NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the
United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter
of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Washington,
D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in
order that corrections may be made before the preliminary print
goes to press.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 13–1402
_________________
JOHN F. KERRY, SECRETARY OF STATE,
et al., PETITIONERS
v. FAUZIA DIN
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the ninth circuit
[June 15, 2015]
Justice Scalia announced the judgment of the
Court and delivered an opinion, in which The Chief Justice and
Justice Thomas join.
Fauzia Din is a citizen and resident of the
United States. Her husband, Kanishka Berashk, is an Afghan citizen
and former civil servant in the Taliban regime who resides in that
country. When the Government declined to issue an immigrant visa to
Berashk, Din sued.
The state action of which Din complains is the
denial of
Berashk’s visa application. Naturally, one would
expect him—not Din—to bring this suit. But because Berashk is an
unadmitted and nonresident alien, he has no right of entry into the
United States, and no cause of action to press in furtherance of
his claim for admission. See
Kleindienst v.
Mandel,
408 U. S. 753, 762 (1972) . So, Din attempts to bring suit on
his behalf, alleging that the Government’s denial of her
husband’s visa application violated
her
constitutional rights. See App. 36–37, Complaint ¶56. In
particular, she claims that the Government denied her due process
of law when, without adequate explanation of the reason for the
visa denial, it deprived her of her constitutional right to live in
the United States with her spouse. There is no such constitutional
right. What Justice Breyer’s dissent strangely describes as a
“deprivation of her freedom to live together with her spouse in
America,”
post, at 4–5, is, in any world other than the
artificial world of ever-expanding constitutional rights, nothing
more than a deprivation of her spouse’s freedom to immigrate into
America.
For the reasons given in this opinion and in the
opinion concurring in the judgment, we vacate and remand.
I
A
Under the Immigration and Nationality Act
(INA), 66Stat. 163, as amended, 8 U. S. C. §1101
et seq., an alien may not enter and permanently reside
in the United States without a visa. §1181(a). The INA creates a
special visa-application process for aliens sponsored by “immediate
relatives” in the United States. §§1151(b), 1153(a). Under this
process, the citizen-relative first files a petition on behalf of
the alien living abroad, asking to have the alien classified as an
immediate relative. See §§1153(f), 1154(a)(1). If and when a
petition is approved, the alien may apply for a visa by submitting
the required documents and appearing at a United States Embassy or
consulate for an interview with a consular officer. See
§§1201(a)(1), 1202. Before issuing a visa, the consular officer
must ensure the alien is not inadmissible under any provision of
the INA. §1361.
One ground for inadmissibility, §1182(a)(3)(B),
covers “[t]errorist activities.” In addition to the violent and
destructive acts the term immediately brings to mind, the INA
defines “terrorist activity” to include providing material support
to a terrorist organization and serving as a terrorist
organization’s representative. §1182(a)(3)(B)(i), (iii)–(vi).
B
Fauzia Din came to the United States as a
refugee in 2000, and became a naturalized citizen in 2007. She
filed a petition to have Kanishka Berashk, whom she married in
2006, classified as her immediate relative. The petition was
granted, and Berashk filed a visa application. The U. S.
Embassy in Islamabad, Pakistan, interviewedBerashk and denied his
application. A consular officer informed Berashk that he was
inadmissible under §1182(a)(3)(B) but provided no further
explanation.
Din then brought suit in Federal District Court
seeking a writ of mandamus directing the United States to prop-erly
adjudicate Berashk’s visa application; a declaratory judgment that
8 U. S. C. §1182(b)(2)–(3), which exempts the Government
from providing notice to an alien found inadmissible under the
terrorism bar, is unconstitutional as applied; and a declaratory
judgment that the denial violated the Administrative Procedure Act.
App. 36–39, Complaint ¶¶55–68. The District Court granted the
Government’s motion to dismiss, but the Ninth Circuit reversed. The
Ninth Circuit concluded that Din “has a protected liberty interest
in marriage that entitled [her] to review of the denial of [her]
spouse’s visa,” 718 F. 3d 856, 860 (2013), and that the
Government’s citation of §1182(a)(3)(B) did not provide Din with
the “limited judicial review” to which she was entitled under the
Due Process Clause,
id., at 868. This Court granted
certiorari. 573 U. S. ___ (2014).
