SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
Nos. 17–1618, 17–1623 and 18–107
_________________
GERALD LYNN BOSTOCK, PETITIONER
17–1618
v.
CLAYTON COUNTY, GEORGIA
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the eleventh circuit
ALTITUDE EXPRESS, INC., et al.,
PETITIONERS
17–1623
v.
MELISSA ZARDA and William Allen Moore,
Jr., co-independent executors of the ESTATE OF DONALD ZARDA
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the second circuit
R.G. & G.R. HARRIS FUNERAL HOMES,
INC., PETITIONER
18–107
v.
EQUAL EMPLOYMENT OPPORTUNITY
COMMISSION, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the sixth circuit
[June 15, 2020]
Justice Alito, with whom Justice Thomas joins,
dissenting.
There is only one word for what the Court has
done today: legislation. The document that the Court releases is in
the form of a judicial opinion interpreting a statute, but that is
deceptive.
Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964
prohibits employment discrimination on any of five specified
grounds: “race, color, religion, sex, [and] national origin.” 42
U. S. C. §2000e–2(a)(1). Neither “sexual orientation” nor
“gender identity” appears on that list. For the past 45 years,
bills have been introduced in Congress to add “sexual orientation”
to the list,[
1] and in recent
years, bills have included “gender identity” as well.[
2] But to date, none has passed both
Houses.
Last year, the House of Representatives passed a
bill that would amend Title VII by defining sex discrimination to
include both “sexual orientation” and “gender identity,” H. R.
5, 116th Cong., 1st Sess. (2019), but the bill has stalled in the
Senate. An alternative bill, H. R. 5331, 116th Cong., 1st
Sess. (2019), would add similar prohibitions but contains
provisions to protect religious liberty.[
3] This bill remains before a House Subcommittee.
Because no such amendment of Title VII has been
enacted in accordance with the requirements in the Constitution
(passage in both Houses and presentment to the President, Art. I,
§7, cl. 2), Title VII’s prohibition of discrimination because of
“sex” still means what it has always meant. But the Court is not
deterred by these constitutional niceties. Usurping the
constitutional authority of the other branches, the Court has
essentially taken H. R. 5’s provision on employment
discrimination and issued it under the guise of statutory
interpretation.[
4] A more
brazen abuse of our authority to interpret statutes is hard to
recall.
The Court tries to convince readers that it is
merely enforcing the terms of the statute, but that is
preposterous. Even as understood today, the concept of
discrimination because of “sex” is different from discrimination
because of “sexual orientation” or “gender identity.” And in any
event, our duty is to interpret statutory terms to “mean what they
conveyed to reasonable people
at the time they were
written.” A. Scalia & B. Garner, Reading Law: The
Interpretation of Legal Texts 16 (2012) (emphasis added). If every
single living American had been surveyed in 1964, it would have
been hard to find any who thought that discrimination because of
sex meant discrimination because of sexual orientation––not to
mention gender identity, a concept that was essentially unknown at
the time.
The Court attempts to pass off its decision as
the inevitable product of the textualist school of statutory
interpretation championed by our late colleague Justice Scalia, but
no one should be fooled. The Court’s opinion is like a pirate ship.
It sails under a textualist flag, but what it actually represents
is a theory of statutory interpretation that Justice Scalia
excoriated––the theory that courts should “update” old statutes so
that they better reflect the current values of society. See A.
Scalia, A Matter of Interpretation 22
(1997). If the Court finds it appropriate to
adopt this theory, it should own up to what it is doing.[
5]
Many will applaud today’s decision because they
agree on policy grounds with the Court’s updating of Title VII. But
the question in these cases is not whether discrimination because
of sexual orientation or gender identity
should be outlawed.
The question is
whether Congress did that in 1964.
It indisputably did not.
I
A
Title VII, as noted, prohibits discrimination
“because of . . . sex,” §2000e–2(a)(1), and in 1964, it
was as clear as clear could be that this meant discrimination
because of the genetic and anatomical characteristics that men and
women have at the time of birth. Determined searching has not found
a single dictionary from that time that defined “sex” to mean
sexual orientation, gender identity, or “transgender
status.”[
6]
Ante, at 2.
