SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 13–7120
_________________
SAMUEL JAMES JOHNSON, PETITIONER
v.
UNITED STATES
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the eighth circuit
[June 26, 2015]
Justice Thomas, concurring in the
judgment.
I agree with the Court that Johnson’s sentence
cannot stand. But rather than use the Fifth Amendment’s Due Process
Clause to nullify an Act of Congress, I would resolve this case on
more ordinary grounds. Under conventional principles of
interpretation and our precedents, the offense of unlawfully
possessing a short-barreled shotgun does not constitute a “violent
felony” under the residual clause of the Armed Career Criminal Act
(ACCA).
The majority wants more. Not content to engage
in the usual business of interpreting statutes, it holds this
clause to be unconstitutionally vague, notwithstanding the fact
that on four previous occasions we found it determinate enough for
judicial application. As Justice Alito explains, that decision
cannot be reconciled with our precedents concerning the vagueness
doctrine. See
post, at 13–17 (dissenting opinion). But even
if it were a closer case under those decisions, I would be wary of
holding the residual clause to be unconstitutionally vague.
Although I have joined the Court in applying our modern vagueness
doctrine in the past, see
FCC v.
Fox Television Stations,
Inc., 567 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2012) (slip op., at 16–17),
I have become increasingly concerned about its origins and
application. Simply put, our vagueness doctrine shares an
uncomfortably similar history with substantive due process, a
judicially created doctrine lacking any basis in the
Constitution.
I
We could have easily disposed of this case
without nullifying ACCA’s residual clause. Under ordinary
principles of statutory interpretation, the crime of unlawfully
possessing a short-barreled shotgun does not constitute a “violent
felony” under ACCA. In relevant part, that Act defines a “violent
felony” as a “crime punishable by imprisonment for a term exceeding
one year” that either
“(i) has as an element the use, attempted use,
or threatened use of physical force against the person of another;
or
“(ii) is burglary, arson, or extortion, involves
use of explosives, or otherwise involves conduct that presents a
serious potential risk of physical injury to another.” 18
U. S. C. §924(e)(2)(B).
The offense of unlawfully possessing a
short-barreled shotgun neither satisfies the first clause of this
definition nor falls within the enumerated offenses in the second.
It therefore can constitute a violent felony only if it falls
within ACCA’s so-called “residual clause”—
i.e., if it
“involves conduct that presents a serious potential risk of
physical injury to another.” §924(e)(2)(B)(ii).
To determine whether an offense falls within the
residual clause, we consider “whether the conduct encompassed by
the elements of the offense, in the ordinary case, presents a
serious potential risk of injury to another.”
James v.
United States, 550 U. S. 192, 208 (2007) . The specific
crimes listed in §924(e)(2)(B)(ii)—arson, extortion, bur-glary, and
an offense involving the use of explosives—offer a “baseline
against which to measure the degree of risk” a crime must present
to fall within that clause.
Id., at 208
. Those
offenses do not provide a high threshold, see
id., at 203,
207–208, but the crime in question must still present a
“ ‘serious’ ”—a “ ‘significant’ or
‘important’ ”—risk of physical injury to be deemed a violent
felony,
Begay v.
United States, 553 U. S. 137,
156 (2008) (Alito, J., dissenting); accord,
Chambers v.
United States, 555 U. S. 122, 128 (2009) .
To qualify as serious, the risk of injury
generally must be closely related to the offense itself. Our
precedents provide useful examples of the close relationship that
must exist between the conduct of the offense and the risk
presented. In
Sykes v.
United States, 564 U. S.
1 (2011) , for instance, we held that the offense of intentional
vehicular flight constitutes a violent felony because that conduct
always triggers a dangerous confrontation,
id., at ___ (slip
op., at 8). As we explained, vehicular flights “by definitional
necessity occur when police are present” and are done “in defiance
of their instructions . . . with a vehicle that can be
used in a way to cause serious potential risk of physical injury to
another.”