II
The Fifth Amendment provides that “[n]o person
shall be . . . deprived of life, liberty, or property,
without due process of law.” Although the amount and quality of
process that our precedents have recognized as “due” under the
Clause has changed considerably since the founding, see
Pacific
Mut. Life Ins. Co. v.
Haslip, 499 U. S. 1 –36
(1991) (Scalia, J., concurring in judgment), it remains the case
that
no process is due if one is not deprived of “life,
liberty, or property,”
Swarthout v.
Cooke, 562
U. S. 216, 219 (2011) (
per curiam). The first question
that we must ask, then, is whether the denial of Berashk’s visa
application deprived Din of any of these interests. Only if we
answer in the affirmative must we proceed to consider whether the
Government’s explanation afforded sufficient process.
A
The Due Process Clause has its origin in Magna
Carta. As originally drafted, the Great Charter provided that “[n]o
freeman shall be taken, or imprisoned, or be disseised of his
freehold, or liberties, or free customs, or be outlawed, or exiled,
or any otherwise destroyed; nor will we not pass upon him, nor
condemn him, but by lawful judgment of his peers, or
by the law
of the land.” Magna Carta, ch. 29, in 1 E. Coke, The Second
Part of the Institutes of the Laws of England 45 (1797) (emphasis
added). The Court has recognized that at the time of the Fifth
Amendment’s ratification, the words “due process of law” were
understood “to convey the same meaning as the words ‘by the law of
the land’ ” in Magna Carta.
Murray’s Lessee v.
Hoboken Land & Improvement Co., 18 How. 272, 276 (1856).
Although the terminology associated with the guarantee of due
process changed dramatically between 1215 and 1791, the general
scope of the underlying rights protected stayed roughly
constant.
Edward Coke, whose Institutes “were read in the
American Colonies by virtually every student of law,”
Klopfer v.
North Carolina, 386 U. S. 213, 225
(1967) , thoroughly described the scope of the interests that could
be deprived only pursuant to “the law of the land.” Magna Carta, he
wrote, ensured that, without due process, “no man [may] be taken or
imprisoned”; “disseised of his lands, or tenements, or dispossessed
of his goods, or chattels”; “put from his livelihood without
answer”; “barred to have the benefit of the law”; denied “the
franchises, and priviledges, which the subjects have of the gift of
the king”; “exiled”; or “fore-judged of life, or limbe, disherited,
or put to torture, or death.” 1 Coke,
supra, at 46–48.
Blackstone’s description of the rights protected by Magna Carta is
similar, al-though he discusses them in terms much closer to the
“life, liberty, or property” terminology used in the Fifth
Amendment. He described first an interest in “personal security,”
“consist[ing] in a person’s legal and uninterrupted enjoyment of
his life, his limbs, his body, his health,and his reputation.” 1 W.
Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England 125 (1769). Second,
the “personal liberty of individuals” “consist[ed] in the power of
loco-motion, of changing situation, or removing one’s person to
whatsoever place one’s own inclination may direct; without
imprisonment or restraint.”
Id., at 130. And finally, a
person’s right to property included “the free use, enjoyment, and
disposal of all his acquisitions.”
Id., at 134.
Din, of course, could not conceivably claim that
the denial of Berashk’s visa application deprived her—or for that
matter even Berashk—of life or property; and under the above
described historical understanding, a claim that it deprived her of
liberty is equally absurd. The Government has not “taken or
imprisoned” Din, nor has it “confine[d]” her, either by “keeping
[her] against h[er] will in a private house, putting h[er] in the
stocks, arresting or forcibly detaining h[er] in the street.”
Id., at 132. Indeed, not even Berashk has suffered a
deprivation of liberty so understood.