(Appendix A,
infra, to this opinion includes the full
definitions of “sex” in the unabridged dictionaries in use in the
1960s.)
In all those dictionaries, the primary
definition of “sex” was essentially the same as that in the
then-most recent edition of Webster’s New International Dictionary
2296 (def. 1) (2d ed. 1953): “[o]ne of the two divisions of
organisms formed on the distinction of male and female.” See also
American Heritage Dictionary 1187 (def. 1(a)) (1969) (“The property
or quality by which organisms are classified according to their
reproductive functions”); Random House Dictionary of the English
Language 1307 (def. 1) (1966) (Random House Dictionary) (“the fact
or character of being either male or female”); 9 Oxford English
Dictionary 577 (def. 1) (1933) (“Either of the two divisions of
organic beings distinguished as male and female respectively”).
The Court does not dispute that this is what
“sex” means in Title VII, although it coyly suggests that there is
at least some support for a different and potentially relevant
definition.
Ante, at 5. (I address alternative definitions
below. See Part I–B–3,
infra.) But the Court declines to
stand on that ground and instead “proceed[s] on the assumption that
‘sex’ . . . refer[s] only to biological distinctions
between male and female.”
Ante, at 5.
If that is so, it should be perfectly clear that
Title VII does not reach discrimination because of sexual
orientation or gender identity. If “sex” in Title VII means
biologically male or female, then discrimination because of sex
means discrimination because the person in question is biologically
male or biologically female, not because that person is sexually
attracted to members of the same sex or identifies as a member of a
particular gender.
How then does the Court claim to avoid that
conclusion? The Court tries to cloud the issue by spending many
pages discussing matters that are beside the point. The Court
observes that a Title VII plaintiff need not show that “sex” was
the sole or primary motive for a challenged employment decision or
its sole or primary cause; that Title VII is limited to
discrimination with respect to a list of specified actions (such as
hiring, firing, etc.); and that Title VII protects individual
rights, not group rights. See
ante, at 5–9, 11.
All that is true, but so what? In cases like
those before us, a plaintiff must show that sex was a “motivating
factor” in the challenged employment action, 42 U. S. C.
§2000e–2(m), so the question we must decide comes down to this: if
an individual employee or applicant for employment shows that his
or her sexual orientation or gender identity was a “motivating
factor” in a hiring or discharge decision, for example, is that
enough to establish that the employer discriminated “because of
. . . sex”? Or, to put the same question in different
terms, if an employer takes an employment action solely because of
the sexual orientation or gender identity of an employee or
applicant, has that employer necessarily discriminated because of
biological sex?
The answers to those questions must be no,
unless discrimination because of sexual orientation or gender
identity inherently constitutes discrimination because of sex. The
Court attempts to prove that point, and it argues, not merely that
the terms of Title VII
can be interpreted that way but that
they
cannot reasonably be interpreted any other way.
According to the Court, the text is unambiguous. See
ante,
at 24, 27, 30.
The arrogance of this argument is breathtaking.
As I will show, there is not a shred of evidence that any Member of
Congress interpreted the statutory text that way when Title VII was
enacted. See Part III–B,
infra. But the Court apparently
thinks that this was because the Members were not “smart enough to
realize” what its language means.
Hively v.
Ivy Tech
Community College of Ind., 853 F.3d 339, 357 (CA7 2017)
(Posner, J., concurring). The Court seemingly has the same opinion
about our colleagues on the Courts of Appeals, because until 2017,
every single Court of Appeals to consider the question interpreted
Title VII’s prohibition against sex discrimination to mean
discrimination on the basis of biological sex. See Part III–C,
infra. And for good measure, the Court’s conclusion that
Title VII unambiguously reaches discrimination on the basis of
sexual orientation and gender identity necessarily means that the
EEOC failed to see the obvious for the first 48 years after Title
VII became law.[
7] Day in and
day out, the Commission enforced Title VII but did not grasp what
discrimination “because of . . . sex” unambiguously
means. See Part III–C,
infra.