Ibid. In
James, we likewise held that
attempted burglary offenses “requir[ing] an overt act directed
toward the entry of a structure” are violent felonies because the
underlying conduct often results in a dangerous confrontation. 550
U. S., at 204, 206. But we distinguished those crimes from
“the more attenuated conduct encompassed by” attempt offenses “that
c[an] be satisfied by preparatory conduct that does not pose the
same risk of violent confrontation,” such as “ ‘possessing
burglary tools.’ ”
Id., at 205, 206, and n. 4. At
some point, in other words, the risk of injury from the crime may
be too attenuated for the conviction to fall within the residual
clause, such as when an additional, voluntary act (
e.g., the
use of burglary tools to enter a structure) is necessary to
bring about the risk of physical injury to another.
In light of the elements of and reported
convictions for the unlawful possession of a short-barreled
shotgun, this crime does not “involv[e] conduct that presents a
serious potential risk of physical injury to another,”
§924(e)(2)(B)(ii). The acts that form the basis of this offense are
simply too remote from a risk of physical injury to fall within the
residual clause.
Standing alone, the elements of this offense—(1)
unlawfully (2) possessing (3) a short-barreled shotgun—do not
describe inherently dangerous conduct. As a conceptual matter,
“simple possession [of a firearm], even by a felon, takes place in
a variety of ways (
e.g., in a closet, in a storeroom, in a
car, in a pocket) many, perhaps most, of which do not involve
likely accompanying violence.”
United States v.
Doe,
960 F. 2d 221, 225 (CA1 1992). These weapons also can be
stored in a manner posing a danger to no one, such as unloaded,
disassembled, or locked away. By themselves, the elements of this
offense indicate that the ordinary commission of this crime is far
less risky than ACCA’s enumerated offenses.
Reported convictions support the conclusion that
mere possession of a short-barreled shotgun does not, in the
ordinary case, pose a serious risk of injury to others. A few
examples suffice. In one case, officers found the sawed-off shotgun
locked inside a gun cabinet in an empty home.
State v.
Salyers, 858 N. W. 2d 156, 157–158 (Minn. 2015). In another,
the firearm was retrieved from the trunk of the defendant’s car.
State v.
Ellenberger, 543 N. W. 2d 673, 674 (Minn.
App. 1996). In still another, the weapon was found missing a firing
pin.
State v.
Johnson, 171 Wis. 2d 175, 178, 491
N. W. 2d 110, 111 (App. 1992). In these instances and others,
the offense threatened no one.
The Government’s theory for why this crime
should nonetheless qualify as a “violent felony” is unpersuasive.
Although it does not dispute that the unlawful possession of a
short-barreled shotgun can occur in a nondangerous manner, the
Government contends that this offense poses a serious risk of
physical injury due to the connection between short-barreled
shotguns and other serious crimes. As the Government explains,
these firearms are “weapons not typically possessed by law-abiding
citizens for lawful purposes,”
District of Columbia v.
Heller, 554 U. S. 570, 625 (2008) , but are instead
primarily intended for use in criminal activity. In light of that
intended use, the Government reasons that the ordinary case of this
possession offense will involve the
use of a short-barreled
shotgun in a serious crime, a scenario obviously posing a serious
risk of physical injury.
But even assuming that those who unlawfully
possess these weapons typically intend to use them in a serious
crime, the risk that the Government identifies arises not from the
act of possessing the weapon, but from the act of using it. Unlike
attempted burglary (at least of the type at issue in
James)
or intentional vehicular flight—conduct that by itself often or
always invites a dangerous confrontation—possession of a
short-barreled shotgun poses a threat
only when an offender
decides to engage in additional, voluntary conduct that is not
included in the elements of the crime. Until this weapon is
assembled, loaded, or used, for example, it poses no risk of injury
to others in and of itself. The risk of injury to others from mere
possession of this firearm is too attenuated to treat this offense
as a violent felony. I would reverse the Court of Appeals on that
basis.
II
As the foregoing analysis demonstrates, ACCA’s
resid-ual clause can be applied in a principled manner. One would
have thought this proposition well established given that we have
already decided four cases addressing this clause. The majority
nonetheless concludes that the operation of this provision violates
the Fifth Amendment’s Due Process Clause.
