Petitioner was charged with capital murder in Texas state court.
He was found competent to stand trial, although a psychologist
testified that he was mildly to moderately retarded and had the
mental age of a 6 1/2-year-old. At the guilt-innocence phase of the
trial, petitioner raised an insanity defense and presented
psychiatric testimony that he suffered from a combination of
organic brain damage and moderate retardation which resulted in
poor impulse control and an inability to learn from experience. His
evidence also indicated that he had been abused as a child. The
State introduced testimony that petitioner was legally sane, but
had an antisocial personality. The jury rejected petitioner's
insanity defense and found him guilty of capital murder. At the
penalty phase of the trial, the sentencing jury was instructed to
consider all the evidence introduced at trial in answering the
following "special issues": (1) whether petitioner's conduct was
committed deliberately and with the reasonable expectation that
death would result; (2) whether there was a probability that he
would be a continuing threat to society; and (3) whether the
killing was unreasonable in response to any provocation by the
victim. The trial court rejected petitioner's request for jury
instructions defining the terms in the special issues and
authorizing a grant of mercy based upon the existence of mitigating
circumstances. The jury answered "yes" to each special issue, and,
as required by Texas law, the court therefore sentenced petitioner
to death. A "no" answer to any of the special issues would have
required a sentence of life imprisonment. The Texas Court of
Criminal Appeals affirmed, rejecting petitioner's contentions that
his death sentence violated the Eighth Amendment first, because the
jury was not adequately instructed to consider all of his
mitigating evidence and because the special issues' terms were not
defined in such a way that the jury could consider and give effect
to that evidence in answering them; and, second, because it is
cruel and unusual punishment to execute a mentally retarded person
with petitioner's mental ability. After this Court denied
certiorari on direct review, the Federal District Court and the
Court of Appeals upheld petitioner's death sentence in habeas
corpus proceedings. Although it denied him relief, the Court of
Appeals nevertheless found considerable merit in petitioner's claim
that
Page 492 U. S. 303
his mitigating evidence of mental retardation and childhood
abuse could not be given effect by the jury, under the instructions
given, in answering the special issues.
Held: The judgment is affirmed in part and reversed in
part, and the case is remanded.
832 F.2d 915, affirmed in part, reversed in part, and
remanded.
JUSTICE O'CONNOR delivered the opinion of the Court with respect
to Parts I, II-A, II-B, III, IV-A, and IV-B, concluding that:
1. Granting petitioner relief on his claim that, when mitigating
evidence of mental retardation and an abused childhood is
presented, Texas juries must, upon request, be given instructions
that allow them to give effect to that mitigating evidence in
determining whether to impose the death penalty, would not create a
"new rule" which, under
Teague v. Lane, 489 U.
S. 288,
489 U. S. 301,
may not generally be applied or announced in cases on collateral
review. Pp.
492 U. S.
313-319.
(a) The
Teague rule of nonretroactivity and its two
exceptions are applicable in the capital sentencing context. A
criminal judgment includes the sentence imposed, and collateral
challenges to sentences foster delay and undermine the finality
concerns underlying
Teague's rule of nonretroactivity. Pp.
492 U. S.
313-314.
(b) Under
Teague, a case announces a "new rule" when it
breaks new ground or imposes a new obligation on the States or the
Federal Government, or if the result is not dictated by precedent
which existed at the time the defendant's conviction became final.
Id. at
489 U. S. 301.
Here, since
Lockett v. Ohio, 438 U.
S. 586, and
Eddings v. Oklahoma, 455 U.
S. 104, were decided before petitioner's conviction
became final when this Court denied his certiorari petition on
direct review, he is entitled to the benefit of those decisions
under
Griffith v. Kentucky, 479 U.
S. 314. The rule that petitioner seeks does not impose a
new obligation on Texas, because
Jurek v. Texas,
428 U. S. 262,
upheld the Texas death penalty statute on the basis of assurances
that the special issues would be interpreted broadly enough to
permit the jury to consider all of the relevant mitigating evidence
a defendant might present in imposing sentence. Moreover, the rule
that petitioner seeks in this case is dictated by
Eddings
and
Lockett, which established that a State cannot,
consistent with the Eighth and Fourteenth Amendments, prevent the
sentencer from considering and giving effect to evidence relevant
to the defendant's background or character or to the circumstances
of the offense that mitigates against imposing the death penalty.
Pp.
492 U.S. 314-319.
2. The absence of instructions informing the jury that it could
consider and give effect to petitioner's mitigating evidence of
mental retardation and abused background by declining to impose the
death penalty
Page 492 U. S. 304
compels the conclusion that the jury was not provided with a
vehicle for expressing its "reasoned moral response" to that
evidence in rendering its sentencing decision, as is required by
the Eighth and Fourteenth Amendments under
Lockett,
Eddings, and subsequent decisions. Those decisions are
based on the principle that punishment must be directly related to
the defendant's personal culpability, and that a defendant who
commits crimes attributable to a disadvantaged background or
emotional and mental problems may be less culpable than one who has
no such excuse. Here, although petitioner was permitted to
introduce and argue the significance of his mitigating evidence to
the jury, the jury instructions did not permit the jury to give
effect to that evidence in answering the three special issues. As
to the first such issue, without a special instruction defining
"deliberately" in a way that would clearly direct the jury to fully
consider petitioner's mitigating evidence as it bears on his moral
culpability, a juror who believed that that evidence made
imposition of the death penalty unwarranted would be unable to give
effect to that conclusion if the juror also believed that
petitioner committed the crime "deliberately." Nor did the second
special issue provide a vehicle for the jury to give mitigating
effect to petitioner's evidence of mental retardation and childhood
abuse; to the contrary, the evidence concerning his inability to
learn from his mistakes by virtue of his mental retardation
actually suggests that he will be dangerous in the future. Although
such evidence may lessen his blameworthiness, it made an
affirmative answer to the second issue more likely. Furthermore, a
juror who believed that petitioner lacked the moral culpability to
be sentenced to death could not express that view in answering the
third special issue if the juror also believed that his conduct was
not a reasonable response to provocation by the victim. There is no
merit to the State's contention that to instruct the jury that it
could decline to impose the death penalty based on petitioner's
mitigating evidence would allow it the sort of unbridled discretion
prohibited by
Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.
S. 238. As
Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.
S. 153, made clear, so long as the class of murderers
subject to capital punishment is narrowed, there is no
constitutional infirmity in a procedure that allows a jury to
recommend mercy based on the mitigating evidence introduced by a
defendant. Furthermore, because the punishment imposed should be
directly related to the personal culpability of the defendant, the
sentencer must be allowed to consider and give effect to mitigating
evidence relevant to a defendant's background, character, and
crime. Full consideration of such mitigating evidence enhances the
reliability of the jury's sentencing decision. Pp.
492 U. S.
319-328.
Page 492 U. S. 305
3. The Eighth Amendment does not categorically prohibit the
execution of mentally retarded capital murderers of petitioner's
reasoning ability. Pp.
492 U. S.
328-335.
(a) Although granting petitioner relief on this issue would
create a "new rule" within the meaning of
Teague, supra,
that rule would fall within the first exception to
Teague's general rule of nonretroactivity. That exception
applies not only to new rules that place certain kinds of primary,
private individual conduct beyond the power of the criminal
lawmaking authority to proscribe. It also applies to new rules
prohibiting a certain category of punishment for a class of
defendants because of their status or offense.
Cf., e.g., Ford
v. Wainwright, 477 U. S. 399,
477 U. S. 410.
Pp.
492 U. S.
329-330.
(b) The Eighth Amendment's categorical prohibition upon the
infliction of cruel and unusual punishment applies to practices
condemned by the common law at the time the Bill of Rights was
adopted, as well as to punishments which offend our society's
evolving standards of decency as expressed in objective evidence of
legislative enactments and the conduct of sentencing juries. Since
the common law prohibited the punishment of "idiots" -- which term
was generally used to describe persons totally lacking in reason,
understanding, or the ability to distinguish between good and evil
-- it may indeed be "cruel and unusual punishment" to execute
persons who are profoundly or severely retarded and wholly lacking
in the capacity to appreciate the wrongfulness of their actions.
Such persons, however, are not likely to be convicted or face the
prospect of punishment today, since the modern insanity defense
generally includes "mental defect" as part of the legal definition
of insanity, and since
Ford v. Wainwright, supra,
prohibits the execution of persons who are unaware of their
punishment and why they must suffer it. Moreover, petitioner is not
such a person, since the jury (1) found him competent to stand
trial, and therefore to have a rational as well as factual
understanding of the proceedings; and (2) rejected his insanity
defense, thereby reflecting the conclusion that he knew his conduct
was wrong and was capable of conforming it to the requirements of
law. Nor is there sufficient objective evidence today of a national
consensus against executing mentally retarded capital murderers,
since petitioner has cited only one state statute that explicitly
bans that practice, and has offered no evidence of the general
behavior of juries in this regard. Opinion surveys indicating
strong public opposition to such executions do not establish a
societal consensus, absent some legislative reflection of the
sentiment expressed therein. Pp.
492 U. S.
330-335.
JUSTICE O'CONNOR concluded in Part IV-C that, on the present
record, it cannot be said that executing capital murderers who are
mentally retarded violates the Eighth Amendment's proportionality
requirement.
Page 492 U. S. 306
To be sure, retardation has long been regarded as a factor that
may diminish culpability, and, in its most severe form, may result
in complete exculpation. Moreover, most States with death penalty
statutes that list mitigating factors include reduced mental
capacity as a mitigating circumstance, and this Court holds today
that the sentencing body must be allowed to consider retardation in
making the individualized determination whether the death penalty
is appropriate. Mentally retarded persons, however, are individuals
whose abilities and behavioral deficits can vary greatly depending
on the degree of their retardation, their life experience, and the
ameliorative effects of education and habilitation. On the present
record, it cannot be said that all mentally retarded people of
petitioner's ability -- by virtue of their mental retardation
alone, and apart from any individualized consideration of their
personal responsibility -- inevitably lack the cognitive,
volitional, and moral capacity to act with the degree of
culpability associated with the death penalty. Moreover, the
concept of "mental age" is an insufficient basis for a categorical
Eighth Amendment rule, since it is imprecise, does not adequately
account for individuals' varying experiences and abilities, ceases
to change after a person reaches the chronological age of 15 or 16,
and could have a disempowering effect if applied to retarded
persons in other areas of the law, such as the opportunity to enter
contracts or to marry. Pp.
492 U. S. 335-340.
O'CONNOR, J., announced the judgment of the Court and delivered
the opinion for a unanimous Court with respect to Parts I and IV-A,
the opinion of the Court with respect to Parts II-B and III, in
which BRENNAN, MARSHALL, BLACKMUN, and STEVENS, JJ., joined, the
opinion of the Court with respect to Parts II-A and IV-B, in which
REHNQUIST, C.J., and WHITE, SCALIA, and KENNEDY, JJ., joined, and
an opinion with respect to Part IV-C. BRENNAN, J., filed an opinion
concurring in part and dissenting in part, in which MARSHALL, J.,
joined,
post, p.
492 U. S. 341.
STEVENS, J., filed an opinion concurring in part and dissenting in
part, in which BLACKMUN, J., joined,
post, p.
492 U. S. 349.
SCALIA, J., filed an opinion concurring in part and dissenting in
part, in which REHNQUIST, C.J., and WHITE and KENNEDY, JJ., joined,
post, p.
492 U. S.
350.
Page 492 U. S. 307
JUSTICE O'CONNOR delivered the opinion of the Court, except as
to Part IV-C.
In this case, we must decide whether petitioner, Johnny Paul
Penry, was sentenced to death in violation of the Eighth Amendment
because the jury was not instructed that it could consider and give
effect to his mitigating evidence in imposing its sentence. We must
also decide whether the Eighth Amendment categorically prohibits
Penry's execution because he is mentally retarded.
I
On the morning of October 25, 1979, Pamela Carpenter was
brutally raped, beaten, and stabbed with a pair of scissors in her
home in Livingston, Texas. She died a few hours later in the course
of emergency treatment. Before she died, she described her
assailant. Her description led two local sheriff's deputies to
suspect Penry, who had recently been released on parole after
conviction on another rape charge. Penry subsequently gave two
statements confessing to the crime, and was charged with capital
murder.
At a competency hearing held before trial, a clinical
psychologist, Dr. Jerome Brown, testified that Penry was mentally
retarded. As a child, Penry was diagnosed as having organic brain
damage, which was probably caused by trauma to the brain at birth.
App. 34-35. Penry was tested over the years as having an IQ between
50 and 63, which indicates
Page 492 U. S. 308
mild to moderate retardation. [
Footnote 1]
Id. at 36-38, 55. Dr. Brown's own
testing before the trial indicated that Penry had an IQ of 54. Dr.
Brown's evaluation also revealed that Penry, who was 22 years old
at the time of the crime, had the mental age of a 6 1/2-year-old,
which means that "he has the ability to learn and the learning or
the knowledge of the average 6 1/2-year-old kid."
Id. at
41. Penry's social maturity, or ability to function in the world,
was that of a 9- or 10-year-old. Dr. Brown testified that "there's
a point at which anyone with [Penry's] IQ is always incompetent,
but, you know, this man is more in the borderline range."
Id. at 47.
The jury found Penry competent to stand trial.
Id. at
20-24. The guilt-innocence phase of the trial began on March 24,
1980. The trial court determined that Penry's confessions were
voluntary, and they were introduced into evidence. At trial, Penry
raised an insanity defense and presented the testimony of a
psychiatrist, Dr. Jose Garcia. Dr. Garcia testified that Penry
suffered from organic brain damage and moderate retardation, which
resulted in poor impulse control and an inability to learn from
experience.
Id. at 18, 19, 87-90. Dr. Garcia indicated
that Penry's brain damage was probably caused at birth,
id. at 106, but may have been caused by beatings and
multiple injuries to the
Page 492 U. S. 309
brain at an early age.