B
Despite this historical evidence, this Court
has seen fit on several occasions to expand the meaning of
“liberty” under the Due Process Clause to include certain implied
“fundamental rights.” (The reasoning presumably goes like this: If
you have a right to do something, you are free to do it, and
deprivation of freedom is a deprivation of “liberty”—never mind the
original meaning of that word in the Due Process Clause.) These
implied rights have been given
more protection than “life,
liberty, or property” properly understood. While one may be
dispossessed of property, thrown in jail, or even executed so long
as proper procedures are followed, the enjoyment of implied
constitutional rights cannot be limited at all, except by
provisions that are “narrowly tailored to serve a compelling state
interest.”
Reno v.
Flores, 507 U. S. 292 –302
(1993). Din does not explicitly argue that the Government has
violated this absolute prohibition of the
substantive
component of the Due Process Clause, likely because it is obvious
that a law barring aliens engaged in terrorist activities from
entering this country
is narrowly tailored to serve a
compelling state interest. She nevertheless insists that, because
enforcement of the law affects her enjoyment of an implied
fundamental liberty, the Govern-ment must first provide her a full
battery of procedural-due-process protections.
I think it worth explaining why,
even if
one accepts the textually unsupportable doctrine of implied
fundamental rights, Din’s arguments would fail. Because “extending
constitutional protection to an asserted right or liberty interest
. . . place[s] the matter outside the arena of public
debate and legislative action,”
Washington v.
Glucksberg, 521 U. S. 702, 720 (1997) , and because the
“guideposts for responsible decisionmaking in this unchartered area
are scarce and open-ended,”
Collins v.
Harker
Heights, 503 U. S. 115, 125 (1992) , “[t]he doctrine of
judicial self-restraint requires us to exercise the utmost care
whenever we are asked to break new ground in this field,”
ibid. Accordingly, before conferring constitutional status
upon a previously unrecognized “liberty,” we have required “a
careful description of the asserted fundamental liberty interest,”
as well as a demonstration that the interest is “objectively,
deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition, and implicit
in the concept of ordered liberty, such that neither liberty nor
justice would exist if [it was] sacrificed.”
Glucksberg,
supra, at 720–721 (citations and internal quotation marks
omitted).
Din describes the denial of Berashk’s visa
application as implicating, alternately, a “liberty interest in her
marriage,” Brief for Respondent 28, a “right of association with
one’s spouse,”
id., at 18, “a liberty interest in being
reunited with certain blood relatives,”
id., at 22, and “the
liberty interest of a U. S. citizen under the Due Process
Clause to be free from arbitrary restrictions on his right to live
with his spouse,”
ibid. To be sure, this Court has at times
indulged a propensity for grandiloquence when reviewing the sweep
of implied rights, describing them so broadly that they would
include not only the interests Din asserts but many others as well.
For example: “Without doubt, [the liberty guaranteed by the Due
Process Clause] denotes not merely freedom from bodily restraint
but also the right of the individual to contract, to engage in
anyof the common occupations of life, to acquire useful knowledge,
to marry, establish a home and bring up children, [and] to worship
God according to the dictates of his own conscience”
Meyer
v.
Nebraska, 262 U. S. 390, 399 (1923) . But this Court
is not bound by dicta, especially dicta that have been repudiated
by the holdings of our subsequent cases. And the actual holdings of
the cases Din relies upon hardly establish the capacious right she
now asserts.
Unlike the States in
Loving v.
Virginia, 388 U. S. 1 (1967) ,
Zablocki v.
Redhail, 434 U. S. 374 (1978) , and
Turner v.
Safley, 482 U. S. 78 (1987) , the Federal Government
here has not attempted to forbid a marriage. Al-though Din and the
dissent borrow language from those cases invoking a fundamental
right to marriage, they both implicitly concede that no such right
has been infringed in this case. Din relies on the “associational
interests in marriage that necessarily are protected by the right
to marry,” and that are “presuppose[d]” by later cases establishing
a right to marital privacy. Brief for Respondent 16, 18. The
dissent supplements the fundamental right to marriage with a
fundamental right to live in the United States in order to find an
affected liberty interest.
Post, at 2–3 (Breyer, J.,
dissenting).
Attempting to abstract from these cases some
liberty interest that might be implicated by Berashk’s visa denial,
Din draws on even more inapposite cases.