Justice Alito shows why that analysis is wrong
under our precedents. See
post, at 13–17 (dissenting
opinion). But I have some concerns about our modern vagueness
doctrine itself. Whether that doctrine is defensible under the
original meaning of “due process of law” is a difficult question I
leave for the another day, but the doctrine’s history should prompt
us at least to examine its constitutional underpinnings more
closely before we use it to nullify yet another duly enacted
law.
A
We have become accustomed to using the Due
Process Clauses to invalidate laws on the ground of “vagueness.”
The doctrine we have developed is quite sweeping: “A statute can be
impermissibly vague . . . if it fails to provide people
of ordinary intelligence a reasonable opportunity to understand
what conduct it prohibits” or “if it authorizes or even encourages
arbitrary and discriminatory enforcement.”
Hill v.
Colorado, 530 U. S. 703, 732 (2000) . Using this
framework, we have nullified a wide range of enactments. We have
struck down laws ranging from city ordinances,
Papachristou
v.
Jacksonville, 405 U. S. 156 –171 (1972), to Acts of
Congress,
United States v.
L. Cohen Grocery Co., 255
U. S. 81 –93 (1921). We have struck down laws whether they are
penal,
Lanzetta v.
New Jersey, 306 U. S. 451,
452, 458 (1939) , or not,
Keyishian v.
Board of Regents
of Univ. of State of N. Y., 385 U. S. 589 –604
(1967).[
1] We have struck down
laws addressing subjects ranging from abortion,
Colautti v.
Franklin, 439 U. S. 379, 390 (1979) , and obscenity,
Winters v.
New York, 333 U. S. 507 –520 (1948),
to the minimum wage,
Connally v.
General Constr. Co.,
269 U. S. 385 –395 (1926), and antitrust,
Cline v.
Frink Dairy Co., 274 U. S. 445 –465 (1927). We have
even struck down a law using a term that has been used to describe
criminal conduct in this country since before the Constitution was
ratified.
Chicago v.
Morales, 527 U. S. 41, 51
(1999) (invalidating a “loitering” law); see
id., at 113,
and n. 10 (Thomas, J., dissenting) (discussing a 1764 Georgia law
requiring the apprehension of “all able bodied persons
. . . who shall be found loitering”).
That we have repeatedly used a doctrine to
invalidate laws does not make it legitimate. Cf.,
e.g., Dred
Scott v.
Sandford, 19 How. 393, 450–452 (1857) (stating
that an Act of Congress prohibiting slavery in certain Federal
Territories violated the substantive due process rights of
slaveowners and was therefore void). This Court has a history of
wielding doctrines purportedly rooted in “due process of law” to
achieve its own policy goals, substantive due process being the
poster child. See
McDonald v.
Chicago, 561 U. S.
742, 811 (2010) (Thomas, J., concurring in part and concurring in
judgment) (“The one theme that links the Court’s substantive due
process precedents together is their lack of a guiding principle to
distinguish ‘fundamental’ rights that warrant protection from
nonfundamental rights that do not”). Although our vagueness
doctrine is distinct from substantive due process, their histories
have disquieting parallels.
1
The problem of vague penal statutes is nothing
new. The notion that such laws may be void under the Constitution’s
Due Process Clauses, however, is a more recent development.
Before the end of the 19th century, courts
addressed vagueness through a rule of strict construction of penal
statutes, not a rule of constitutional law. This rule of
construction—better known today as the rule of lenity—first emerged
in 16th-century England in reaction to Parliament’s practice of
making large swaths of crimes capital offenses, though it did not
gain broad acceptance until the following century. See Hall, Strict
or Liberal Construction of Penal Statutes, 48 Harv. L. Rev.
748, 749–751 (1935); see also 1 L. Radzinowicz, A History of
English Criminal Law and Its Administration From 1750, pp. 10–11
(1948) (noting that some of the following crimes triggered the
death penalty: “marking the edges of any current coin of the
kingdom,” “maliciously cutting any hop-binds growing on poles in
any plantation of hops,” and “being in the company of gypsies”).