Id. at 18, 90. In Dr. Garcia's
judgment, Penry was suffering from an organic brain disorder at the
time of the offense which made it impossible for him to appreciate
the wrongfulness of his conduct or to conform his conduct to the
law.
Id. at 86-87.
Penry's mother testified at trial that Penry was unable to learn
in school, and never finished the first grade. Penry's sister
testified that their mother had frequently beaten him over the head
with a belt when he was a child. Penry was also routinely locked in
his room without access to a toilet for long periods of time.
Id. at 124, 126, 127. As a youngster, Penry was in and out
of a number of state schools and hospitals, until his father
removed him from state schools altogether when he was 12.
Id. at 120. Penry's aunt subsequently struggled for over a
year to teach Penry how to print his name.
Id. at 133.
The State introduced the testimony of two psychiatrists to rebut
the testimony of Dr. Garcia. Dr. Kenneth Vogtsberger testified
that, although Penry was a person of limited mental ability, he was
not suffering from any mental illness or defect at the time of the
crime, and that he knew the difference between right and wrong and
had the potential to honor the law.
Id. at 144-145. In his
view, Penry had characteristics consistent with an antisocial
personality, including an inability to learn from experience and a
tendency to be impulsive and to violate society's norms.
Id. at 149-150. He testified further that Penry's low IQ
scores underestimated his alertness and understanding of what went
on around him.
Id. at 146.
Dr. Felix Peebles also testified for the State that Penry was
legally sane at the time of the offense, and had a "full-blown
anti-social personality."
Id. at 171. In addition, Dr.
Peebles testified that he personally diagnosed Penry as being
mentally retarded in 1973 and again in 1977, and that Penry "had a
very bad life generally, bringing up."
Id. at 168-169. In
Dr. Peebles' view, Penry "had been socially and
Page 492 U. S. 310
emotionally deprived, and he had not learned to read and write
adequately."
Id. at 169. Although they disagreed with the
defense psychiatrist over the extent and cause of Penry's mental
limitations, both psychiatrists for the State acknowledged that
Penry was a person of extremely limited mental ability, and that he
seemed unable to learn from his mistakes.
Id. at 149,
172-173.
The jury rejected Penry's insanity defense, and found him guilty
of capital murder. Tex.Penal Code Ann. ยง19.03 (1974 and Supp.
1989). The following day, at the close of the penalty hearing, the
jury decided the sentence to be imposed on Penry by answering three
"special issues":
"(1) whether the conduct of the defendant that caused the death
of the deceased was committed deliberately and with the reasonable
expectation that the death of the deceased or another would
result;"
"(2) whether there is a probability that the defendant would
commit criminal acts of violence that would constitute a continuing
threat to society; and"
"(3) if raised by the evidence, whether the conduct of the
defendant in killing the deceased was unreasonable in response to
the provocation, if any, by the deceased."
Tex.Code Crim.Proc.Ann., Art. 37.071(b) (Vernon 1981 and Supp.
1989). If the jury unanimously answers "yes" to each issue
submitted, the trial court must sentence the defendant to death.
Art. 37.071(c)-(e). Otherwise, the defendant is sentenced to life
imprisonment.
Ibid.
Defense counsel raised a number of objections to the proposed
charge to the jury. With respect to the first special issue, he
objected that the charge failed to define the term "deliberately."
App. 210. With respect to the second special issue, he objected
that the charge failed to define the terms "probability," "criminal
acts of violence," and "continuing threat to society."
Id.
at 210-211. Defense counsel
Page 492 U. S. 311
also objected to the charge because it failed to "authorize a
discretionary grant of mercy based upon the existence of mitigating
circumstances" and because it
"fail[ed] to require as a condition to the assessment of the
death penalty that the State show beyond a reasonable doubt that
any aggravating circumstances found to exist outweigh any
mitigating circumstances."
Id. at 211. In addition, the charge failed to instruct
the jury that it may take into consideration all of the evidence
whether aggravating or mitigating in nature which was submitted in
the full trial of the case.
Id. at 212. Defense counsel
also objected that, in light of Penry's mental retardation,
permitting the jury to assess the death penalty in this case
amounted to cruel and unusual punishment prohibited by the Eighth
Amendment.
Id. at 211.
These objections were overruled by the trial court. The jury was
then instructed that the State bore the burden of proof on the
special issues, and that, before any issue could be answered "yes,"
all twelve jurors must be convinced by the evidence beyond a
reasonable doubt that the answer to that issue should be "yes."
Id. at 25. The jurors were further instructed that, in
answering the three special issues, they could consider all the
evidence submitted in both the guilt-innocence phase and the
penalty phase of the trial.
Id. at 26. The jury charge
then listed the three questions, with the names of the defendant
and the deceased inserted.
The jury answered "yes" to all three special issues, and Penry
was sentenced to death. The Texas Court of Criminal Appeals
affirmed his conviction and sentence on direct appeal.
Penry v.
State, 691
S.W.2d 636 (Tex. Crim.App. 1985). That court held that terms
such as "deliberately," "probability," and "continuing threat to
society" used in the special issues need not be defined in the jury
charge, because the jury would know their common meaning.
Id. at 653-654. The court concluded that Penry was allowed
to present all relevant mitigating evidence at the punishment
hearing, and that there was no constitutional infirmity in failing
to
Page 492 U. S. 312
require the jury to find that aggravating circumstances
outweighed mitigating ones or in failing to authorize a
discretionary grant of mercy based upon the existence of mitigating
circumstances.
Id. at 654. The court also held that
imposition of the death penalty was not prohibited by virtue of
Penry's mental retardation.
Id. at 654-655. This Court
denied certiorari on direct review.
Sub nom. Penry v.
Texas, 474 U. S. 1073
(1986).
Penry then filed this federal habeas corpus petition challenging
his death sentence. Among other claims, Penry argued that he was
sentenced in violation of the Eighth Amendment because the trial
court failed to instruct the jury on how to weigh mitigating
factors in answering the special issues, and failed to define the
term "deliberately." Penry also argued that it was cruel and
unusual punishment to execute a mentally retarded person. The
District Court denied relief, App. 234-273, and Penry appealed to
the Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit.
The Court of Appeals affirmed the District Court's judgment. 832
F.2d 915 (1987). The court stressed, however, that it found
considerable merit in Penry's claim that the jury was not allowed
to consider and apply all of his personal mitigating circumstances
in answering the Texas special issues. Although the jury was
presented with evidence that might mitigate Penry's personal
culpability for the crime, such as his mental retardation, arrested
emotional development, and abused background, the jury could not
give effect to that evidence by mitigating Penry's sentence to life
imprisonment. "Having said that it was a deliberate murder and that
Penry will be a continuing threat, the jury can say no more."
Id. at 920. In short, the court did not see how Penry's
mitigating evidence, under the instructions given, could be fully
acted upon by the jury, because "[t]here is no place for the jury
to say
no' to the death penalty" based on the mitigating force
of those circumstances. Id. at 925. Although the court
questioned whether Penry was given the individualized
Page 492 U. S. 313
sentencing that the Constitution requires, it ultimately
concluded that prior Circuit decisions required it to reject
Penry's claims.
Id. at 926. The court also rejected
Penry's contention that it was cruel and unusual punishment to
execute a mentally retarded person such as himself.
Id. at
918 (citing
Brogdon v. Butler, 824 F.2d 338, 341 (CA5
1987)).
We granted certiorari to resolve two questions. 487 U.S. 1233
(1988). First, was Penry sentenced to death in violation of the
Eighth Amendment because the jury was not adequately instructed to
take into consideration all of his mitigating evidence and because
the terms in the Texas special issues were not defined in such a
way that the jury could consider and give effect to his mitigating
evidence in answering them? Second, is it cruel and unusual
punishment under the Eighth Amendment to execute a mentally
retarded person with Penry's reasoning ability?
II
A
Penry is currently before the Court on his petition in federal
court for a writ of habeas corpus. Because Penry is before us on
collateral review, we must determine, as a threshold matter,
whether granting him the relief he seeks would create a "new rule."
Teague v. Lane, 489 U. S. 288,
489 U. S. 301
(1989). Under
Teague, new rules will not be applied or
announced in cases on collateral review unless they fall into one
of two exceptions.
Id. at
489 U. S.
311-313.
Teague was not a capital case, and the plurality
opinion expressed no views regarding how the retroactivity approach
adopted in
Teague would be applied in the capital
sentencing context.
Id. at
489 U. S. 314,
n. 2. The plurality noted, however, that a criminal judgment
necessarily includes the sentence imposed, and that collateral
challenges to sentences
"delay the enforcement of the judgment at issue and decrease the
possibility that 'there will at some point be the certainty that
comes with an end to litigation.'"
Ibid. (quoting
Sanders v.
Page 492 U. S. 314
United States, 373 U. S. 1,
373 U. S. 25
(1963) (Harlan, J., dissenting)).
See also Mackey v. United
States, 401 U. S. 667,
401 U. S.
690-695 (1971) (Harlan, J., concurring in judgments in
part and dissenting in part). In our view, the finality concerns
underlying Justice Harlan's approach to retroactivity are
applicable in the capital sentencing context, as are the two
exceptions to his general rule of nonretroactivity.
See Teague,
supra, at
489 U. S.
311-313.
B
As we indicated in
Teague,
"[i]n general . . . a case announces a new rule when it breaks
new ground or imposes a new obligation on the States or the Federal
Government."
489 U.S. at
489 U. S. 301.
Or,
"[t]o put it differently, a case announces a new rule if the
result was not
dictated by precedent existing at the time
the defendant's conviction became final."
Ibid. (emphasis in original).
Teague noted
that "[i]t is admittedly often difficult to determine when a case
announces a new rule."
Ibid. Justice Harlan recognized
"the inevitable difficulties that will arise in attempting "to
determine whether a particular decision has really announced a
new' rule at all, or whether it has simply applied a
well-established constitutional principle to govern a case which is
closely analogous to those which have been previously considered in
the prior case law.""
Mackey, supra, at
401 U. S. 695
(opinion concurring in judgments in part and dissenting in part)
(quoting
Desist v. United States, 394 U.
S. 244,
394 U. S. 263
(1969) (Harlan, J., dissenting)).
See generally Yates v.
Aiken, 484 U. S. 211,
484 U. S.
216-217 (1988) (concluding that
Francis v.
Franklin, 471 U. S. 307
(1985), did not announce a new rule, but was "merely an application
of the principle that governed our decision in
Sandstrom
v. Montana, [
442 U.S.
510 (1979),] which had been decided before petitioner's trial
took place").
Penry's conviction became final on January 13, 1986, when this
Court denied his petition for certiorari on direct review of his
conviction and sentence.
Sub nom. Penry v. Texas, supra.
This Court's decisions in
Lockett v.
Ohio, 438 U.S.
Page 492 U. S. 315
586 (1978), and
Eddings v. Oklahoma, 455 U.
S. 104 (1982), were rendered before his conviction
became final. Under the retroactivity principles adopted in
Griffith v. Kentucky, 479 U. S. 314
(1987), Penry is entitled to the benefit of those decisions. Citing
Lockett and
Eddings, Penry argues that he was
sentenced to death in violation of the Eighth Amendment because, in
light of the jury instructions given, the jury was unable to fully
consider and give effect to the mitigating evidence of his mental
retardation and abused background, which he offered as the basis
for a sentence less than death. Penry thus seeks a rule that, when
such mitigating evidence is presented, Texas juries must, upon
request, be given jury instructions that make it possible for them
to give effect to that mitigating evidence in determining whether a
defendant should be sentenced to death. We conclude, for the
reasons discussed below, that the rule Penry seeks is not a "new
rule" under
Teague.
Penry does not challenge the facial validity of the Texas death
penalty statute, which was upheld against an Eighth Amendment
challenge in
Jurek v. Texas, 428 U.
S. 262 (1976). Nor does he dispute that some types of
mitigating evidence can be fully considered by the sentencer in the
absence of special jury instructions.
See Franklin v.
Lynaugh, 487 U. S. 164,
487 U. S. 175
(1988) (plurality opinion);
id. at
487 U. S.
185-186 (O'CONNOR, J., concurring in judgment). Instead,
Penry argues that, on the facts of this case, the jury was unable
to fully consider and give effect to the mitigating evidence of his
mental retardation and abused background in answering the three
special issues. In our view, the relief Penry seeks does not
"impos[e] a new obligation" on the State of Texas.
Teague,
supra, at
489 U. S. 301.
Rather, Penry simply asks the State to fulfill the assurance upon
which
Jurek was based: namely, that the special issues
would be interpreted broadly enough to permit the sentencer to
consider all of the relevant mitigating evidence a defendant might
present in imposing sentence.
Page 492 U. S. 316
In
Jurek, the joint opinion of Justices Stewart,
Powell, and STEVENS noted that the Texas statute narrowed the
circumstances in which the death penalty could be imposed to five
categories of murders. 428 U.S. at
428 U. S. 268.
Thus, although Texas had not adopted a list of statutory
aggravating factors that the jury must find before imposing the
death penalty, "its action in narrowing the categories of murders
for which a death sentence may ever be imposed serves much the same
purpose,"
id. at
428 U. S. 270,
and effectively "requires the sentencing authority to focus on the
particularized nature of the crime."
Id. at
428 U. S. 271.
To provide the individualized sentencing determination required by
the Eighth Amendment, however, the sentencer must be allowed to
consider mitigating evidence.
Ibid. Indeed, as
Woodson
v. North Carolina, 428 U. S. 280
(1976), made clear,
"in capital cases, the fundamental respect for humanity
underlying the Eighth Amendment . . . requires consideration of the
character and record of the individual offender and the
circumstances of the particular offense as a constitutionally
indispensable part of the process of inflicting the penalty of
death."
Id. at
428 U. S. 304
(plurality opinion).
