astoria Fed. Sav.
& Loan Assn. v.
Solimino, 501 U. S. 104, 108
(1991) , these cases would qualify as the “use of physical force”
against a family member.[
4]
3
Finally, and most problematic for the
majority’s approach, a person could recklessly unleash force that
recklessly causes injury. Consider two examples:
1. The Text-Messaging Dad: Knowing that he
should not be texting and driving, a father sends a text message to
his wife. The distraction causes the father to rear end the car in
front of him. His son, who is a passenger, is injured.
2. The Reckless Policeman: A police officer
speeds to a crime scene without activating his emergency lights and
siren and careens into another car in an intersection. That
accident causes the police officer’s car to strike another police
officer, who was standing at the intersection. See
Seaton v.
State, 385 S. W. 3d 85, 88 (Tex. App. 2012).
In these cases, both the unleashing of the
“force” (the car crash) and the resulting harm (the physical
injury) were reckless. Under the majority’s reading of
§921(a)(33)(A)(ii), the husband “use[d] . . . physical
force” against his son, and the police officer “use[d]
. . . physical force” against the other officer.
But this category is where the majority and I
part company. These examples do not involve the “use of physical
force” under any conventional understanding of “use” because they
do not involve an active employment of something for a particular
purpose. See
supra, at 2–3. In the second category, the
actors intentionally use violence against property; this is why the
majority can plausibly argue that they have “used” force, even
though that force was not intended to harm their family members.
See
supra, at 8–9 (discussing transferred intent). But when
an individual does not engage in any violence against persons or
property—that is, when physical injuries result from purely
reckless conduct—there is no “use” of physical force.
* * *
The “use of physical force” against a family
member includes cases where a person intentionally commits a
violent act against a family member. And the term includes at least
some cases where a person engages in a violent act that results in
an unintended injury to a family member. But the term does not
include nonviolent, reckless acts that cause physical injury or an
offensive touching. Accordingly, the majority’s definition is
overbroad.
B
In reaching its contrary conclusion, the
majority con-fuses various concepts. First, and as discussed, the
majority decides that a person who acts recklessly has used
physical force against another.
Ante, at 6–8. But that fails
to appreciate the distinction between intentional and reckless
conduct. A “use” of physical force requires the intent to cause
harm, and the law will impute that intent where the actor knows
with a practical certainty that it will cause harm. But the law
will not impute that intent from merely reckless conduct. Second,
and perhaps to rein in its overly broad conception of a use of
force, the majority concludes that only “volitional” acts
constitute uses of force,
ante, at 6, and that mere
“accident[s]” do not,
ante, at 7. These portions of the
majority’s analysis conflate “volitional” conduct with
“intentional”
mens rea and misapprehends the relevant
meaning of an “accident.”
1
The majority blurs the distinction between
recklessness and intentional wrongdoing by overlooking the
difference between the
mens rea for force and the
mens
rea for causing harm with that force. The majority says that
“ ‘use’ does not demand that the person applying force have
the purpose or practical certainty that it will cause harm”
(namely, knowledge), “as compared with the understanding that it is
[a substantial and unjustifiable risk that it will] do so” (the
standard for recklessness).[
5]
Ante, at 6. Put in the language of
mens rea, the
majority is saying that purposeful, knowing, and reckless
applications of force are all equally “uses” of force.
But the majority fails to explain why mere
recklessness in creating force—as opposed to recklessness in
causing harm with intentional force—is sufficient. The majority
gives the Angry Plate Thrower and the Door Slammer as examples of
reckless conduct that are “uses” of physical force, but those
examples involve persons who
intentionally use force that
recklessly causes injuries.
Ibid. Reckless assault,
however, extends well beyond intentional force that recklessly
causes injury. In States where the Model Penal Code has influence,
reckless assault includes any recklessly caused physical injury.
See ALI, Model Penal Code §211.1(1)(a) (1980). This means that the
Reckless Policeman and the Text-Messaging Dad are as guilty of
assault as the Angry Plate Thrower. See,
e.g., Seaton, 385
S. W. 3d, at 89–90; see also
People v.