Courts relied on this rule of construction in refusing to apply
vague capital-offense statutes to prosecutions before them. As an
example of this rule, William Blackstone described a notable
instance in which an English statute imposing the death penalty on
anyone convicted of “stealing sheep,
or other cattle” was
“held to extend to nothing but mere sheep” as “th[e] general words,
‘or other cattle,’ [were] looked upon as much too loose to create a
capital offence.” 1 Commentaries on the Laws of England 88
(1765).[
2]
Vague statutes surfaced on this side of the
Atlantic as well. Shortly after the First Congress proposed the
Bill of Rights, for instance, it passed a law providing “[t]hat
every person who shall attempt to trade with the Indian tribes, or
be found in the Indian country with such merchandise in his
possession as are usually vended to the Indians, without a
license,” must forfeit the offending goods. Act of July 22, 1790,
ch. 33, §3, 1Stat. 137–138. At first glance, punishing the
unlicensed possession of “merchandise . . . usually
vended to the Indians,”
ibid., would seem far more likely to
“invit[e] arbitrary enforcement,”
ante, at 5, than does the
residual clause.
But rather than strike down arguably vague laws
under the Fifth Amendment Due Process Clause, antebellum American
courts—like their English predecessors—simply refused to apply them
in individual cases under the rule that penal statutes should be
construed strictly. See,
e.g., United States v.
Sharp, 27 F. Cas. 1041 (No. 16,264) (CC Pa. 1815)
(Washington, J.). In
Sharp, for instance, several defendants
charged with violating an Act rendering it a capital offense for
“any seaman” to “make a revolt in [a] ship,” Act of Apr. 30, 1790,
§8, 1Stat. 114, objected that “the offence of making a revolt,
[wa]s not sufficiently defined by this law, or by any other
standard, to which reference could be safely made; to warrant the
court in passing a sentence upon [them].” 27 F. Cas., at 1043.
Justice Washington, riding circuit, apparently agreed, observing
that the common definitions for the phrase “make a revolt” were “so
multifarious, and so different” that he could not “avoid feeling a
natural repugnance, to selecting from this mass of definitions,
one, which may fix a crime upon these men, and that too of a
capital nature.”
Ibid. Remarking that “[l]aws which create
crimes, ought to be so explicit in themselves, or by reference to
some other standard, that all men, subject to their penalties, may
know what acts it is their duty to avoid,” he refused to “recommend
to the jury, to find the prisoners guilty of making, or
endeavouring to make a revolt, however strong the evidence may be.”
Ibid.
Such analysis does not mean that federal courts
believed they had the power to invalidate vague penal laws as
unconstitutional. Indeed, there is good evidence that courts at the
time understood judicial review to consist “of a refusal to give a
statute effect as operative law in resolving a case,” a notion
quite distinct from our modern practice of “ ‘strik[ing] down’
legislation.” Walsh, Partial Unconstitutionality, 85 N. Y. U.
L. Rev. 738, 756 (2010). The process of refusing to apply such
laws appeared to occur on a case-by-case basis. For instance,
notwithstanding his doubts expressed in
Sharp, Justice
Washington, writing for this Court, later rejected the argument
that lower courts could arrest a judgment under the same
ship-revolt statute because it “does not define the offence of
endeavouring to make a revolt.”
United States v.
Kelly, 11 Wheat. 417, 418 (1826). The Court explained that
“it is . . . competent to the Court to give a judicial
definition” of “the offence of endeavouring to make a revolt,” and
that such definition “consists in the endeavour of the crew of a
vessel, or any one or more of them, to overthrow the legitimate
authority of her commander, with intent to remove him from his
command, or against his will to take possession of the vessel by
assuming the government and navigation of her, or by transferring
their obedience from the lawful commander to some other person.”