Because the Texas death penalty statute does not explicitly
mention mitigating circumstances, but rather directs the jury to
answer three questions,
Jurek reasoned that the statute's
constitutionality "turns on whether the enumerated questions allow
consideration of particularized mitigating factors." 428 U.S. at
428 U. S. 272.
Although the various terms in the special questions had yet to be
defined, the joint opinion concluded that the sentencing scheme
satisfied the Eighth Amendment on the assurance that the Texas
Court of Criminal Appeals would interpret the question concerning
future dangerousness so as to allow the jury to consider whatever
mitigating circumstances a defendant may be able to show, including
a defendant's prior criminal record, age, and mental or emotional
state.
Id. at
428 U. S.
272-273.
Page 492 U. S. 317
Our decisions subsequent to
Jurek have reaffirmed that
the Eighth Amendment mandates an individualized assessment of the
appropriateness of the death penalty. In
Lockett v. Ohio,
438 U. S. 586
(1978), a plurality of this Court held that the Eighth and
Fourteenth Amendments require that the sentencer
"not be precluded from considering,
as a mitigating
factor, any aspect of a defendant's character or record and
any of the circumstances of the offense that the defendant proffers
as a basis for a sentence less than death."
Id. at
438 U. S. 604
(emphasis in original). Thus, the Court held unconstitutional the
Ohio death penalty statute which mandated capital punishment upon a
finding of one aggravating circumstance unless one of three
statutory mitigating factors was present.
Lockett underscored
Jurek's recognition that
the constitutionality of the Texas scheme "turns on whether the
enumerated questions allow consideration of particularized
mitigating factors."
Jurek, 428 U.S. at
428 U. S. 272.
The plurality opinion in
Lockett indicated that the Texas
death penalty statute had
"survived the petitioner's Eighth and Fourteenth Amendment
attack [in
Jurek] because three Justices concluded that
the Texas Court of Criminal Appeals had broadly interpreted the
second question -- despite its facial narrowness -- so as to permit
the sentencer to consider 'whatever mitigating circumstances' the
defendant might be able to show."
438 U.S. at
438 U. S. 607.
Thus, the
Lockett plurality noted that neither the Texas
statute upheld in 1976 nor the statutes that had survived facial
challenges in
Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.
S. 153 (1976), and
Proffitt v. Florida,
428 U. S. 242
(1976),
"clearly operated at that time to prevent the sentencer from
considering any aspect of the defendant's character and record or
any circumstances of his offense as an independently mitigating
factor."
Lockett, supra, at
438 U. S. 607.
Cf. Hitchcock v. Dugger, 481 U. S. 393
(1987) (sustaining "as applied" challenge to Florida death penalty
statute);
Godfrey
Page 492 U. S. 318
v. Georgia, 446 U. S. 420
(1980) (sustaining "as applied" challenge to Georgia death penalty
statute).
In
Eddings v. Oklahoma, 455 U.
S. 104 (1982), a majority of the Court reaffirmed that a
sentencer may not be precluded from considering, and may not refuse
to consider, any relevant mitigating evidence offered by the
defendant as the basis for a sentence less than death. In
Eddings, the Oklahoma death penalty statute permitted the
defendant to introduce evidence of any mitigating circumstance, but
the sentencing judge concluded, as a matter of law, that he was
unable to consider mitigating evidence of the youthful defendant's
troubled family history, beatings by a harsh father, and emotional
disturbance. Applying
Lockett, we held that
"[j]ust as the State may not by statute preclude the sentencer
from considering any mitigating factor, neither may the sentencer
refuse to consider,
as a matter of law, any relevant
mitigating evidence."
455 U.S. at
455 U. S.
113-114 (emphasis in original). In that case, "it was as
if the trial judge had instructed a jury to disregard the
mitigating evidence [the defendant] proffered on his behalf."
Id. at 114.
Thus, at the time Penry's conviction became final, it was clear
from
Lockett and
Eddings that a State could not,
consistent with the Eighth and Fourteenth Amendments, prevent the
sentencer from considering and giving effect to evidence relevant
to the defendant's background or character or to the circumstances
of the offense that mitigate against imposing the death penalty.
Moreover, the facial validity of the Texas death penalty statute
had been upheld in
Jurek on the basis of assurances that
the special issues would be interpreted broadly enough to enable
sentencing juries to consider all of the relevant mitigating
evidence a defendant might present. Penry argues that those
assurances were not fulfilled
in his particular case
because, without appropriate instructions, the jury could not fully
consider and give effect to the mitigating evidence of his mental
retardation and abused childhood in rendering its sentencing
decision. The rule
Page 492 U. S. 319
Penry seeks -- that when such mitigating evidence is presented,
Texas juries must, upon request, be given jury instructions that
make it possible for them to give effect to that mitigating
evidence in determining whether the death penalty should be imposed
-- is not a "new rule" under
Teague, because it is
dictated by
Eddings and
Lockett. Moreover, in
light of the assurances upon which
Jurek was based, we
conclude that the relief Penry seeks does not "impos[e] a new
obligation" on the State of Texas.
Teague, 489 U.S. at
489 U. S.
301.
Underlying
Lockett and
Eddings is the
principle that punishment should be directly related to the
personal culpability of the criminal defendant. If the sentencer is
to make an individualized assessment of the appropriateness of the
death penalty,
"evidence about the defendant's background and character is
relevant because of the belief, long held by this society, that
defendants who commit criminal acts that are attributable to a
disadvantaged background, or to emotional and mental problems, may
be less culpable than defendants who have no such excuse."
California v. Brown, 479 U. S. 538,
479 U. S. 545
(1987) (O'CONNOR, J., concurring). Moreover,
Eddings makes
clear that it is not enough simply to allow the defendant to
present mitigating evidence to the sentencer. The sentencer must
also be able to consider and give effect to that evidence in
imposing sentence.
Hitchcock v. Dugger, 481 U.
S. 393 (1987). Only then can we be sure that the
sentencer has treated the defendant as a "uniquely individual human
bein[g]," and has made a reliable determination that death is the
appropriate sentence. Woodson, 428 U.S. at
428 U. S. 304,
428 U. S.
305.
"Thus, the sentence imposed at the penalty stage should reflect
a reasoned
moral response to the defendant's background,
character, and crime."
California v. Brown, supra, at
479 U. S. 545
(O'CONNOR, J., concurring) (emphasis in original).
Page 492 U. S. 320
Although Penry offered mitigating evidence of his mental
retardation and abused childhood as the basis for a sentence of
life imprisonment rather than death, the jury that sentenced him
was only able to express its views on the appropriate sentence by
answering three questions: Did Penry act deliberately when he
murdered Pamela Carpenter? Is there a probability that he will be
dangerous in the future? Did he act unreasonably in response to
provocation? The jury was never instructed that it could consider
the evidence offered by Penry as
mitigating evidence, and
that it could give mitigating effect to that evidence in imposing
sentence.
Like the petitioner in
Franklin v. Lynaugh,, Penry
contends that, in the absence of his requested jury instructions,
the Texas death penalty statute was applied in an unconstitutional
manner by precluding the jury from acting upon the particular
mitigating evidence he introduced.
Franklin was the first
case considered by this Court since
Jurek to address a
claim concerning the treatment of mitigating evidence under the
Texas special issues. Like
Jurek itself,
Franklin
did not produce a majority opinion for the Court. The
Franklin plurality, and the two concurring Justices,
concluded that Franklin was not sentenced to death in violation of
the Eighth Amendment because the jury was free to give effect to
his mitigating evidence of good behavior in prison by answering
"no" to the question on future dangerousness. 487 U.S. at
487 U. S. 177
(plurality opinion);
id. at
487 U. S. 185
(O'CONNOR, J., concurring in judgment). Moreover, a majority agreed
that "residual doub[t]" as to Franklin's guilt was not a
constitutionally mandated mitigating factor.
Id. at
487 U. S. 173,
and n. 6 (plurality opinion);
id. at
487 U. S.
187-188 (O'CONNOR, J., concurring in judgment).
In
Franklin, however, the five concurring and
dissenting Justices did not share the plurality's categorical
reading of
Jurek. In the plurality's view,
Jurek
had expressly and unconditionally upheld the manner in which
mitigating evidence is considered under the special issues.
Id. at
487 U. S.
179-180, and
Page 492 U. S. 321
n. 10. In contrast, five Members of the Court read
Jurek as not precluding a claim that, in a particular
case, the jury was unable to fully consider the mitigating evidence
introduced by a defendant in answering the special issues.
Id. at
487 U. S. 183
(O'CONNOR, J., concurring in judgment);
id. at
487 U. S.
199-200 (STEVENS, J., dissenting). Indeed, both the
concurrence and the dissent understood
Jurek as resting
fundamentally on the express assurance that the special issues
would permit the jury to fully consider all the mitigating evidence
a defendant introduced that was relevant to the defendant's
background and character and to the circumstances of the offense.
Moreover, both the concurrence and the dissent stressed that
"the right to have the sentencer consider and weigh relevant
mitigating evidence would be meaningless unless the sentencer was
also permitted to give effect to its consideration"
in imposing sentence.
Id. at
487 U. S. 185
(O'CONNOR, J., concurring in judgment);
id. at
487 U. S. 199
(STEVENS, J., dissenting).
The concurrence in
Franklin concluded that there was no
Eighth Amendment violation in that case because Franklin's evidence
of his good prison behavior had no clear relevance to his character
other than to demonstrate his ability to live in a highly
structured prison environment without endangering others. Thus, the
jury was able to give effect to the mitigating force of this
evidence in answering the second special issue. The concurrence
noted, however:
"If . . . petitioner had introduced mitigating evidence about
his background or character or the circumstances of the crime that
was not relevant to the special verdict questions, or that had
relevance to the defendant's moral culpability beyond the scope of
the special verdict questions, the jury instructions would have
provided the jury with no vehicle for expressing its 'reasoned
moral response' to that evidence. If this were such a case, then we
would have to decide whether the jury's inability to give effect to
that evidence amounted to an Eighth Amendment violation."
Id. at
487 U. S.
185.
Page 492 U. S. 322
Penry argues that his mitigating evidence of mental retardation
and childhood abuse has relevance to his moral culpability beyond
the scope of the special issues, and that the jury was unable to
express its "reasoned moral response" to that evidence in
determining whether death was the appropriate punishment. We agree.
Thus, we reject the State's contrary argument that the jury was
able to consider and give effect to all of Penry's mitigating
evidence in answering the special issues without any jury
instructions on mitigating evidence.
The first special issue asks whether the defendant acted
"deliberately and with the reasonable expectation that the death of
the deceased . . . would result." Neither the Texas Legislature nor
the Texas Court of Criminal Appeals have defined the term
"deliberately," and the jury was not instructed on the term, so we
do not know precisely what meaning the jury gave to it. Assuming,
however, that the jurors in this case understood "deliberately" to
mean something more than that Penry was guilty of "intentionally"
committing murder, those jurors may still have been unable to give
effect to Penry's mitigating evidence in answering the first
special issue.
Penry's mental retardation was relevant to the question whether
he was capable of acting "deliberately," but it also "had relevance
to [his] moral culpability beyond the scope of the special verdict
questio[n]."
Franklin, 487 U.S. at
487 U. S. 185.
Personal culpability is not solely a function of a defendant's
capacity to act "deliberately." A rational juror at the penalty
phase of the trial could have concluded, in light of Penry's
confession, that he deliberately killed Pamela Carpenter to escape
detection. Because Penry was mentally retarded, however, and thus
less able than a normal adult to control his impulses or to
evaluate the consequences of his conduct, and because of his
history of childhood abuse, that same juror could also conclude
that Penry was less morally "culpable than defendants who have no
such excuse," but
Page 492 U. S. 323
who acted "deliberately" as that term is commonly understood.
California v. Brown, 479 U.S. at
479 U. S. 545
(O'CONNOR, J., concurring).
See also Skipper v. South
Carolina, 476 U. S. 1,
476 U. S. 13-14
(1986) (Powell, J., concurring in judgment) (evidence concerning a
defendant's "emotional history . . . bear[s] directly on the
fundamental justice of imposing capital punishment").
In the absence of jury instructions defining "deliberately" in a
way that would clearly direct the jury to consider fully Penry's
mitigating evidence as it bears on his personal culpability, we
cannot be sure that the jury was able to give effect to the
mitigating evidence of Penry's mental retardation and history of
abuse in answering the first special issue. Without such a special
instruction, a juror who believed that Penry's retardation and
background diminished his moral culpability and made imposition of
the death penalty unwarranted would be unable to give effect to
that conclusion if the juror also believed that Penry committed the
crime "deliberately." Thus, we cannot be sure that the jury's
answer to the first special issue reflected a "reasoned moral
response" to Penry's mitigating evidence.
The second special issue asks
"whether there is a probability that the defendant would commit
criminal acts of violence that would constitute a continuing threat
to society."
The mitigating evidence concerning Penry's mental retardation
indicated that one effect of his retardation is his inability to
learn from his mistakes. Although this evidence is relevant to the
second issue, it is relevant only as an
aggravating
factor, because it suggests a "yes" answer to the question of
future dangerousness. The prosecutor argued at the penalty hearing
that there was
"a very strong probability, based on the history of this
defendant, his previous criminal record, and the psychiatric
testimony that we've had in this case, that the defendant will
continue to commit acts of this nature."
App. 214. Even in a prison setting, the prosecutor
Page 492 U. S. 324
argued, Penry could hurt doctors, nurses, librarians, or
teachers who worked in the prison.
Penry's mental retardation and history of abuse is thus a
two-edged sword: it may diminish his blameworthiness for his crime
even as it indicates that there is a probability that he will be
dangerous in the future. As Judge Reavley wrote for the Court of
Appeals below:
"What was the jury to do if it decided that Penry, because of
retardation, arrested emotional development and a troubled youth,
should not be executed? If anything, the evidence made it more
likely, not less likely, that the jury would answer the second
question yes. It did not allow the jury to consider a major thrust
of Penry's evidence as
mitigating evidence."