Grenier, 250 App. Div. 2d 874, 874–875, 672
N. Y. S. 2d 499, 500–501 (1998) (upholding an assault
conviction where a drunk driver injured his passengers in a car
accident).
The majority’s examples are only those in which
a person has intentionally used force, meaning that the person acts
with purpose or knowledge that force is involved.
Ante, at
6. As a result, the majority overlooks the critical distinction
between conduct that is intended to cause harm and conduct that is
not intended to cause harm. Violently throwing a plate against a
wall is a use of force. Speeding on a roadway is not. That reflects
the fundamental difference between intentional and reckless
wrongdoing. An intentional wrong is designed to inflict harm. See
Restatement (Second) of Torts §8A, at 15. A reckless wrong is not:
“While an act to be reckless must be intended by the actor, the
actor does not intend to cause the harm which results from it.”
Id., §500, Comment
f, at 590.
All that remains of the majority’s analysis is
its unsupported conclusion that recklessness looks enough like
knowledge, so that the former suffices for a use of force just as
the latter does.
Ante, at 6. That overlooks a crucial
distinction between a “practical certainty” and a substantial risk.
When a person acts with practical certainty, he intentionally
produces a result. As explained above,
supra, at 7, when a
person acts with knowledge that certain consequences will result,
the law imputes to that person the intent to cause those
consequences. And the requirement of a “practical” certainty
reflects that, in ordinary life, people rarely have perfect
certitude of the facts that they “know.” But as the probability
decreases, “the actor’s conduct loses the character of intent, and
becomes mere recklessness.” Restatement (Second) of Torts §8A,
Comment
b, at 15. And the distinction between intentional
and reckless conduct is key for defining “use.” When a person acts
with a practical certainty that he will employ force, he intends to
cause harm; he has actively employed force for an instrumental
purpose, and that is why we can fairly say he “uses” force. In the
case of reckless wrong-doing, however, the injury the actor has
caused is just an accidental byproduct of inappropriately risky
behavior; he has not actively employed force.
In sum, “use” requires the intent to employ the
thing being used. And in law, that intent will be imputed when a
person acts with practical certainty that he will actively employ
that thing. Merely disregarding a risk that a harm will result,
however, does not supply the requisite intent.
2
To limit its definition of “use,” the majority
adds two additional requirements. The conduct must be
“voli-tional,” and it cannot be merely “accident[al].”
Ante,
at 5–7. These additional requirements will cause confusion, and
neither will limit the breadth of the majority’s adopted
understanding of a “use of physical force.”
First, the majority requires that the use of
force must be “volitional,” so that “an involuntary motion, even a
powerful one, is not naturally described as an active employment of
force.”
Ante, at 5–6. The majority provides two
examples:
1. The Soapy-Handed Husband: “[A] person with
soapy hands loses his grip on a plate, which then shatters and cuts
his wife.”
Ante, at 6.
2. The Chivalrous Door Holder: “[A] person lets
slip a door that he is trying to hold open for his girlfriend.”
Ibid.
In the majority’s view, a husband who loses his
grip on a plate or a boyfriend who lets the door slip has not
engaged in a volitional act creating force.
Ibid. The
majority distinguishes this “volitional” act requirement from the
“mental state of intention, knowledge, or recklessness with respect
to the harmful consequences of his volitional conduct.”
Ibid. The Angry Plate Thrower—unlike the Soapy-Handed
Husband or Chivalrous Door Holder—has engaged in a volitional act,
even if he did not intend to hurl the plate at his wife.
Ibid.
The majority’s use of “volitional” is
inconsistent with its traditional legal definition. The husband who
drops a dish on his wife’s foot and the boyfriend who loses his
grip while holding the door have acted volitionally. “[A]n ‘act,’
as that term is ordinarily used, is a voluntary contraction of the
muscles, and nothing more.” Prosser and Keeton §8, at 34; see also
Model Penal Code §2.01 (defining the voluntary act requirement).
For the plate and door examples not to be volitional acts, they
would need to be unwilled muscular movements, such as a person who
drops the plate because of a seizure.