Id., at 418–419. In dealing with statutory indeterminacy,
federal courts saw themselves engaged in construction, not judicial
review as it is now understood. [
3]
2
Although vagueness concerns played a role in
the strict construction of penal statutes from early on, there is
little indication that anyone before the late 19th century believed
that courts had the power under the Due Process Clauses to nullify
statutes on that ground. Instead, our modern vagueness doctrine
materialized after the rise of substantive due process. Following
the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment, corporations began to
use that Amendment’s Due Process Clause to challenge state laws
that attached penalties to unauthorized commercial conduct. In
addition to claiming that these laws violated their substantive due
process rights, these litigants began—with some success—to contend
that such laws were unconstitutionally indefinite. In one case, a
railroad company challenged a Tennessee law authorizing penalties
against any railroad that demanded “more than a just and reasonable
compensation” or engaged in “unjust and unreasonable
discrimination” in setting its rates.
Louisville & Nashville
R. Co. v.
Railroad Comm’n of Tenn., 19 F. 679, 690
(CC MD Tenn. 1884) (internal quotation marks deleted). Without
specifying the constitutional authority for its holding, the
Circuit Court concluded that “[n]o citizen . . . can be
constitutionally subjected to penalties and despoiled of his
property, in a criminal or quasi criminal proceeding, under and by
force of such indefinite legislation.”
Id., at 693 (emphasis
deleted).
Justice Brewer—widely recognized as “a leading
spokesman for ‘substantized’ due process,” Gamer, Justice Brewer
and Substantive Due Process: A Conservative Court Revisited, 18
Vand. L. Rev. 615, 627 (1965)—employed similar reasoning while
riding circuit, though he did not identify the constitutional
source of judicial authority to nullify vague laws. In reviewing an
Iowa law authorizing fines against railroads for charging more than
a “reasonable and just” rate, Justice Brewer mentioned in dictum
that “no penal law can be sustained unless its mandates are so
clearly expressed that any ordinary person can determine in advance
what he may and what he may not do under it.”
Chicago &
N. W. R. Co. v.
Dey, 35 F. 866, 876 (CC SD Iowa
1888).
Constitutional vagueness challenges in this
Court initially met with some resistance. Although the Court
appeared to acknowledge the possibility of unconstitutionally
indefinite enactments, it repeatedly rejected vagueness challenges
to penal laws addressing railroad rates,
Railroad Comm’n
Cases, 116 U. S. 307 –337 (1886), liquor sales,
Ohio
ex rel. Lloyd v.
Dollison, 194 U. S. 445 –451
(1904), and anticompetitive conduct,
Nash v.
United
States, 229 U. S. 373 –378 (1913);
Waters-Pierce Oil
Co. v.
Texas (No. 1), 212 U. S. 86 –111 (1909).
In 1914, however, the Court nullified a law on
vagueness grounds under the Due Process Clause for the first time.
In
International Harvester Co. of America v.
Kentucky, 234 U. S. 216 (1914) , a tobacco company
brought a Fourteenth Amendment challenge against several Kentucky
antitrust laws that had been construed to render unlawful “any
combination [made] . . . for the purpose or with the
effect of fixing a price that was greater or less than the real
value of the article,”
id., at 221. The com-pany argued that
by referring to “real value,” the laws pro-vided “no standard of
conduct that it is possible to know.”
Ibid. The Court
agreed.
Id., at 223–224. Although it did not specify in that
case which portion of the Fourteenth Amendment served as the basis
for its holding,
ibid., it explained in a related case that
the lack of a knowable standard of conduct in the Kentucky statutes
“violated the fundamental principles of justice embraced in the
conception of due process of law.”
Collins v.
Kentucky, 234 U. S. 634, 638 (1914) .
3
Since that time, the Court’s application of
its vagueness doctrine has largely mirrored its application of
substantive due process. During the
Lochner era, a period
marked by the use of substantive due process to strike down
economic regulations,
e.g., Lochner v.
New York, 198
U. S. 45, 57 (1905) , the Court frequently used the vagueness
doctrine to invalidate economic regulations penalizing commercial
activity.[
4] Among the penal
laws it found to be impermissibly vague were a state law regulating
the production of crude oil,
Champlin Refining Co. v.