832 F.2d at 925 (footnote omitted) (emphasis in original). The
second special issue, therefore, did not provide a vehicle for the
jury to give mitigating effect to Penry's evidence of mental
retardation and childhood abuse.
The third special issue asks
"whether the conduct of the defendant in killing the deceased
was unreasonable in response to the provocation, if any, by the
deceased."
On this issue, the State argued that Penry stabbed Pamela
Carpenter with a pair of scissors not in response to provocation,
but "for the purpose of avoiding detection." App. 215. Penry's own
confession indicated that he did not stab the victim after she
wounded him superficially with a scissors during a struggle, but
rather killed her after her struggle had ended and she was lying
helpless. Even if a juror concluded that Penry's mental retardation
and arrested emotional development rendered him less culpable for
his crime than a normal adult, that would not necessarily diminish
the "unreasonableness" of his conduct in response to "the
provocation, if any, by the deceased." Thus, a juror who believed
Penry lacked the moral culpability to be sentenced to death could
not express that view in answering the third special issue if she
also concluded
Page 492 U. S. 325
that Penry's action was not a reasonable response to
provocation.
The State contends, notwithstanding the three interrogatories,
that Penry was free to introduce and argue the significance of his
mitigating circumstances to the jury. In fact, defense counsel did
argue that, if a juror believed that Penry, because of the
mitigating evidence of his mental retardation and abused
background, did not deserve to be put to death, the juror should
vote "no" on one of the special issues even if it believed the
State had proved that the answer should be "yes." Thus, Penry's
counsel stressed the evidence of Penry's mental retardation and
abused background, and asked the jurors, "can you be proud to be a
party to putting a man to death with that affliction?" App. 222. He
urged the jury to answer the first special issue "no" because "it
would be the just answer, and I think it would be a proper answer."
Id. at 223. As for the prediction of the prosecution
psychiatrist that Penry was likely to continue to get into trouble,
the defense argued:
"That may be true. But, a boy with this mentality, with this
mental affliction, even though you have found that issue against us
as to insanity, I don't think that there is any question in a
single one of you juror's [
sic] minds that there is
something definitely wrong, basically, with this boy. And I think
there is not a single one of you that doesn't believe that this boy
had brain damage. . . ."
Id. at 223-224. In effect, defense counsel urged the
jury to
"[t]hink about each of those special issues and see if you don't
find that we're inquiring into the mental state of the defendant in
each and every one of them."
Id. at 221.
In rebuttal, the prosecution countered by stressing that the
jurors had taken an oath to follow the law, and that they must
follow the instructions they were given in answering the special
issues:
"You've all taken an oath to follow the law, and you know what
the law is. . . . In answering these questions based on the
evidence and following the law, and that's all that
Page 492 U. S. 326
I asked you to do, is to go out and look at the evidence. The
burden of proof is on the State, as it has been from the beginning,
and we accept that burden. And I honestly believe that we have more
than met that burden, and that's the reason that you didn't hear
Mr. Newman [defense attorney] argue. He didn't pick out these
issues and point out to you where the State had failed to meet this
burden. He didn't point out the weaknesses in the State's case
because, ladies and gentlemen, I submit to you we've met our
burden. . . . [Y]our job as jurors and your duty as jurors is not
to act on your emotions, but to act on the law as the Judge has
given it to you, and on the evidence that you have heard in this
courtroom, then answer those questions accordingly."
Id. at 225-226. In light of the prosecutor's argument,
and in the absence of appropriate jury instructions, a reasonable
juror could well have believed that there was no vehicle for
expressing the view that Penry did not deserve to be sentenced to
death based upon his mitigating evidence.
The State conceded at oral argument in this Court that, if a
juror concluded that Penry acted deliberately and was likely to be
dangerous in the future, but also concluded that, because of his
mental retardation, he was not sufficiently culpable to deserve the
death penalty, that juror would be unable to give effect to that
mitigating evidence under the instructions given in this case. Tr.
of Oral Arg. 38. The State contends, however, that to instruct the
jury that it could render a discretionary grant of mercy, or say
"no" to the death penalty, based on Penry's mitigating evidence,
would be to return to the sort of unbridled discretion that led to
Furman v. Georgia, 408 U. S. 238
(1972). We disagree.
To be sure,
Furman held that,
"in order to minimize the risk that the death penalty would be
imposed on a capriciously selected group of offenders, the decision
to impose it had to be guided by standards so that the sentencing
authority
Page 492 U. S. 327
would focus on the particularized circumstances of the crime and
the defendant."
Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U. S. 153,
428 U. S. 199
(1976) (joint opinion of Stewart, Powell, and STEVENS, JJ.). But as
we made clear in
Gregg, so long as the class of murderers
subject to capital punishment is narrowed, there is no
constitutional infirmity in a procedure that allows a jury to
recommend mercy based on the mitigating evidence introduced by a
defendant.
Id. at
428 U. S. 197-199,
428 U. S. 203.
As JUSTICE WHITE wrote in
Gregg:
"The Georgia legislature has plainly made an effort to guide the
jury in the exercise of its discretion, while at the same time
permitting the jury to dispense mercy on the basis of factors too
intangible to write into a statute, and I cannot accept the naked
assertion that the effort is bound to fail. As the types of murders
for which the death penalty may be imposed become more narrowly
defined and are limited to those which are particularly serious or
for which the death penalty is particularly appropriate, as they
are in Georgia by reason of the aggravating-circumstance
requirement, it becomes reasonable to expect that juries -- even
given discretion not to impose the death penalty -- will impose the
death penalty in a substantial portion of the cases so defined. If
they do, it can no longer be said that the penalty is being imposed
wantonly and freakishly or so infrequently that it loses its
usefulness as a sentencing device."
Id. at
428 U. S. 222
(opinion concurring in judgment).
"In contrast to the carefully defined standards that must narrow
a sentencer's discretion to
impose the death sentence, the
Constitution limits a State's ability to narrow a sentencer's
discretion to consider relevant evidence that might cause it to
decline to impose the death sentence."
McCleskey v. Kemp, 481 U. S. 279,
481 U. S. 304
(1987) (emphasis in original). Indeed, it is precisely because the
punishment should be directly related to the personal culpability
of the defendant that the jury must be allowed to consider and
give
Page 492 U. S. 328
effect to mitigating evidence relevant to a defendant's
character or record or the circumstances of the offense. Rather
than creating the risk of an unguided emotional response, full
consideration of evidence that mitigates against the death penalty
is essential if the jury is to give a "
reasoned moral response
to the defendant's background, character, and crime.'"
Franklin, 487 U.S. at 487 U. S. 184
(O'CONNOR, J., concurring in judgment) (quoting California v.
Brown, 479 U.S. at 479 U. S. 545
(O'CONNOR, J., concurring)). In order to ensure "reliability in the
determination that death is the appropriate punishment in a
specific case," Woodson, 428 U.S. at 428 U. S. 305,
the jury must be able to consider and give effect to any mitigating
evidence relevant to a defendant's background and character or the
circumstances of the crime.
In this case, in the absence of instructions informing the jury
that it could consider and give effect to the mitigating evidence
of Penry's mental retardation and abused background by declining to
impose the death penalty, we conclude that the jury was not
provided with a vehicle for expressing its "reasoned moral
response" to that evidence in rendering its sentencing decision.
Our reasoning in
Lockett and
Eddings thus compels
a remand for resentencing, so that we do not "risk that the death
penalty will be imposed in spite of factors which may call for a
less severe penalty."
Lockett, 438 U.S. at
438 U. S. 605;
Eddings, 455 U.S. at
455 U. S. 119
(O'CONNOR, J., concurring).
"When the choice is between life and death, that risk is
unacceptable and incompatible with the commands of the Eighth and
Fourteenth Amendments."
Lockett, 438 U.S. at
438 U. S.
605.
IV
Penry's second claim is that it would be cruel and unusual
punishment, prohibited by the Eighth Amendment, to execute a
mentally retarded person like himself with the reasoning capacity
of a 7-year-old. He argues that, because of their mental
disabilities, mentally retarded people do not possess the level of
moral culpability to justify imposing the death
Page 492 U. S. 329
sentence. He also argues that there is an emerging national
consensus against executing the retarded, and that existing
procedural safeguards adequately protect the interests of mentally
retarded persons such as Penry.
A
Under
Teague, we address the retroactivity issue as a
threshold matter because Penry is before us on collateral review.
489 U.S. at
489 U. S. 310.
If we were to hold that the Eighth Amendment prohibits the
execution of mentally retarded persons such as Penry, we would be
announcing a "new rule."
Id. at
489 U. S. 301.
Such a rule is not dictated by precedent existing at the time
Penry's conviction became final. Moreover, such a rule would
"brea[k] new ground," and would impose a new obligation on the
States and the Federal Government.
Ibid. (citing
Ford
v. Wainwight, 477 U. S. 399
(1986), which held that the Eighth Amendment prohibits the
execution of insane persons, as a case announcing a new rule).
In
Teague, we concluded that a new rule will not be
applied retroactively to defendants on collateral review unless it
falls within one of two exceptions. Under the first exception
articulated by Justice Harlan, a new rule will be retroactive if it
places "
certain kinds of primary, private individual conduct
beyond the power of the criminal lawmaking authority to
proscribe.'" Teague, 489 U.S. at 489 U. S. 307
(quoting Mackey, 401 U.S. at 401 U. S. 692
(Harlan, J., concurring in judgments in part and dissenting in
part)). Although Teague reads this exception as focusing
solely on new rules according constitutional protection to an
actor's primary conduct, Justice Harlan did speak in terms of
substantive categorical guarantees accorded by the Constitution,
regardless of the procedures followed. This Court subsequently held
that the Eighth Amendment, as a substantive matter, prohibits
imposing the death penalty on a certain class of defendants because
of their
Page 492 U. S. 330
status,
Ford v. Wainwright, supra, at
477 U. S. 410
(insanity), or because of the nature of their offense,
Coker v.
Georgia, 433 U. S. 584
(1977) (rape) (plurality opinion). In our view, a new rule placing
a certain class of individuals beyond the State's power to punish
by death is analogous to a new rule placing certain conduct beyond
the State's power to punish at all. In both cases, the Constitution
itself deprives the State of the power to impose a certain penalty,
and the finality and comity concerns underlying Justice Harlan's
view of retroactivity have little force. As Justice Harlan wrote:
"There is little societal interest in permitting the criminal
process to rest at a point where it ought properly never to
repose."
Mackey, 401 U.S. at
401 U. S. 693.
Therefore, the first exception set forth in
Teague should
be understood to cover not only rules forbidding criminal
punishment of certain primary conduct, but also rules prohibiting a
certain category of punishment for a class of defendants because of
their status or offense. Thus, if we held, as a substantive matter,
that the Eighth Amendment prohibits the execution of mentally
retarded persons such as Penry regardless of the procedures
followed, such a rule would fall under the first exception to the
general rule of nonretroactivity and would be applicable to
defendants on collateral review. Accordingly, we address the merits
of Penry's claim.
B
The Eighth Amendment categorically prohibits the infliction of
cruel and unusual punishments. At a minimum, the Eighth Amendment
prohibits punishment considered cruel and unusual at the time the
Bill of Rights was adopted.
Ford v. Wainwright, supra, at
477 U. S. 405;
Solem v. Helm, 463 U. S. 277,
462 U. S.
285-286 (1983). The prohibitions of the Eighth Amendment
are not limited, however, to those practices condemned by the
common law in 1789.
Ford, supra, at
477 U. S. 406;
Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. at
428 U. S. 171.
The prohibition against cruel and unusual punishments also
recognizes the "evolving standards
Page 492 U. S. 331
of decency that mark the progress of a maturing society."
Trop v. Dulles, 356 U. S. 86,
356 U. S. 101
(1958) (plurality opinion);
Ford, supra, at
477 U. S. 406.
In discerning those "evolving standards," we have looked to
objective evidence of how our society views a particular punishment
today.
See Coker v. Georgia, 433 U.S. at
433 U. S.
593-597;
Enmund v. Florida, 458 U.
S. 782,
458 U. S.
788-796 (1982). The clearest and most reliable objective
evidence of contemporary values is the legislation enacted by the
country's legislatures. We have also looked to data concerning the
actions of sentencing juries.
Enmund, supra, at
458 U. S.
794-796;
Thompson v. Oklahoma, 487 U.
S. 815,
487 U. S. 831
(1988) (plurality opinion).
It was well settled at common law that "idiots," together with
"lunatics," were not subject to punishment for criminal acts
committed under those incapacities. As Blackstone wrote:
"The second case of a deficiency in will, which excuses from the
guilt of crimes, arises also from a defective or vitiated
understanding, viz. in an
idiot or a
lunatic. . .
. [I]diots and lunatics are not chargeable for their own acts, if
committed when under these incapacities: no, not even for treason
itself. . . . [A] total idiocy, or absolute insanity, excuses from
the guilt, and of course from the punishment, of any criminal
action committed under such deprivation of the senses. . . ."
4 W. Blackstone, Commentaries *24-*25 (emphasis in original).
See also 1 W. Hawkins, Pleas of the Crown 1-2 (7th ed.
1795) ("[T]hose who are under a natural disability of
distinguishing between good and evil, as . . . ideots, and
lunaticks are not punishable by any criminal prosecution
whatsoever"). Idiocy was understood as "a defect of understanding
from the moment of birth," in contrast to lunacy, which was "a
partial derangement of the intellectual faculties, the senses
returning at uncertain intervals."
Id. at 2, n. 2.
There was no one definition of idiocy at common law, but the
term "idiot" was generally used to describe persons who
Page 492 U. S. 332
had a total lack of reason or understanding, or an inability to
distinguish between good and evil. Hale wrote that a person who is
deaf and mute from birth
"is in presumption of law an ideot . . . because he hath no
possibility to understand what is forbidden by law to be done, or
under what penalties: but if it can appear, that he hath the use of
understanding, . . . then he may be tried, and suffer judgment and
execution."