Meyer, for example,
invalidated a state statute proscribing the teaching of foreign
language to children who had not yet passed the eighth grade,
reasoning that it violated the teacher’s “right thus to teach and
the right of parents to engage him so to instruct their children.”
262 U. S., at 400.
Pierce v.
Society of Sisters,
268 U. S. 510 –535 (1925), extended
Meyer, finding that
a law requiring children to attend public schools “interferes with
the liberty of parents and guardians to direct the upbringing and
education of children under their control.”
Moore v.
East
Cleveland, 431 U. S. 494 –506 (1977), extended this
interest in raising children to caretakers in a child’s extended
family, striking down an ordinance that limited occupancy of a
single-family house to members of a nuclear family on the ground
that “[d]ecisions concerning child rearing . . . long
have been shared with grandparents or other relatives.” And
Griswold v.
Connecticut, 381 U. S. 479, 485
(1965) , concluded that a law criminalizing the use of
contraceptives by married couples violated “penumbral rights of
‘privacy and repose’ ” protecting “the sacred precincts of the
marital bedroom”—rights which do not plausibly extend into the
offices of our consulates abroad.
Nothing in the cases Din cites establishes a
free-floating and categorical liberty interest in marriage (or any
other formulation Din offers) sufficient to trigger constitutional
protection whenever a regulation in any way touches upon an aspect
of the marital relationship. Even if our cases could be construed
so broadly, the relevant question is not whether the asserted
interest “is consistent with this Court’s substantive-due-process
line of cases,” but whether it is supported by “this Nation’s
history and practice.”
Glucksberg, 521 U. S., at
723–724 (emphasis deleted). Even if we might “imply” a liberty
interest in marriage generally speaking, that must give way when
there is a tradition denying the specific application of that
general interest. Thus,
Glucksberg rejected a claimed
liberty interest in “self-sovereignty” and “personal autonomy” that
extended to assisted suicide when there was a longstanding
tradition of outlawing the practice of suicide.
Id., at 724,
727–728 (internal quotation marks omitted).
Here, a long practice of regulating spousal
immigration precludes Din’s claim that the denial of Berashk’s visa
application has deprived her of a fundamental liberty interest.
Although immigration was effectively unregu-lated prior to 1875, as
soon as Congress began legislating in this area it enacted a
complicated web of regulations that erected serious impediments to
a person’s ability to bring a spouse into the United States. See
Abrams, What Makes the Family Special? 80 U. Chi. L. Rev. 7,
10–16 (2013).
Most strikingly, perhaps, the Expatriation Act
of 1907 provided that “any American woman who marries a foreigner
shall take the nationality of her husband.” Ch. 2534, 34Stat. 1228.
Thus, a woman in Din’s position not only lacked a liberty interest
that might be affected by the Government’s disposition of her
husband’s visa application, she lost her
own rights as a
citizen upon marriage. When Congress began to impose quotas on
immigration by country of origin less than 15 years later, with the
Immigration Act of 1921, it omitted fiancés and husbands from the
family relations eligible for preferred status in the allocation of
quota spots. §2(d), 42Stat. 6. Such relations were similarly
excluded from the relations eligible for nonquota status, when that
status was expanded three years later. Immigration Act of 1924,
§4(a), 43Stat. 155.
To be sure, these early regulations were
premised on the derivative citizenship of women, a legacy of the
law of coverture that was already in decline at the time. C.
Bredbenner, A Nationality of Her Own 5 (1998). Modern
equal-protection doctrine casts substantial doubt on the
permissibility of such asymmetric treatment of women citizens in
the immigration context, and modern moral judgment rejects the
premises of such a legal order. Never-theless, this all-too-recent
practice repudiates any con-tention that Din’s asserted liberty
interest is “deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition,
and implicit in the concept of ordered liberty.”
Glucksberg,
supra, at 720 (citations and internal quotations marks
omitted).