Corporation Comm’n of Okla., 286 U. S. 210 –243 (1932),
a state antitrust law,
Cline, 274 U. S., at 453–465, a
state minimum-wage law,
Connally, 269 U. S., at
390–395, and a federal price-control statute,
L. Cohen Grocery
Co., 255 U. S., at 89–93.[
5]
Around the time the Court began shifting the
focus of its substantive due process (and equal protection)
jurisprudence from economic interests to “discrete and insular
minorities,” see
United States v.
Carolene Products
Co., 304 U. S. 144 , n. 4 (1938), the target of its
vagueness doctrine changed as well. The Court began to use the
vagueness doctrine to invalidate noneconomic regulations, such as
state statutes penalizing obscenity,
Winters, 333
U. S., at 517–520, and membership in a gang,
Lanzetta,
306 U. S., at 458.
Successful vagueness challenges to regulations
penalizing commercial conduct, by contrast, largely fell by the
wayside. The Court, for instance, upheld a federal regulation
punishing the knowing violation of an order instructing drivers
transporting dangerous chemicals to “ ‘avoid, so far as
practicable . . . driving into or through congested
thoroughfares, places where crowds are assembled, street car
tracks, tunnels, viaducts, and dangerous crossings,’ ”
Boyce Motor Lines, Inc. v.
United States, 342
U. S. 337 , 338–339, 343 (1952). And notwithstanding its
earlier conclusion that an Oklahoma law requiring state employees
and contractors to be paid “ ‘not less than the current rate
of per diem wages in the locality where the work is
performed’ ” was unconstitutionally vague,
Connally,
supra, at 393, the Court found sufficiently definite a federal
law forbidding radio broadcasting companies from attempting to
compel by threat or duress a licensee to hire “ ‘persons in
excess of the number of employees needed by such licensee to
perform actual services,’ ”
United States v.
Petrillo, 332 U. S. 1 –7 (1947).
In more recent times, the Court’s substantive
due process jurisprudence has focused on abortions, and our
vagueness doctrine has played a correspondingly significant role.
In fact, our vagueness doctrine served as the basis for the first
draft of the majority opinion in
Roe v.
Wade, 410
U. S. 113 (1973) , on the theory that laws prohibiting all
abortions save for those done “for the purpose of saving the life
of the mother” forced abortionists to guess when this exception
would apply on penalty of conviction. See B. Schwartz, The
Unpublished Opinions of the Burger Court 116–118 (1988) (reprinting
first draft of
Roe).
Roe, of course, turned out as a
substantive due process opinion. See 410 U. S., at 164. But
since then, the Court has repeatedly deployed the vagueness
doctrine to nullify even mild regulations of the abortion industry.
See
Akron v.
Akron Center for Reproductive Health,
Inc., 462 U. S. 416 –452 (1983) (nullifying law requiring
“ ‘that the remains of the unborn child [be] disposed of in a
humane and sanitary manner’ ”);
Colautti, 439
U. S., at 381 (nullifying law mandating abortionists adhere to
a prescribed standard of care if “ there is ‘sufficient reason
to believe that the fetus may be viable’ ”).[
6]
In one of our most recent decisions nullifying a
law on vagueness grounds, substantive due process was again lurking
in the background. In
Morales, a plurality of this Court
insisted that “the freedom to loiter for innocent purposes is part
of the ‘liberty’ protected by the Due Process Clause of the
Fourteenth Amendment,” 527 U. S., at 53, a conclusion that
colored its analysis that an ordinance prohibiting loitering was
unconstitutionally indeterminate, see
id., at 55 (“When
vagueness permeates the text of” a penal law “infring[ing] on
constitutionally protected rights,” “it is subject to facial
attack”).
I find this history unsettling. It has long been
understood that one of the problems with holding a statute “void
for ‘indefiniteness’ ” is that “ ‘indefiniteness’
. . . is itself an indefinite concept,”
Winters,
supra, at 524 (Frankfurter, J., dissenting), and we as a
Court have a bad habit of using indefinite concepts—especially ones
rooted in “due process”—to invalidate democratically enacted
laws.