M. Hale, Pleas of the Crown 34 (1736) (footnote omitted).
See also id. at 29 (citing A. Fitzherbert, 2 Natura
Brevium 233 (9th ed. 1794)); Trial of Edward Arnold, 16 How.St.Tr.
695, 765 (Eng.1724) ("[A] man that is totally deprived of his
understanding and memory, and doth not know what he is doing, no
more than an infant, than a brute, or a wild beast, such a one is
never the object of punishment"); S. Glueck, Mental Disorder and
the Criminal Law 128-144 (1925).
The common law prohibition against punishing "idiots" and
"lunatics" for criminal acts was the precursor of the insanity
defense, which today generally includes "mental defect" as well as
"mental disease" as part of the legal definition of insanity.
See, e.g., American Law Institute, Model Penal Code ยง4.01,
p. 61 (1985) ("A person is not responsible for criminal conduct if
at the time of such conduct as a result of mental disease or defect
he lacks substantial capacity either to appreciate the criminality
[wrongfulness] of his conduct or to conform his conduct to the
requirements of law"); 18 U.S. C. ยง17 (1982 ed., Supp. V) (it is an
affirmative defense to federal prosecution if "the defendant, as a
result of a severe mental disease or defect, was unable to
appreciate the nature and quality or the wrongfulness of his acts"
at the time the offense was committed).
See generally
Ellis & Luckasson, Mentally Retarded Criminal Defendants, 53
Geo.Wash.L.Rev. 414, 432-444 (1985).
In its emphasis on a permanent, congenital mental deficiency,
the old common law notion of "idiocy" bears some similarity to the
modern definition of mental retardation. Ellis & Luckasson,
supra, at 417. The common law prohibition
Page 492 U. S. 333
against punishing "idiots" generally applied, however, to
persons of such severe disability that they lacked the reasoning
capacity to form criminal intent or to understand the difference
between good and evil. In the 19th and early 20th centuries, the
term "idiot" was used to describe the most retarded of persons,
corresponding to what is called "profound" and "severe" retardation
today.
See AAMR, Classification in Mental Retardation 179
(H. Grossman ed. 1983);
id. at 9 ("idiots" generally had
IQ of 25 or below).
The common law prohibition against punishing "idiots" for their
crimes suggests that it may indeed be "cruel and unusual"
punishment to execute persons who are profoundly or severely
retarded and wholly lacking the capacity to appreciate the
wrongfulness of their actions. Because of the protections afforded
by the insanity defense today, such a person is not likely to be
convicted or face the prospect of punishment.
See ABA
Standards for Criminal Justice 7-9.1, commentary, p. 460 (2d ed.
1980) (most retarded people who reach the point of sentencing are
mildly retarded). Moreover, under
Ford v. Wainwright,
477 U. S. 399
(1986), someone who is "unaware of the punishment they are about to
suffer and why they are to suffer it" cannot be executed.
Id. at
477 U. S. 422
(Powell, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment).
Such a case is not before us today. Penry was found competent to
stand trial. In other words, he was found to have the ability to
consult with his lawyer with a reasonable degree of rational
understanding, and was found to have a rational as well as factual
understanding of the proceedings against him.
Dusky v. United
States, 362 U. S. 402
(1960); App. 20-24. In addition, the jury rejected his insanity
defense, which reflected their conclusion that Penry knew that his
conduct was wrong, and was capable of conforming his conduct to the
requirements of the law. Tex.Penal Code Ann. ยง8.01(a) (1974 and
Supp. 1989).
Penry argues, however, that there is objective evidence today of
an emerging national consensus against execution of
Page 492 U. S. 334
the mentally retarded, reflecting the "evolving standards of
decency that mark the progress of a maturing society."
Trop v.
Dulles, 356 U.S. at
356 U. S. 101.
Brief for Petitioner 37-39. The federal Anti-Drug Abuse Act of
1988, Pub.L. 100-690, ยง 7001(1), 102 Stat. 4390, 21 U.S.C. ยง848(1)
(1988 ed.), prohibits execution of a person who is mentally
retarded. Only one State, however, currently bans execution of
retarded persons who have been found guilty of a capital offense.
Ga.Code Ann. ยง17-7-131(j) (Supp.1988). Maryland has enacted a
similar statute which will take effect on July 1, 1989.
Md.Ann.Code, Art. 27, ยง412(f)(1) (1989).
In contrast, in
Ford v. Wainwright, which held that the
Eighth Amendment prohibits execution of the insane, considerably
more evidence of a national consensus was available. No State
permitted the execution of the insane, and 26 States had statutes
explicitly requiring suspension of the execution of a capital
defendant who became insane.
Ford, 477 U.S. at
477 U. S. 408,
n. 2. Other States had adopted the common law prohibition against
executing the insane.
Ibid. Moreover, in examining the
objective evidence of contemporary standards of decency in
Thompson v. Oklahoma, the plurality noted that 18 States
expressly established a minimum age in their death penalty
statutes, and all of them required that the defendant have attained
at least the age of 16 at the time of the offense. 487 U.S. at
487 U. S. 829,
and n. 30. In our view, the two state statutes prohibiting
execution of the mentally retarded, even when added to the 14
States that have rejected capital punishment completely, do not
provide sufficient evidence at present of a national consensus.
Penry does not offer any evidence of the general behavior of
juries with respect to sentencing mentally retarded defendants, nor
of decisions of prosecutors. He points instead to several public
opinion surveys that indicate strong public opposition to execution
of the retarded. For example, a poll taken in Texas found that 86%
of those polled supported the death penalty, but 73% opposed its
application to the mentally
Page 492 U. S. 335
retarded. Reply Brief for Petitioner 6-7; Austin American
Statesman, November 15, 1988, p. B3. A Florida poll found 71% of
those surveyed were opposed to the execution of mentally retarded
capital defendants, while only 12% were in favor. Brief for
Petitioner 38; App. 279. A Georgia poll found 66% of those polled
opposed to the death penalty for the retarded, 17% in favor, with
16% responding that it depends how retarded the person is. Brief
for Petitioner 38; App. 283. In addition, the AAMR, the country's
oldest and largest organization of professionals working with the
mentally retarded, opposes the execution of persons who are
mentally retarded. AAMR, Resolution on Mental Retardation and the
Death Penalty, January 1988, App. to Brief for American Association
on Mental Retardation
et al. as Amici Curiae
la-2a
(hereafter Amici
Brief for AAMR et al.). The public
sentiment expressed in these and other polls and resolutions may
ultimately find expression in legislation, which is an objective
indicator of contemporary values upon which we can rely. But at
present, there is insufficient evidence of a national consensus
against executing mentally retarded people convicted of capital
offenses for us to conclude that it is categorically prohibited by
the Eighth Amendment.
C
Relying largely on objective evidence such as the judgments of
legislatures and juries, we have also considered whether
application of the death penalty to particular categories of crimes
or classes of offenders violates the Eighth Amendment because
it
"makes no measurable contribution to acceptable goals of
punishment, and hence is nothing more than the purposeless and
needless imposition of pain and suffering"
or because it is "grossly out of proportion to the severity of
the crime."
Coker v. Georgia, 433 U.S. at
433 U. S. 592
(plurality opinion);
Thompson v. Oklahoma, 487 U.S. at 833
(plurality opinion);
Tison v. Arizona, 481 U.
S. 137 (1987);
Enmund v. Florida, 458 U.S. at
458 U. S.
798-801.
Gregg noted
Page 492 U. S. 336
that
"[t]he death penalty is said to serve two principal social
purposes: retribution and deterrence of capital crimes by
prospective offenders."
Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. at
428 U. S. 183
(joint opinion of Stewart, Powell, and STEVENS, JJ.).
"The heart of the retribution rationale is that a criminal
sentence must be directly related to the personal culpability of
the criminal offender."
Tison v. Arizona, supra, at
481 U. S. 149.
See also Enmund, supra, at
458 U. S. 825
(O'CONNOR, J., dissenting) (the Eighth Amendment concept of
"proportionality requires a nexus between the punishment imposed
and the defendant's blameworthiness").
Penry argues that execution of a mentally retarded person like
himself with a reasoning capacity of approximately a 7-year-old
would be cruel and unusual because it is disproportionate to his
degree of personal culpability. Brief for Petitioner 49-50. Just as
the plurality in
Thompson reasoned that a juvenile is less
culpable than an adult for the same crime, 487 U.S. at
487 U. S. 835,
Penry argues that mentally retarded people do not have the
judgment, perspective, and self-control of a person of normal
intelligence. In essence, Penry argues that, because of his
diminished ability to control his impulses, to think in long-range
terms, and to learn from his mistakes, he "is not capable of acting
with the degree of culpability that can justify the ultimate
penalty,"
id. at
487 U. S.
823.
The AAMR and other groups working with the mentally retarded
agree with Penry. They argue as
amici that all mentally
retarded people, regardless of their degree of retardation, have
substantial cognitive and behavioral disabilities that reduce their
level of blameworthiness for a capital offense.
Amici
Brief for AAMR
et al. 5-9, 13-15.
Amici do not
argue that people with mental retardation cannot be held
responsible or punished for criminal acts they commit. Rather, they
contend that, because of
"disability in the areas of cognitive impairment, moral
reasoning, control of impulsivity, and the ability to understand
basic relationships between cause and effect,"
mentally retarded people cannot act
Page 492 U. S. 337
with the level of moral culpability that would justify
imposition of the death sentence.
Id. at 4. Thus, in their
view, execution of mentally retarded people convicted of capital
offenses serves no valid retributive purpose.
Id. at
19.
It is clear that mental retardation has long been regarded as a
factor that may diminish an individual's culpability for a criminal
act.
See supra, at
492 U. S.
331-333; ABA Standards for Criminal Justice 7-9.3,
commentary, at 463;
State v. Hall, 176 Neb. 295, 310,
125 N.W.2d
918, 927 (1964).
See generally Ellis & Luckasson,
53 Geo.Wash.L.Rev. at 414. In its most severe forms, mental
retardation may result in complete exculpation from criminal
responsibility. Moreover, virtually all of the States with death
penalty statutes that list statutory mitigating factors include as
a mitigating circumstance evidence that
"[t]he capacity of the defendant to appreciate the criminality
of his conduct or to conform his conduct to the requirements of law
was substantially impaired. [
Footnote 2]"
A number of States explicitly mention "mental defect" in
connection with such a mitigating circumstance. [
Footnote 3] Indeed, as the Court holds in
492 U. S. the
sentencing body must be allowed to consider mental retardation
Page 492 U. S. 338
as a mitigating circumstance in making the individualized
determination whether death is the appropriate punishment in a
particular case.
On the record before the Court today, however, I cannot conclude
that all mentally retarded people of Penry's ability -- by virtue
of their mental retardation alone, and apart from any
individualized consideration of their personal responsibility --
inevitably lack the cognitive, volitional, and moral capacity to
act with the degree of culpability associated with the death
penalty. Mentally retarded persons are individuals whose abilities
and experiences can vary greatly. As the AAMR's standard work,
Classification in Mental Retardation, points out:
"The term
mental retardation, as commonly used today,
embraces a heterogeneous population, ranging from totally dependent
to nearly independent people. Although all individuals so
designated share the common attributes of low intelligence and
inadequacies in adaptive behavior, there are marked variations in
the degree of deficit manifested and the presence or absence of
associated physical handicaps, stigmata, and psychologically
disordered states."
Classification in Mental Retardation, at 12. In addition to the
varying degrees of mental retardation, the consequences of a
retarded person's mental impairment, including the deficits in his
or her adaptive behavior, "may be ameliorated through education and
habilitation." Ellis & Luckasson,
supra, at 424, n.
54. Although retarded persons generally have difficulty learning
from experience,
Amici Brief for AAMR
et al. 7,
some are fully "capable of learning, working, and living in their
communities."
Id. at 6.
See American Association
on Mental Deficiency, Monograph 6, Lives in Process: Mildly
Retarded Adults in a Large City (R. Edgerton ed. 1984). In light of
the diverse capacities and life experiences of mentally retarded
persons, it cannot be said on the record before us today that all
mentally retarded
Page 492 U. S. 339
people, by definition, can never act with the level of
culpability associated with the death penalty.
Penry urges us to rely on the concept of "mental age," and to
hold that execution of any person with a mental age of seven or
below would constitute cruel and unusual punishment. Tr. of Oral
Arg. 22-25. Mental age is "calculated as the chronological age of
nonretarded children whose average IQ test performance is
equivalent to that of the individual with mental retardation."
Amici Brief for AAMR
et al. 14, n. 6.
See D. Wechsler, The Measurement and Appraisal of Adult
Intelligence 24-25 (4th ed. 1958). Such a rule should not be
adopted today. First, there was no finding below by the judge or
jury concerning Penry's "mental age." One of Penry's expert
witnesses, Dr. Brown, testified that he estimated Penry's "mental
age" to be 6 1/2. App. 41. That same expert estimated that Penry's
"social maturity" was that of a 9- or 10-year-old.
Ibid.
As a more general matter, the "mental age" concept, irrespective of
its intuitive appeal, is problematic in several respects. As the
AAMR acknowledges, "[t]he equivalence between nonretarded children
and retarded adults is, of course, imprecise."
Amici Brief
for AAMR
et al. 14, n. 6. The "mental age" concept may
underestimate the life experiences of retarded adults, while it may
overestimate the ability of retarded adults to use logic and
foresight to solve problems.
Ibid. The mental age concept
has other limitations as well. Beyond the chronological age of 15
or 16, the mean scores on most intelligence tests cease to increase
significantly with age. Wechsler,
supra, at 26. As a
result, "[t]he average mental age of the average 20-year-old is not
20, but 15 years."
Id. at 27.
See also In re Ramon
M., 22 Cal. 3d
419, 429, 584 P.2d 524, 531 (1978) ("[T]he
mental age' of
the average adult under present norms is approximately 16 years and
8 months").