In calling the force in these cases
nonvolitional, the majority has confounded the minimum
mens
rea generally necessary to trigger criminal liability
(recklessness) with the requirement that a person perform a
volitional act. Although all involuntary actions are blameless, not
all blameless conduct is involuntary.
What the majority means to say is that the men
did not
intentionally employ force, a requirement materially
different from a volitional act. And this requirement poses a
dilemma for the majority. Recklessly unleashing a force that
recklessly causes physical injury—for example, a police officer
speeding through the intersection without triggering his lights and
siren—is an assault in States that follow the Model Penal Code. See
supra, at 9. If the majority’s rule is to include
all
reckless assault, then the majority must accept that the
Text-Messaging Dad is as guilty of using force against his son as
the husband who angrily throws a plate toward his wife—an
implausible result. Alternatively, the majority must acknowledge
that its “volitional” act requirement is actually a requirement
that the use of force be intentional, even if that intentional act
of violence results in a recklessly caused, but unintended, injury.
The majority, of course, refuses to do so because that approach
would remove many assault convictions, especially in the many
States that have adopted the Model Penal Code, from the sweep of
the federal statute. Thus, the majority is left misapplying basic
principles of criminal law to rationalize why all “assault” under
the Model Penal Code constitutes the “use of physical force” under
§921(a)(33)(A)(ii).
Second and relatedly, the majority asserts that
a use of force cannot be merely accidental. But this gloss on what
constitutes a use of force provides no further clarity. The
majority’s attempt to distinguish “recklessness” from an
“accident,”
ante, at 7, is an equivocation on the meaning of
“accident.” An accident can mean that someone was blameless—for
example, a driver who accidentally strikes a deer that darts into a
roadway. But an accident can also refer to the fact that the result
was unintended: A car accident is no less an “accident” just
because a driver acted negligently or recklessly. Neither labeling
an act “volitional” nor labeling it a mere “accident” will rein in
the majority’s overly broad understanding of a “use of physical
force.”
* * *
If Congress wanted to sweep in all reckless
conduct, it could have written §921(a)(33)(A)(ii) in different
language. Congress might have prohibited the possession of firearms
by anyone convicted under a state law prohibiting assault or
battery. Congress could also have used language tracking the Model
Penal Code by saying that a conviction must have, as an element,
“the intentional, knowing, or reckless causation of physical
injury.” But Congress instead defined a “misdemeanor crime of
domestic violence” by requiring that the offense have “the use of
physical force.” And a “use of physical force” has a
well-understood meaning applying only to intentional acts designed
to cause harm.
III
Even assuming any doubt remains over the
reading of “use of physical force,” the majority errs by reading
the statute in a way that creates serious constitutional problems.
The doctrine of constitutional avoidance “command[s] courts, when
faced with two plausible constructions of a statute—one
constitutional and the other unconstitutional—to choose the
constitutional reading.”
Northwest Austin Municipal Util. Dist.
No. One v.
Holder, 557 U. S. 193, 213 (2009)
(Thomas, J., concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part)
(internal quotation marks omitted). Section 922(g)(9) is already
very broad. It imposes a lifetime ban on gun ownership for a single
intentional nonconsensual touching of a family member. A mother who
slaps her 18-year-old son for talking back to her—an intentional
use of force—could lose her right to bear arms forever if she is
cited by the police under a local ordinance. The majority seeks to
expand that already broad rule to any reckless physical injury or
nonconsensual touch. I would not extend the statute into that
constitutionally problematic territory.
The Second Amendment protects “the right of the
people to keep and bear Arms.” In
District of Columbia v.
Heller, 554 U. S. 570, 624, 627, 635 (2008) , the Court
held that the Amendment protects the right of all law-abiding
citizens to keep and bear arms that are in common use for
traditionally lawful purposes, including self-defense. And in
McDonald v.
Chicago, 561 U. S. 742 (2010) , the
Court held that the right to keep and bear arms is a fundamental
right. See
id., at 767–778;
id., at 806 (Thomas, J.,
concurring in part and concurring in judgment).
The protections enumerated in the Second
Amendment, no less than those enumerated in the First, are not
absolute prohibitions against government regulation.