B
It is also not clear that our vagueness
doctrine can be reconciled with the original understanding of the
term “due process of law.” Our traditional justification for this
doctrine has been the need for notice: “A conviction fails to
comport with due process if the statute under which it is obtained
fails to provide a person of ordinary intelligence fair notice of
what is prohibited.”
United States v.
Williams, 553
U. S. 285, 304 (2008) ; accord,
ante, at 3. Presumably,
that justification rests on the view expressed in
Murray’s
Lessee v.
Hoboken Land & Improvement Co., 18 How.
272 (1856), that “due process of law” constrains the legislative
branch by guaranteeing “usages and modes of proceeding existing in
the common and statute law of England, before the emigration of our
ancestors, and which are shown not to have been unsuited to their
civil and political condition by having been acted on by them after
the settlement of this country,”
id., at 277. That
justification assumes further that providing “a person of ordinary
intelligence [with] fair notice of what is prohib-ited,”
Williams,
supra, at 304, is one such usage or
mode.[
7]
To accept the vagueness doctrine as founded in
our Constitution, then, one must reject the possibility “that the
Due Process Clause requires only that our Government must proceed
according to the ‘law of the land’—that is, according to written
constitutional and statutory provisions,” which may be all that the
original meaning of this provision demands.
Hamdi v.
Rumsfeld, 542 U. S. 507, 589 (2004) (Thomas, J.,
dissenting) (some internal quotation marks omitted); accord,
Turner v.
Rogers, 564 U. S. ___, ___ (2011)
(Thomas, J., dissenting) (slip op., at 2). Although
Murray’s
Lessee stated the contrary, 18 How., at 276, a number of
scholars and jurists have concluded that “considerable historical
evidence supports the position that ‘due process of law’ was a
separation-of-powers concept designed as a safeguard against
unlicensed executive action, forbidding only deprivations not
authorized by legislation or common law.” D. Currie, The
Constitution in the Supreme Court: The First Hundred Years
1789–1888, p. 272 (1985); see also,
e.g., In re
Winship, 397 U. S. 358 –382 (1970) (Black, J.,
dissenting). Others have disagreed. See,
e.g., Chapman &
McConnell, Due Process as Separation of Powers, 121 Yale L. J.
1672, 1679 (2012) (arguing that, as originally understood, “the
principle of due process” required, among other things, that
“statutes that purported to empower the other branches to deprive
persons of rights without adequate procedural guarantees [be]
subject to judicial review”).
I need not choose between these two
understandings of “due process of law” in this case. Justice Alito
explains why the majority’s decision is wrong even under our
precedents. See
post, at 13–17 (dissenting opinion). And
more generally, I adhere to the view that “ ‘[i]f any fool
would know that a particular category of conduct would be within
the reach of the statute, if there is an unmistakable core that a
reasonable person would know is forbidden by the law, the enactment
is not unconstitutional on its face,’ ”
Morales,
supra, at 112 (Thomas, J., dissenting), and there is no
question that ACCA’s residual clause meets that description, see
ante, at 10 (agreeing with the Government that “there will
be straightforward cases under the residual clause”).
* * *
I have no love for our residual clause
jurisprudence: As I observed when we first got into this business,
the Sixth Amendment problem with allowing district courts to
conduct factfinding to determine whether an offense is a “violent
felony” made our attempt to construe the residual clause “ ‘an
unnecessary exercise.’ ”
James, 550 U. S.
,
at 231 (Thomas, J., dissenting). But the Court rejected my
argument, choosing instead to begin that unnecessary exercise. I
see no principled way that, four cases later, the Court can now
declare that the residual clause has become too indeterminate to
apply. Having damaged the residual clause through our misguided
jurisprudence, we have no right to send this provision back to
Congress and ask for a new one. I cannot join the Court in using
the Due Process Clause to nullify an Act of Congress that contains
an unmistakable core of forbidden conduct, and I concur only in its
judgment.