Not surprisingly, courts have long been reluctant to rely on the
concept of mental age as a basis for exculpating a defendant from
criminal responsibility.
See, e.g., In re
Page 492 U. S. 340
Ramon M., supra, at 531;
State v. Schilling,
95 N.J.L. 145, 148, 112 A. 400, 402 (1920);
People v.
Marquis, 344 Ill. 261, 267, 176 N.E. 314, 316 (1931);
Chriswell v. State, 171 Ark. 255, 259, 283 S.W. 981, 983
(1926).
Cf. Pickett v. State, 71 So. 2d
102,
107
(Ala.1954).
See generally Ellis & Luckasson, 53
Geo.Wash.L.Rev., at 435. Moreover, reliance on mental age to
measure the capabilities of a retarded person for purposes of the
Eighth Amendment could have a disempowering effect if applied in
other areas of the law. Thus, on that premise, a mildly mentally
retarded person could be denied the opportunity to enter into
contracts or to marry by virtue of the fact that he had a "mental
age" of a young child. In light of the inherent problems with the
mental age concept, and in the absence of better evidence of a
national consensus against execution of the retarded, mental age
should not be adopted as a line-drawing principle in our Eighth
Amendment jurisprudence.
In sum, mental retardation is a factor that may well lessen a
defendant's culpability for a capital offense. But we cannot
conclude today that the Eighth Amendment precludes the execution of
any mentally retarded person of Penry's ability convicted of a
capital offense simply by virtue of his or her mental retardation
alone. So long as sentencers can consider and give effect to
mitigating evidence of mental retardation in imposing sentence, an
individualized determination whether "death is the appropriate
punishment" can be made in each particular case. While a national
consensus against execution of the mentally retarded may someday
emerge reflecting the "evolving standards of decency that mark the
progress of a maturing society," there is insufficient evidence of
such a consensus today.
Accordingly, the judgment below is affirmed in part and reversed
in part, and the case is remanded for further proceedings
consistent with this opinion.
It is so ordered.
Page 492 U. S. 341
[
Footnote 1]
Persons who are mentally retarded are described as having
"significantly subaverage general intellectual functioning
existing concurrently with deficits in adaptive behavior and
manifested during the developmental period."
American Association on Mental Deficiency (now Retardation)
(AAMR), Classification in Mental Retardation 1 (H. Grossman ed.
1983). To be classified as mentally retarded, a person generally
must have an IQ of 70 or below.
Id. at 11. Under the AAMR
classification system, individuals with IQ scores between 50-55 and
70 have "mild" retardation. Individuals with scores between 35-40
and 50-55 have "moderate" retardation. "Severely" retarded people
have IQ scores between 20-25 and 35-40, and "profoundly" retarded
people have scores below 20 or 25.
Id. at 13.
Approximately 89% of retarded persons are "mildly" retarded. Ellis
& Luckasson, Mentally Retarded Criminal Defendants, 53
Geo.Wash.L.Rev. 414, 423 (1985).
[
Footnote 2]
Ala. Code ยง13A-5-51(6) (1982).
See also
Ariz.Rev.Stat.Ann. ยง13702(E)(2) (Supp. 1988); Colo.Rev.Stat.
ยง16-11-103(5)(b) (1986 and Supp.1988); Conn.Gen.Stat.
ยง53a-46a(g)(2) (1989); Fla.Stat. ยง921.141(6)(f) (1987); Miss.Code
Ann. ยง99-19-101(6)(f) (Supp.1988); Mo.Rev.Stat. ยง 565.032(3)(6)
(1986); Mont.Code Ann. ยง 46-18-304(4) (1987); N.H.Rev.Stat.Ann. ยง
630:5(II)(b)(4) (1986); N.M.Stat.Ann. ยง 31-20A-6(C) (1987);
N.C.Gen.Stat. ยง15A-2000(f)(6) (1988); 42 Pa.Cons.Stat. ยง9711(e)(3)
(1982); S.C.Code ยง16-3-20(C)(b)(6) (1985); Va.Code
ยง19.2-264.4(B)(iv) (1983); Wyo.Stat. ยง 6-2-102(j)(vi) (1988).
[
Footnote 3]
Ark.Code Ann. ยง 5-4-605(3) (1987); Cal.Penal Code Ann. ยง190.3(h)
(West 1988); Ky.Rev.Stat.Ann. ยง 532.025(2)(b)7 (Baldwin 1984);
La.Code Crim.Proc.Ann., Art. 905.5(e) (West 1984); Neb.Rev.Stat.
ยง29-2523 (2)(g) (1985); N.J.Stat. Ann. ยง 2C:11-3(c)(5)(d) (West
Supp. 1988); Ohio Rev.Code Ann. ยง 2929.04(B)(3) (1987); Tenn.Code
Ann. ยง 39-2-203 (j)(8) (1982), Wash.Rev.Code ยง10.95.070(6) (1987).
Other formulations are used in Ind.Code ยง 35-50-2-9(c)(6) (1988);
Md.Ann.Code, Art. 27, ยง 413(g)(4) (1988); and Utah Code Ann. ยง
76-3-207(2)(d) (Supp. 1988).
JUSTICE BRENNAN, with whom JUSTICE MARSHALL joins, concurring in
part and dissenting in part.
I agree that the jury instructions given at sentencing in this
case deprived petitioner of his constitutional right to have a jury
consider all mitigating evidence that he presented before
sentencing him to die. I would also hold, however, that the Eighth
Amendment prohibits the execution of offenders who are mentally
retarded, and who thus lack the full degree of responsibility for
their crimes that is a predicate for the constitutional imposition
of the death penalty.
I
I dissented in
Teague v. Lane, 489 U.
S. 288,
489 U. S. 326
(1989), and I continue to believe that the plurality's
unprecedented curtailment of the reach of the Great Writ in that
case was without foundation. The
Teague plurality adopted
for no adequate reason a novel threshold test for federal review of
state criminal convictions that, subject to narrow exceptions,
precludes federal courts from considering a vast array of important
federal questions on collateral review, and thereby both prevents
the vindication of personal constitutional rights and deprives our
society of a significant safeguard against future violations. In
this case, the Court compounds its error by extending
Teague's notion that new rules will not generally be
announced on collateral review to cases in which a habeas
petitioner challenges the constitutionality of a capital sentencing
procedure. This extension means that a person may be killed
although he or she has a sound constitutional claim that would have
barred his or her execution had this Court only announced the
constitutional rule before his or her conviction and sentence
became final. It is intolerable that the difference between life
and death should turn on such a fortuity of timing, and beyond my
comprehension that a majority of this Court will so blithely allow
a State to take a human life though the method by which sentence
was determined violates our Constitution.
Page 492 U. S. 342
I say the Court takes this step "blithely" advisedly. The Court
extends
Teague without the benefit of briefing or oral
argument.
Teague, indeed, was decided only after we had
heard argument in this case. Rather than postponing decision on the
important issue whether
Teague should be extended to
capital cases until it is presented in a case in which it may be
briefed and argued, the Court rushes to decide
Teague's
applicability in such circumstances here. It does so in two
sentences,
ante at
492 U. S.
313-314, saying merely that not to apply
Teague
would result in delay in killing the prisoner and in a lack of
finality. There is not the least hint that the Court has even
considered whether different rules might be called for in capital
cases, let alone any sign of reasoning justifying the extension.
Such peremptory treatment of the issue is facilitated, of course,
by the Court's decision to reach the
Teague question
without allowing counsel to set out the opposing arguments.
Though I believe
Teague was wrongly decided, and the
Court's precipitous decision to extend
Teague to capital
cases an error, nevertheless, if these mistakes are to be made law,
I agree that the Court's discussion of the question whether the
jury had an opportunity to consider Penry's mitigating evidence in
answering Texas' three "special issues" does not establish a "new
rule." I thus join Part II-B of the Court's opinion, and all of
Parts I and III. I also agree that there is an exception to
Teague so that new rules "prohibiting a certain category
of punishment for a class of defendants because of their status or
offense" may be announced in, and applied to, cases on collateral
review.
Ante at
492 U. S. 330.
I thus join Part IV-A of the Court's opinion.
II
A majority of the Court today reaffirms, in this case and in
Stanford v. Kentucky, post at
492 U. S. 382
(O'CONNOR, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment);
post at
492 U. S. 393
(BRENNAN, J., dissenting), the well-established principle that
Page 492 U. S. 343
"application of the death penalty to particular categories of
crimes or classes of offenders violates the Eighth Amendment [if]
it"
"makes no measurable contribution to acceptable goals of
punishment and hence is nothing more than the purposeless and
needless imposition of pain and suffering"
"or [if] it is 'grossly out of proportion to the severity of the
crime."
Ante at
492 U. S. 335
(opinion of O'CONNOR, J.), quoting
Coker v. Georgia,
433 U. S. 584,
433 U. S. 592
(1977). The contours of these these two inquiries are clear. We
gauge whether a punishment is disproportionate by comparing "the
gravity of the offense," understood to include not only the injury
caused, but also the defendant's moral culpability, with "the
harshness of the penalty."
Solem v. Helm, 463 U.
S. 277,
463 U. S. 292
(1983).
See ante at
492 U. S. 336;
Stanford, post at
492 U. S. 382 (O'CONNOR, J., concurring in part and
concurring in judgment);
post at
492 U. S.
393-394 (BRENNAN, J., dissenting);
Thompson v.
Oklahoma, 487 U. S. 815,
487 U. S. 834
(1988) (plurality opinion);
id. at
487 U. S. 853
(opinion of O'CONNOR, J.);
Coker, supra, at
433 U. S. 598;
Enmund v. Florida, 458 U. S. 782,
458 U. S. 798
(1982) (opinion of the Court);
id. at
458 U. S. 815
(O'CONNOR, J., dissenting). And we require that a punishment
further the penal goals of deterrence or retribution.
Ante
at
492 U. S.
335-336;
Stanford, post at
492 U.S. 403 (BRENNAN, J., dissenting);
Thompson, supra, at
487 U. S. 836
(plurality opinion);
Enmund, supra, at
458 U. S. 798;
Coker, supra, at
433 U. S. 592;
Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U. S. 153,
428 U. S. 183
(1976) (opinion of Stewart, Powell, and STEVENS, JJ.). In my view,
execution of the mentally retarded is unconstitutional under both
these strands of Eighth Amendment analysis.
A
I agree with JUSTICE O'CONNOR that one question to be asked in
determining whether the execution of mentally retarded offenders is
always unconstitutional because disproportionate is whether the
mentally retarded, as a class,
"by virtue of their mental retardation alone, . . . inevitably
lack the cognitive, volitional, and moral capacity to act with
the
Page 492 U. S. 344
degree of culpability associated with the death penalty."
Ante at
492 U. S. 338.
JUSTICE O'CONNOR answers that question in the negative, "[i]n light
of the diverse capacities and life experiences of mentally retarded
persons."
Ibid. It seems to me that the evidence compels a
different conclusion.
For many purposes, legal and otherwise, to treat the mentally
retarded as a homogeneous group is inappropriate, bringing the risk
of false stereotyping and unwarranted discrimination.
See
Ellis & Luckasson, Mentally Retarded Criminal Defendants, 53
Geo.Wash.L.Rev. 414, 427 (1985). Nevertheless, there are
characteristics as to which there is no danger of spurious
generalization because they are a part of the clinical definition
of mental retardation. "Mental retardation" is defined by the
American Association on Mental Retardation (AAMR) as
"significantly subaverage general intellectual functioning
existing concurrently with deficits in adaptive behavior and
manifested during the developmental period."
AAMR, Classification in Mental Retardation 11 (H. Grossman ed.
1983) (hereafter AAMR Classification). To fall within this
definition, an individual must be among the approximately two
percent of the population with an IQ below 70 on standardized
measures of intelligence,
see id. at 31, and
in
addition must be subject to
"significant limitations in [his or her] effectiveness in
meeting the standards of maturation, learning, personal
independence, and/or social responsibility that are expected for
his or her age level and cultural group,"
id. at 11;
see also id. at 76 (noting "the
imperfect correlation of intelligence and adaptive behavior,
especially at the upper ends of the intellectual range of
retardation"). Thus, while as between the mildly, moderately,
severely, and profoundly mentally retarded, with IQs ranging from
70 to below 20, there are indeed "marked variations in the degree
of deficit manifested," it is also true that
"
all individuals [designated as mentally retarded]
share the common attributes of
Page 492 U. S. 345
low intelligence and inadequacies in adaptive behavior."
Id. at 12 (emphasis added). [
Footnote 2/1]
In light of this clinical definition of mental retardation, I
cannot agree that the undeniable fact that mentally retarded
persons have "diverse capacities and life experiences,"
ante at
492 U. S. 338,
is of significance to the Eighth Amendment proportionality analysis
we must conduct in this case. "Every individual who has mental
retardation" -- irrespective of his or her precise capacities or
experiences -- has "a substantial disability in cognitive ability
and adaptive behavior." Brief for the AAMR
et al. as
Amici Curiae 5 (hereafter AAMR Brief). This is true even
of the "highest functioning individuals in the
mild'
retardation category," id. at 14, and of course of those
like Penry whose cognitive and behavioral disabilities place them
on the borderline between mild and moderate retardation. See
ante at 492 U. S.
307-308, and n. 1. Among the mentally retarded,
"reduced ability is found in every dimension of the individual's
functioning, including his language, communication, memory,
attention, ability to control impulsivity, moral development,
self-concept, self-perception, suggestibility, knowledge of basic
information, and general motivation."
AAMR Brief 6. Though individuals, particularly those who are
mildly retarded, may be quite capable of overcoming these
limitations to the extent of being able to "maintain
Page 492 U. S. 346
themselves independently or semi-independently in the
community," AAMR Classification 184;
see id. at 207-208,
nevertheless, the mentally retarded by definition "have a reduced
ability to cope with and function in the everyday world."
Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Center, Inc., 473 U.