Indeed, the law showed little more solicitude
for the marital relationship when it was a male resident or citizen
seeking admission for his fiancée or wife. The Immigration Act of
1921 granted nonquota status only to unmarried, minor children of
citizens, §2(a), while granting fiancées and wives preferred status
within the allocation of quota spots, §2(d). In other words,
a citizen could move his spouse forward in the line, but once all
the quota spots were filled for the year, the spouse was barred
without exception. This was not just a theoretical possibility: As
one commentator has observed, “[f]or many immigrants, the family
categories did little to help, because the quotas were so small
that the number of family members seeking slots far outstripped the
number available.” Abrams,
supra, at 13.
Although Congress has tended to show “a
continuing and kindly concern . . . for the unity and the
happiness of the immigrant family,” E. Hutchinson, Legislative
History of American Immigration Policy 1798–1965, p. 518 (1981),
this has been a matter of legislative grace rather than fundamental
right. Even where Congress has provided special privileges to
promote family immigration, it has also “written in careful checks
and qualifications.”
Ibid. This Court has consistently
recognized that these various distinctions are “policy questions
entrusted exclusively to the political branches of our Government,
and we have no judicial authority to substitute our political
judgment for that of the Congress.”
Fiallo v.
Bell,
430 U. S. 787, 798 (1977) . Only by diluting the meaning of a
fundamental liberty interest and jettisoning our established
jurisprudence could we conclude that the denial of Berashk’s visa
application implicates any of Din’s fundamental liberty
interests.
C
Justice Breyer suggests that procedural due
process rights attach to liberty interests that either are (1)
created by nonconstitutional law, such as a statute, or (2)
“sufficiently important” so as to “flow ‘implicit[ly]’ from the
design, object, and nature of the Due Process Clause.”
Post,
at 2.
The first point is unobjectionable, at least
given this Court’s case law. See,
e.g., Goldberg v.
Kelly, 397 U. S. 254 , and n. 8 (1970);
Collins 503 U. S., at 129. But it is unhelpful to Din,
who does not argue that a statute confers on her a liberty interest
protected by the Due Process Clause. Justice Breyer attempts to
make this argument for Din, latching onto language in
Wilkinson v.
Austin, 545 U. S. 209, 221 (2005) ,
saying that a liberty interest “may arise from an expectation or
interest created by state laws or policies.” Such an “expectation”
has been created here, he asserts, because “the law . . .
surrounds marriage with a host of legal protections to the point
that it creates a strong expectation that government will not
deprive married individuals of their freedom to live together
without strong reasons and (in individual cases) without fair
procedure,”
post, at 3. But what
Wilkinson meant by
an “expectation or interest” was not that sort of judicially
unenforceable substantial hope, but a present and legally
recognized substantive entitlement.[
1]* As sole support for its conclusion that
nonconstitutional law can create constitutionally protected liberty
interests,
Wilkinson cited
Wolff v.
McDonnell,
418 U. S. 539 –558 (1974), which held that a prisoner could
not be deprived of statutory good-time credit without procedural
due process. That was not because a prisoner might have “ ‘a
strong expectation’ ” that the government would not deprive
him of good-time credit “ ‘without strong reasons’ ” or
“ ‘fair procedure,’ ” but because “the State itself has
not only provided a statutory
right to good time [credit]
but also specifies that it is to be forfeited
only for
serious misbehavior,”
id., at 557 (emphasis added). The
legal benefits afforded to marriages and the preferential treatment
accorded to visa applicants with citizen relatives are insufficient
to confer on Din a right that can be deprived only pursuant to
procedural due process.
Justice Breyer’s second point—that procedural
due process rights attach even to some nonfundamental liberty
interests that have
not been created by statute—is much more
troubling. He relies on the implied-fundamental-rights cases
discussed above to divine a “right of spouses to live together and
to raise a family,” along with “a citizen’s right to live within
this country.”
Post, at 2–3. But perhaps recognizing that
our established methodology for identifying fundamental rights cuts
against his conclusion, see Part II–B,
supra, he argues that
the term “liberty” in the Due Process Clause includes implied
rights that, although not so fundamental as to deserve
substantive-due-process protection, are important enough to deserve
procedural-due-process protection.
Post, at 2. In other
words, there are two categories of implied rights protected by the
Due Process Clause: really fundamental rights, which cannot be
taken away at all absent a compelling state interest; and
not-so-fundamental rights, whichcan be taken away so long as
procedural due process is observed.