Heller,
554 U. S., at 595, 626–627. Traditionally, States have imposed
narrow limitations on an individual’s exercise of his right to keep
and bear arms, such as prohibiting the carrying of weapons in a
concealed manner or in sensitive locations, such as government
buildings.
Id., at 626–627; see,
e.g., State v.
Kerner, 181 N. C. 574, 578–579, 107 S. E. 222, 225
(1921). But these narrow restrictions neither prohibit nor broadly
frustrate any individual from gener-ally exercising his right to
bear arms.
Some laws, however, broadly divest an individual
of his Second Amendment rights.
Heller approved, in dicta,
laws that prohibit dangerous persons, including felons and the
mentally ill, from having arms. 554 U. S.
, at 626.
These laws are not narrow restrictions on the right because they
prohibit certain individuals from exercising their Second Amendment
rights at all times and in all places. To be constitutional,
therefore, a law that broadly frustrates an individual’s right to
keep and bear arms must target individuals who are beyond the scope
of the “People” protected by the Second Amendment.
Section 922(g)(9) does far more than “close [a]
dangerous loophole” by prohibiting individuals who had committed
felony domestic violence from possessing guns simply because they
pleaded guilty to misdemeanors.
Ante, at 1 (internal
quotation marks omitted). It imposes a lifetime ban on possessing a
gun for
all nonfelony domestic of-fenses, including
so-called infractions or summary offenses. §§921(a)(33)(A)(ii),
922(g)(9); 27 CFR §478.11 (2015) (defining a misdemeanor crime of
domestic violence to include crimes punishable only by a fine).
These infractions, like traffic tickets, are so minor that
individuals do not have a right to trial by jury. See
Lewis
v.
United States, 518 U. S. 322 –326 (1996).
Today the majority expands §922(g)(9)’s sweep
into patently unconstitutional territory. Under the majority’s
reading, a single conviction under a state assault statute for
recklessly causing an injury to a family member—such as by texting
while driving—can now trigger a lifetime ban on gun ownership. And
while it may be true that such incidents are rarely prosecuted,
this decision leaves the right to keep and bear arms up to the
discretion of federal, state, and local prosecutors.
We treat no other constitutional right so
cavalierly. At oral argument the Government could not identify any
other fundamental constitutional right that a person could lose
forever by a single conviction for an infraction punishable only by
a fine. Tr. of Oral Arg. 36–40. Compare the First Amendment. Plenty
of States still criminalize libel. See,
e.g., Ala. Code.
§13A–11–160 (2015); Fla. Stat. §836.01 (2015); La. Rev. Stat. Ann.
§14:47 (West 2016); Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 94, §98C (2014); Minn.
Stat. §609.765 (2014); N. H. Rev. Stat. Ann. §644:11 (2007);
Va. Code Ann. §18.2–209 (2014); Wis. Stat. §942.01 (2005). I have
little doubt that the majority would strike down an absolute ban on
publishing by a person previously con-victed of misdemeanor libel.
In construing the statute before us expansively so that causing a
single minor reckless injury or offensive touching can lead someone
to lose his right to bear arms forever, the Court continues to
“relegat[e] the Second Amendment to a second-class right.”
Friedman v.
Highland Park, 577 U. S. ___, ___
(2015) (Thomas, J., dissenting from denial of certiorari) (slip
op., at 6).
* * *
In enacting §922(g)(9), Congress was not
worried about a husband dropping a plate on his wife’s foot or a
parent injuring her child by texting while driving. Congress was
worried that family members were abusing other family members
through acts of violence and keeping their guns by pleading down to
misdemeanors. Prohibiting those convicted of intentional and
knowing batteries from possessing guns—but not those convicted of
reckless batteries—amply carries out Congress’ objective.
Instead, under the majority’s approach, a parent
who has a car accident because he sent a text message while driving
can lose his right to bear arms forever if his wife or child
suffers the slightest injury from the crash. This is obviously not
the correct reading of §922(g)(9). The “use of physical force” does
not include crimes involving purely reckless conduct. Because
Maine’s statute punishes such conduct, it sweeps more broadly than
the “use of physical force.” I respectfully dissent.