S. 432,
473 U. S. 442
(1985). The impairment of a mentally retarded offender's reasoning
abilities, control over impulsive behavior, and moral development,
in my view, limits his or her culpability so that, whatever other
punishment might be appropriate, the ultimate penalty of death is
always and necessarily disproportionate to his or her
blameworthiness, and hence is unconstitutional. [
Footnote 2/2]
Even if mental retardation alone were not invariably associated
with a lack of the degree of culpability upon which death as a
proportionate punishment is predicated, I would still hold the
execution of the mentally retarded to be unconstitutional. If there
are among the mentally retarded exceptional individuals as
responsible for their actions as persons who suffer no such
disability, the individualized consideration afforded at sentencing
fails to ensure that they are the only mentally retarded offenders
who will be picked out to receive a death sentence. The
consideration of mental retardation as a mitigating factor is
inadequate to guarantee, as the Constitution
Page 492 U. S. 347
requires, that an individual who is not fully blameworthy for
his or her crime because of a mental disability does not receive
the death penalty.
That "sentencers can consider and give effect to mitigating
evidence of mental retardation in imposing sentence" provides no
assurance that an adequate individualized determination of whether
the death penalty is a proportionate punishment will be made at the
conclusion of each capital trial.
Ante at
492 U. S. 340.
At sentencing, the judge or jury considers an offender's level of
blameworthiness only along with a host of other factors that the
sentencer may decide outweigh any want of responsibility. The
sentencer is free to weigh a mentally retarded offender's relative
lack of culpability against the heinousness of the crime and other
aggravating factors, and to decide that even the most retarded and
irresponsible of offenders should die. Indeed, a sentencer will
entirely discount an offender's retardation as a factor mitigating
against imposition of a death sentence if it adopts this line of
reasoning:
"It appears to us that there is all the more reason to execute a
killer if he is also . . . retarded. Killers often kill again; [a]
retarded killer is more to be feared than a . . . normal killer.
There is also far less possibility of his ever becoming a useful
citizen."
Upholding Law and Order, Hartsville Messenger, June 24, 1987, p.
5B, col. 1 (approving death sentence imposed on mentally retarded
murderer by a South Carolina court). Lack of culpability as a
result of mental retardation is simply not isolated at the
sentencing stage as a factor that determinatively bars a death
sentence; for individualized consideration at sentencing is not
designed to ensure that mentally retarded offenders are not
sentenced to death if they are not culpable to the degree necessary
to render execution a proportionate response to their crimes. When
Johnny Penry is resentenced, absent a change in Texas law, there
will be nothing to prevent the jury, acting lawfully, from
Page 492 U. S. 348
sentencing him to death once again -- even though it finds his
culpability significantly reduced by reason of mental retardation.
I fail to see how that result is constitutional, in the face of the
acknowledged Eighth Amendment requirement of proportionality.
B
There is a second ground upon which I would conclude that the
execution of mentally retarded offenders violates the Eighth
Amendment: killing mentally retarded offenders does not measurably
further the penal goals of either retribution or deterrence.
"The heart of the retribution rationale is that a criminal
sentence must be directly related to the personal culpability of
the criminal offender."
Tison v. Arizona, 481 U. S. 137,
481 U. S. 149
(1987);
see also Enmund, 458 U.S. at
458 U. S. 800.
Since mentally retarded offenders as a class lack the culpability
that is a prerequisite to the proportionate imposition of the death
penalty, it follows that execution can never be the "just deserts"
of a retarded offender,
id. at
458 U. S. 801,
and that the punishment does not serve the retributive goal,
see Stanford, post at
492 U. S. 404
(BRENNAN, J., dissenting) ("A punishment that fails the Eighth
Amendment test of proportionality because disproportionate to the
offender's blameworthiness by definition is not justly
deserved").
Furthermore, killing mentally retarded offenders does not
measurably contribute to the goal of deterrence. It is highly
unlikely that the exclusion of the mentally retarded from the class
of those eligible to be sentenced to death will lessen any
deterrent effect the death penalty may have for nonretarded
potential offenders, for they, of course, will under present law
remain at risk of execution. And the very factors that make it
disproportionate and unjust to execute the mentally retarded also
make the death penalty of the most minimal deterrent effect so far
as retarded potential offenders are concerned. "[I]ntellectual
impairments . . . in logical reasoning, strategic thinking, and
foresight," the lack of the intellectual and developmental
predicates of an "ability to
Page 492 U. S. 349
anticipate consequences," and "impairment in the ability to
control impulsivity," AAMR Brief 6-7, mean that the possibility of
receiving the death penalty will not in the case of a mentally
retarded person figure in some careful assessment of different
courses of action.
See also id. at 7 ("[A] person who has
mental retardation often cannot independently generate in his mind
a sufficient range of behaviors from which to select an action
appropriate to the situation he faces (particularly a stressful
situation)"). In these circumstances, the execution of mentally
retarded individuals is "nothing more than the purposeless and
needless imposition of pain and suffering," Coker, 433 U.S. at
433 U. S. 592,
and is unconstitutional under the Eighth Amendment.
Because I believe that the Eighth Amendment to the United States
Constitution stands in the way of a State killing a mentally
retarded person for a crime for which, as a result of his or her
disability, he or she is not fully culpable, I would reverse the
judgment of the Court of Appeals in its entirety.
[
Footnote 2/1]
It is of course possible to classify those with developmental
disabilities in different ways. Indeed, the question on which
certiorari was granted in this case -- whether it violates the
Eighth Amendment "to execute an individual with the reasoning
capacity of a seven-year-old" -- concerned classification according
to mental age. Petitioner conflates mental age and the AAMR's
mental retardation classifications in his brief, and the Court
addresses both proposals for Eighth Amendment line-drawing. JUSTICE
O'CONNOR's opinion does not, however, preclude the possibility that
an Eighth Amendment line might be drawn using a classification that
encompasses only a more substantially disabled group than all those
within the AAMR's clinical definition of the mentally retarded, and
that lacks the problems JUSTICE O'CONNOR associates with the
concept of mental age,
ante at
492 U. S.
338-340.
[
Footnote 2/2]
Because a person's "mental age" is a factor only of his or her
IQ and of the average IQs of nonretarded children,
see
ante at
492 U. S. 339,
it is a less sophisticated and reliable guide to an individual's
abilities than the accepted standards for diagnosing mental
retardation, and must be supplemented with estimates of a person's
"social maturity" measured in comparison to that of nonretarded
children. In the present case, for example, there was testimony
that petitioner had a mental age of 6 1/2 and a social maturity
equivalent to that of a 9- or 10-year-old. This evidence surely
gives some insight into just what it is that Texas has proposed to
do in killing Penry. However, "[t]he equivalence between
nonretarded children and retarded adults is . . . imprecise," AAMR
Brief 14, n. 6, and it seems, on the basis of the information
before us, to be more appropriate to conduct proportionality
analysis by reference to the accepted clinical classification of
mental retardation than on the basis of age comparisons.
JUSTICE STEVENS, with whom JUSTICE BLACKMUN joins, concurring in
part and dissenting in part.
As I stated in my separate opinion in
Teague v. Lane,
489 U. S. 288,
489 U. S.
318-319, and n. 2 (1989), it is neither logical nor
prudent to consider a rule's retroactive application before the
rule itself is articulated. Nor am I at all sure that courts should
decide the retroactivity issue if it was not raised below.
Cf.
Zant v. Moore, 489 U. S. 836,
489 U. S. 837
(1989) (BLACKMUN, J., dissenting). Finally, I do not support the
Court's assertion, without benefit of argument or briefing on the
issue, that
Teague's retroactivity principles pertain to
capital cases.
Cf. Teague, 489 U.S. at
489 U. S. 321,
and n. 3 (STEVENS, J., concurring in part and concurring in
judgment). But assuming,
arguendo, that those principles
do apply, it is clear that the Court's discussion of the mitigating
evidence question, with which I agree, does not establish a "new
rule"
Page 492 U. S. 350
as that term is used for retroactivity purposes. I thus join
Parts I, II-B, and III.
In
492 U. S. the
Court decides that a rule that the Eighth Amendment prohibits the
execution of a mentally retarded person ought to apply
retroactively. Assuming retroactivity is pertinent, I agree that
the first exception to Justice Harlan's nonretroactivity
doctrine
"should be understood to cover not only rules forbidding
criminal punishment of certain primary conduct but also rules
prohibiting a certain category of punishment for a class of
defendants because of their status or offense,"
ante at
492 U. S. 330,
and that this claim lies within that exception.
*
The remaining sections of Part IV adequately and fairly state
the competing arguments respecting capital punishment of mentally
retarded persons. In my judgment, however, that explication --
particularly the summary of the arguments advanced in the Brief for
American Association on Mental Retardation
et al. as
Amici Curiae, ante at
492 U. S.
336-337 -- compels the conclusion that such executions
are unconstitutional. I would therefore reverse the judgment of the
Court of Appeals in its entirety.
* Because I believe that retroactivity should not be considered
until after a right is established,
see Teague v. Lane,
489 U. S. 288,
489 U. S.
318-319, and n. 2 (1989) (STEVENS, J., concurring in
part and concurring in judgment), the Court's rejection of this
claim ordinarily would preclude me from agreeing even for purposes
of argument that the rule Penry seeks may be applied retroactively.
I do so here because the Court has fleshed out the merits of
Penry's claim sufficiently to allow me to reach a contrary
conclusion.
JUSTICE SCALIA, with whom THE CHIEF JUSTICE, JUSTICE WHITE, and
JUSTICE KENNEDY join, concurring in part and dissenting in
part.
I
I join Part I of the Court's opinion, setting forth the facts
and procedural history of this case; Part II-A, holding that
Teague v. Lane, 489 U. S. 288
(1989), which precludes collateral
Page 492 U. S. 351
relief that would establish a "new rule," applies to capital
sentencing; and Part IV-A, holding that the exception to
Teague for a new rule that places certain matters
"
beyond the power of the criminal law-making authority,'"
id. at 492 U. S. 311,
quoting Mackey v. United States, 401 U.
S. 667, 401 U. S. 692
(1971) (separate opinion of Harlan, J.), applies to petitioner's
contention that the Eighth Amendment forbids the execution of
mentally retarded offenders. I also join Part IV-B, rejecting the
latter contention on the ground that execution of mentally retarded
offenders contravenes neither those practices condemned at the time
the Bill of Rights was adopted nor the "evolving standards of
decency that mark the progress of a maturing society." Trop v.
Dulles, 356 U. S. 86,
356 U. S. 101
(1958) (plurality opinion). Unlike JUSTICE O'CONNOR, however, I
think we need go no further to resolve the Eighth Amendment issue.
Part IV-C of her opinion goes on to examine whether application of
the death penalty to mentally retarded offenders
"violates the Eighth Amendment because it 'makes no measurable
contribution to acceptable goals of punishment, and hence is
nothing more than the purposeless and needless imposition of pain
and suffering' or because it is 'grossly out of proportion to the
severity of the crime.'"
Ante at
492 U. S. 335
(citations omitted). For the reasons explained by the plurality in
Stanford v. Kentucky, post p.
492 U. S. 361, I
think this inquiry has no place in our Eighth Amendment
jurisprudence. "The punishment is either
cruel and
unusual' (i.e., society has set its face against it) or it
is not." Post at 492 U. S. 378
(emphasis in original). If it is not unusual, that is, if an
objective examination of laws and jury determinations fails to
demonstrate society's disapproval of it, the punishment is not
unconstitutional even if out of accord with the theories of
penology favored by the Justices of this Court. See post
at 492 U. S.
379.
II
I disagree with the holding in
492 U.
S. that his sentencing was
Page 492 U. S. 352
unconstitutional because the Texas jury was not permitted fully
to consider and give effect to the mitigating evidence of his
mental retardation and background of abuse, does not seek the
application of a "new rule," and is therefore not barred by
Teague. I also disagree with the disposition of the merits
of this contention, in Part
492 U. S.
A
The merits of this mitigation issue, and the question whether,
in raising it on habeas, petitioner seeks application of a "new
rule" within the meaning of
Teague, are obviously
interrelated. I will say only a few words addressed exclusively to
the latter. Our holding in
Teague rested upon the historic
role of habeas corpus in our system of law, which is to provide a
"deterrence,"
"'the threat of [which] serves as a necessary additional
incentive for trial and appellate courts throughout the land to
conduct their proceedings in a manner consistent with established
constitutional standards.'"
489 U.S. at
489 U. S. 306,
quoting
Desist v. United States, 394 U.
S. 244,
394 U. S.
262-263 (1969) (Harlan, J., dissenting). "Deterrence"
and "threat" are meaningless concepts as applied to a situation in
which the law is so uncertain that a judge acting in all good faith
and with the greatest of care could reasonably read our precedents
as permitting the result the habeas petitioner contends is wrong.
Thus, a "new rule," for purposes of
Teague, must include
not only a new rule that replaces an old one, but a new rule that
replaces palpable uncertainty as to what the rule might be. We
acknowledged as much in
Teague (in a passage given
lip-service by the Court today,
see ante at
492 U.S. 314) when we said that "a case
announces a new rule if the result was not
dictated by
precedent existing at the time the defendant's conviction became
final." 489 U.S. at
489 U. S.
301.
As my discussion of the merits will make plain, it challenges
the imagination to think that today's result is "dictated" by our
prior cases. Indeed, if there is any available
Page 492 U. S. 353
contention that our prior cases
compelled a particular
result, it is the contention that petitioner's claim was considered
and rejected by
Jurek v. Texas, 428 U.
S. 262 (1976). Even if that contention is rejected,
however, there is no basis for finding a compulsion in the opposite
direction. It seems to me utterly impossible to say that a judge
acting in good faith and with care should have known the rule
announced today, and that future fault similar to that of which the
Texas courts have been guilty must be deterred by making good on
the "threat" of habeas corpus.