The dissent fails to cite a single case
supporting its novel theory of implied nonfundamental rights. It is
certainly true that
Vitek v.
Jones, 445 U. S.
480 (1980) , and
Washington v.
Harper, 494 U. S.
210 (1990) , do not entail implied
fundamental rights, but
this is because they do not entail
implied rights at all.
Vitek concerned the involuntary commitment of a prisoner,
deprivation of the expressly protected right of liberty under the
original understanding of the term, see Part II–A,
supra.
“ ‘Among the historic liberties’ protected by the Due Process
Clause is the ‘right to be free from, and to obtain judicial relief
for, unjustified intrusions on personal security.’ ”
Vitek,
supra, at 492. The same is true of
Harper, which concerned forced administration of
psychotropic drugs to an inmate. 494 U. S., at 214. Arguably,
Paul v.
Davis, 424 U. S. 693 (1976) , also
addressed an interest expressly contemplated within the meaning of
“liberty.” See 1 W. Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England
125 (“The right of personal security consists in a person’s
. . . reputation”). But that case is of no help to the
dissent anyway, since it found no liberty interest entitled to the
Due Process Clause’s protection.
Paul,
supra, at
713–714. Finally, the dissent points to
Goss v.
Lopez, 419 U. S. 565, 574 (1975) , a case that
“recognize[d] . . . as a property interest” a student’s
right to a public education conferred by Ohio’s express statutory
creation of a public school system; and further concluded that the
student’s 10-day suspension implicated the constitutionally
grounded liberty interest in “ ‘a person’s good name,
reputation, honor, or integrity.’ ”
Ultimately, the dissent identifies no case
holding that there is an implied nonfundamental right protected by
procedural due process, and only one case even
suggesting
that there is. That suggestion, in
Smith v.
Organization
of Foster Families For Equality & Reform, 431 U. S.
816 (1977) , is contained in dictum in a footnote,
id., at
842, n. 48. The holding of the case was that “the procedures
provided by New York State . . . and by New York Cit[y]
. . . are adequate to protect
whatever liberty
interests appellees
may have.”
Id., at 856 (emphasis
added).
The footnoted dictum that Justice Breyer
proposes to elevate to constitutional law is a dangerous doctrine.
It vastly expands the scope of our implied-rights jurisprudence by
setting it free from the requirement that the liberty interest be
“objectively, deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition,
and implicit in the concept of ordered liberty,”
Glucksberg,
521 U. S.
, at 720–721 (internal quotation marks
omitted). Even shallow-rooted liberties would, thanks to this new
procedural-rights-only notion of quasi-fundamental rights, qualify
for judicially imposed procedural requirements. Moreover, Justice
Breyer gives no basis for distinguishing the fundamental rights
recognized in the cases he depends on from the
nonfundamental right he believes they give rise to in the
present case.
Neither Din’s right to live with her spouse nor
her right to live within this country is implicated here. There is
a “simple distinction between government action that di-rectly
affects a citizen’s legal rights, or imposes a direct re-straint on
his liberty, and action that is directed against a third party and
affects the citizen only indirectly or incidentally.”
O’Bannon v.
Town Court Nursing Center, 447 U. S.
773, 788 (1980) . The Government has not refused to recognize Din’s
marriage to Berashk, and Din remains free to live with her husband
anywhere in the world that both individuals are permitted to
reside. And the Government has not expelled Din from the country.
It has simply determined that Kanishka Berashk engaged in terrorist
activities within the meaning of the Immigration and Nationality
Act, and has therefore denied him admission into the country. This
might, indeed, deprive Din of something “important,”
post,
at 2, but if that is the criterion for Justice Breyer’s new pairing
of substantive and procedural due process, we are in for quite a
ride.
* * *
Because Fauzia Din was not deprived of “life,
liberty, or property” when the Government denied Kanishka Berashk
admission to the United States, there is no process due to her
under the Constitution. To the extent that she received any
explanation for the Government’s decision, this was more than the
Due Process Clause required. The judgment of the Ninth Circuit is
vacated, and the case is remanded for further proceedings.
It is so ordered.