In a system based on precedent and
stare decisis, it is
the tradition to find each decision "inherent" in earlier cases
(however well concealed its presence might have been), and rarely
to replace a previously announced rule with a new one. If
Teague does not apply to a claimed "inherency" as vague
and debatable as that in the present case, then it applies only to
habeas requests for plain overruling -- which means that it adds
little if anything to the principles already in place concerning
the retroactivity of new rules in criminal cases, which provide
that "a decision announcing a new standard
is almost
automatically nonretroactive' where the decision `has explicitly
overruled past precedent.'" Allen v. Hardy, 478 U.
S. 255, 478 U. S. 258
(1986), quoting Solem v. Stumes, 465 U.
S. 638, 465 U. S. 646,
465 U. S. 647
(1984). It is rare that a principle of law as significant as that
in Teague is adopted and gutted in the same Term.
B
I turn next to the merits of petitioner's mitigation claim. In
Furman v. Georgia, 408 U. S. 238
(1972), we invalidated Georgia's capital punishment scheme on the
ground that, since there were no standards as to when it would be
applied for a particular crime, it created too great a risk that
the death penalty would be irrationally imposed. Four years later,
however, we struck down the capital sentencing schemes of North
Carolina and Louisiana for the opposite vice -- because they unduly
constricted sentencing discretion
Page 492 U. S. 354
by failing to allow for individualized consideration of the
particular defendant and offense,
see Woodson v. North
Carolina, 428 U. S. 280
(1976);
Roberts v. Louisiana, 428 U.
S. 325 (1976). On the same day, however, we upheld the
schemes of Georgia, Texas, and Florida, because they struck the
proper balance, channeling the sentencer's discretion without
unduly restricting it.
Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.
S. 153 (1976);
Jurek v. Texas, supra; Proffitt v.
Florida, 428 U. S. 242,
428 U. S. 253
(1976). The Texas system upheld in
Jurek was precisely the
same one the Court finds unacceptable today, which structures the
jury's discretion through three questions relating to the
defendant's personal culpability for the crime, his future
dangerousness, and the reasonableness of his response to any
provocation by the victim. In holding that this scheme
unconstitutionally limits the jury's discretion to consider the
mitigating evidence of Penry's mental retardation and abused
childhood, the Court today entirely disregards one of the two lines
of our concern, requiring individualized consideration to displace
the channeling of discretion, and throwing away
Jurek in
the process.
The Court contends that its conclusion is not inconsistent with
Jurek because that case merely upheld a facial challenge
to the Texas Special Issues framework. According to the Court, it
did not
"preclud[e] a claim that, in a particular case, the jury was
unable to fully consider the mitigating evidence introduced by a
defendant in answering the special issues."
Ante at
492 U. S. 321.
I disagree. While rejection of a facial challenge to a statute does
not preclude all as-applied attacks, surely it precludes one
resting upon the same asserted principle of law. And that is the
situation here. The joint opinion announcing the judgment in
Jurek (it is necessary only to describe the joint opinion,
since the three Justices subscribing to the opinion of JUSTICE
WHITE, 428 U.S. at
428 U. S. 277,
would have upheld the Texas statute on even broader grounds) said
that "the constitutionality of the Texas procedures turns on
whether the enumerated questions allow consideration of
Page 492 U. S. 355
particularized mitigating factors."
Id. at
428 U. S. 272.
The claim that the Court entertains and vindicates today flatly
contradicts that analysis, holding that the constitutionality turns
on whether the questions allow mitigating factors not only to be
considered (and, of course, given effect in answering the
questions),
but also to be given effect in all possible ways,
including ways that the questions do not permit. It is simply
not true that, as today's opinion asserts, the
Jurek Court
had before it
"the express assurance that the special issues would permit the
jury to fully consider all the mitigating evidence a defendant
introduced."
Ante at
492 U. S. 321.
What the Court means by "fully consider" (what it
must
mean to distinguish
Jurek) is to consider
for all
purposes, including purposes not specifically permitted by the
questions. But there was no such assurance at all. To the
contrary, the portion of the Texas Court of Criminal Appeals'
opinion quoted in
Jurek to evidence the assurance
began:
"'In determining the likelihood that the defendant would be a
continuing threat to society [
i.e., in considering the
second question under the Texas statute], the jury could consider .
. . [,]'"
428 U.S. at
428 U. S.
272-273, quoting
522
S.W.2d 934, 939-940 (1975). The same focus upon the use of
mitigating evidence for the limited purpose of answering the
enumerated questions, rather than upon the jury's ability to use it
for all purposes, is also evident in the joint opinion's statement
that
"[the] Texas Court of Criminal Appeals has not yet construed the
first and third questions . . . ; thus it is as yet undetermined
whether or not the jury's
consideration of those questions
would properly include consideration of mitigating
circumstances."
428 U.S. at
428 U. S. 272,
n. 7 (emphasis added).
In short, it could not be clearer that
Jurek adopted
the constitutional rule that the instructions had to render all
mitigating circumstances relevant to the jury's verdict, but that
the precise manner of their relevance -- the precise
effect of their consideration -- could be channeled by
law. The joint opinion approved the Texas statute expressly because
it "focuses the
Page 492 U. S. 356
jury's objective consideration of the particularized
circumstances of the individual offense and the individual
offender."
Id. at
428 U. S. 274. Of course, there remains available, in an
as-applied challenge to the Texas statute, the contention that a
particular mitigating circumstance is in fact irrelevant to any of
the three questions it poses, and hence could not be considered.
But that is not the case here, nor is it the ground upon which the
Court relies. Special Issue One required the jury to determine
whether
"the conduct of the defendant that caused the death of the
deceased was committed deliberately and with the reasonable
expectation that the death of the deceased or another would
result."
Ante at
492 U. S. 310.
As the plurality observed in
Franklin v. Lynaugh,
487 U. S. 164
(1988),
"[t]he Texas courts have consistently held that something more
must be found in the penalty phase -- something beyond the
guilt-phase finding of 'intentional' commission of the crime --
before the jury can determine that a capital murder is 'deliberate'
within the meaning of the first Special Issue."
Id. at
487 U. S.
171-175 (citing Texas cases). Evidence of Penry's mental
retardation and abused childhood was relevant to that point. He was
permitted to introduce all that evidence, relied upon it in urging
the jury to answer "no" to the Special Issues, and had the benefit
of an instruction specifically telling the jury to consider all
evidence for that purpose.
See App. 26. Thus, the only
available contention here, and the basis on which the Court decides
the case, is that this evidence "has relevance to . . . moral
culpability beyond the scope of the special issues."
Ante
at
492 U. S. 322.
That contention was considered and rejected by
Jurek's
holding that the statute's "focus[ing of] the jury's objective
consideration" was constitutional. 428 U.S. at
428 U. S.
274.
But even if petitioner's claim is not foreclosed by
Jurek, the Court clearly errs in asserting that our later
precedents "compe[l]" the conclusion that it is valid,
ante at
492 U. S. 328.
While it is true that our cases have held that "a death penalty
statute must not preclude consideration of relevant mitigating
Page 492 U. S. 357
factors," including "any aspect of a defendant's character or
record and any of the circumstances of the offense,"
Lockett v.
Ohio, 438 U. S. 586,
438 U. S. 604,
438 U. S. 608,
(1978);
see also Eddings v. Oklahoma, 455 U.
S. 104,
455 U. S.
110-112 (1982), we have never held that "the State has
no role in structuring or giving shape to the jury's consideration
of these mitigating factors."
Franklin, 487 U.S. at
487 U. S. 179.
As JUSTICE STEVENS pointed out in
Barclay v. Florida,
463 U. S. 939
(1983), neither
Lockett nor
Eddings
"establish[ed] the weight which must be given to any particular
mitigating evidence, or the manner in which it must be considered;
they simply condemn any procedure in which such evidence has no
weight at all."
Id. at
463 U. S. 961,
n. 2 (opinion concurring in judgment).
See also Zant v.
Stephens, 462 U. S. 862,
462 U. S.
875-876, n. 13 (1983) ("[S]pecific standards for
balancing aggravating against mitigating circumstances are not
constitutionally required").
We have held that a State may not make the death penalty
mandatory,
see Sumner v. Shuman, 483 U. S.
66 (1987);
Woodson, 428 U.
S. 280 (1976);
Roberts, 428 U.
S. 325 (1976), and that it may not affirmatively
preclude a sentencer from considering mitigating evidence presented
by a defendant,
see Hitchcock v. Dugger, 481 U.
S. 393 (1987);
Skipper v. South Carolina,
476 U. S. 1 (1986).
The sentences in
Eddings and
Lockett, the cases
upon which the Court principally relies, ran afoul of the latter
rule --
Eddings because the sentencing judge thought
Oklahoma law categorically prevented him from considering certain
mitigating evidence, and
Lockett because Ohio law limited
the mitigating factors to three, which on their face would not
embrace even such rudimentary elements as lack of intent to kill
the victim, the defendant's comparatively minor role in the
offense, and age. As we noted in
Jurek and the Court does
not contest today, Texas permits
all mitigating factors to
be considered, though only for purposes of answering the three
Special Issues (and there is no question that the specific
mitigation offered was relevant to at least one of them). That is
why the
Lockett
Page 492 U. S. 358
Court found the Texas statute "significantly different" from the
Ohio scheme. 438 U.S. at
438 U. S. 607.
And that is why we have continued to say, after
Eddings
and
Lockett, that the Texas Special Issues
"allo[w] the jury to consider the mitigating aspects of the
crime and the unique characteristics of the perpetrator, and
therefore sufficiently provid[e] for jury discretion."
Lowenfield v. Phelps, 484 U. S. 231,
484 U. S. 245
(1988).
See also Pulley v. Harris, 465 U. S.
37,
465 U. S. 48-49
(1984);
Zant v. Stephens, supra, at
462 U. S.
875-876, n. 13;
Adams v. Texas, 448 U. S.
38,
448 U. S. 46
(1980). I acknowledge that some statements in
Lockett and
Eddings, read in isolation from the facts of the cases,
might be thought to establish the principle that the Court today
adopts. One must read cases, however, not in a vacuum, but in light
of their facts -- which, in conjunction with the clear and constant
reaffirmation of
Jurek, leads to the conclusion that all
mitigating factors must be able to be considered by the sentencer,
but need not be able to be considered for all purposes.
Finally, I turn briefly to the place of today's holding within
the broad scheme of our constitutional jurisprudence regarding
capital sentencing, as opposed to the immediately applicable
precedents. It is out of order there as well. As noted at the
outset of this discussion, our law regarding capital sentencing has
sought to strike a balance between complete discretion, which
produces "wholly arbitrary and capricious action,"
Gregg,
428 U.S. at
428 U. S. 189,
and no discretion at all, which prevents the individuating
characteristics of the defendant and of the crime to be taken into
account,
Woodson, supra, at
428 U. S.
303-304. That is why, in
Jurek, we did not
regard the Texas Special Issues as inherently bad, but to the
contrary thought them a desirable means of "focus[ing] the jury's
objective consideration of the particularized circumstances," 428
U.S. at
428 U. S. 274,
or, as the plurality put it in
Franklin, "channel[ing]
jury discretion . . . to achieve a more rational and equitable
administration of the death penalty," 487 U.S. at
487 U. S. 181.
In providing for juries to consider all
Page 492 U. S. 359
mitigating circumstances insofar as they bear upon (1)
deliberateness, (2) future dangerousness, and (3) provocation, it
seems to me Texas had adopted a rational scheme that meets the two
concerns of our Eighth Amendment jurisprudence. The Court today
demands that it be replaced, however, with a scheme that simply
dumps before the jury all sympathetic factors bearing upon the
defendant's background and character, and the circumstances of the
offense, so that the jury may decide without further guidance
whether he "lacked the moral culpability to be sentenced to death,"
ante at
492 U. S. 324,
"did not deserve to be sentenced to death,"
ante at
492 U. S. 326,
or "was not sufficiently culpable to deserve the death penalty,"
ibid. The Court seeks to dignify this by calling it a
process that calls for a "reasoned moral response,"
ante
at
492 U. S. 323,
492 U. S. 328
-- but reason has nothing to do with it, the Court having
eliminated the structure that required reason. It is an unguided,
emotional "moral response" that the Court demands be allowed -- an
outpouring of personal reaction to all the circumstances of a
defendant's life and personality, an unfocused sympathy. Not only
have we never before said the Constitution requires this, but the
line of cases following
Gregg sought to eliminate
precisely the unpredictability it produces.
See, e. g., Godfrey
v. Georgia, 446 U. S. 420,
446 U. S. 428
(1980) (States "must channel the [capital] sentencer's discretion
by
clear and objective standards' that provide `specific and
detailed guidance,' and that `make rationally reviewable the
process for imposing a sentence of death'") (citations omitted);
California v. Brown, 479 U. S. 538,
479 U. S. 541
(1987) ("[S]entencers may not be given unbridled discretion in
determining the fates of those charged with capital offenses"; the
"Constitution . . . requires that death penalty statutes be
structured so as to prevent the penalty from being administered in
an arbitrary and unpredictable fashion").
The Court cannot seriously believe that rationality and
predictability can be achieved, and capriciousness avoided, by
"
narrow[ing] a sentencer's discretion to impose the
death
Page 492 U. S. 360
sentence,'" but expanding his discretion "`to
decline to
impose the death sentence,'"
ante at
492 U. S. 327,
quoting
McCleskey v. Kemp, 481 U.
S. 279,
481 U. S. 304
(1987) (emphasis in original). The decision whether to impose the
death penalty is a unitary one; unguided discretion not to impose
is unguided discretion to impose as well. In holding that the jury
had to be free to deem Penry's mental retardation and sad childhood
relevant for whatever purpose it wished, the Court has come full
circle, not only permitting but requiring what
Furman once
condemned. "Freakishly" and "wantonly,"
Furman, 408 U.S.
at
408 U. S. 310
(Stewart, J. concurring), have been rebaptized "reasoned moral
response." I do not think the Constitution forbids what the Court
imposes here, but I am certain it does not require it.
I respectfully dissent.