The Court’s argument is not only arrogant, it is
wrong. It fails on its own terms. “Sex,” “sexual orientation,” and
“gender identity” are different concepts, as the Court concedes.
Ante, at 19 (“homosexuality and transgender status are
distinct concepts from sex”). And neither “sexual orientation” nor
“gender identity” is tied to either of the two biological sexes.
See
ante, at 10 (recognizing that “discrimination on these
bases” does not have “some disparate impact on one sex or
another”). Both men and women may be attracted to members of the
opposite sex, members of the same sex, or members of both
sexes.[
8] And individuals who
are born with the genes and organs of either biological sex may
identify with a different gender.[
9]
Using slightly different terms, the Court
asserts again and again that discrimination because of sexual
orientation or gender identity inherently or necessarily entails
discrimination because of sex. See
ante, at 2 (When an
employer “fires an individual for being homosexual or transgender,”
“[s]ex plays a necessary and undisguisable role in the decision”);
ante, at 9 (“[I]t is impossible to discriminate against a
person for being homosexual or transgender without discriminating
against that individual based on sex”);
ante, at 11 (“[W]hen
an employer discriminates against homosexual or transgender
employees, [the] employer . . . inescapably
intends to rely on sex in its decisionmaking”);
ante,
at 12 (“For an employer to discriminate against employees for being
homosexual or transgender, the employer must intentionally
discriminate against individual men and women in part because of
sex”);
ante, at 14 (“When an employer fires an employee for
being homosexual or transgender, it necessarily and intentionally
discriminates against that individual in part because of sex”);
ante, at 19 (“[D]iscrimination based on homosexuality or
transgender status necessarily entails discrimination based on
sex”). But repetition of an assertion does not make it so, and the
Court’s repeated assertion is demonstrably untrue.
Contrary to the Court’s contention,
discrimination because of sexual orientation or gender identity
does not in and of itself entail discrimination because of sex. We
can see this because it is quite possible for an employer to
discriminate on those grounds without taking the sex of an
individual applicant or employee into account. An employer can have
a policy that says: “We do not hire gays, lesbians, or transgender
individuals.” And an employer can implement this policy without
paying any attention to or even knowing the biological sex of gay,
lesbian, and transgender applicants. In fact, at the time of the
enactment of Title VII, the United States military had a blanket
policy of refusing to enlist gays or lesbians, and under this
policy for years thereafter, applicants for enlistment were
required to complete a form that asked whether they were
“homosexual.” Appendix D,
infra, at 88, 101.
At oral argument, the attorney representing the
employees, a prominent professor of constitutional law, was asked
if there would be discrimination because of sex if an employer with
a blanket policy against hiring gays, lesbians, and transgender
individuals implemented that policy without knowing the biological
sex of any job applicants. Her candid answer was that this would
“not” be sex discrimination.[
10] And she was right.
The attorney’s concession was necessary, but it
is fatal to the Court’s interpretation, for if an employer
discriminates against individual applicants or employees without
even knowing whether they are male or female, it is impossible to
argue that the employer intentionally discriminated because of sex.
Contra,
ante, at 19. An employer cannot intentionally
discriminate on the basis of a characteristic of which the employer
has no knowledge. And if an employer does not violate Title VII by
discriminating on the basis of sexual orientation or gender
identity without knowing the sex of the affected individuals, there
is no reason why the same employer could not lawfully implement the
same policy even if it knows the sex of these individuals. If an
employer takes an adverse employment action for a perfectly
legitimate reason—for example, because an employee stole company
property—that action is not converted into sex discrimination
simply because the employer knows the employee’s sex. As explained,
a disparate treatment case requires proof of intent—
i.e.,
that the employee’s sex motivated the firing. In short, what this
example shows is that discrimination because of sexual orientation
or gender identity does not inherently or necessarily entail
discrimination because of sex, and for that reason, the Court’s
chief argument collapses.
Trying to escape the consequences of the
attorney’s concession, the Court offers its own hypothetical:
“Suppose an employer’s application form
offered a single box to check if the applicant is either black or
Catholic. If the employer refuses to hire anyone who checks that
box, would we conclude the employer has complied with Title VII, so
long as it studiously avoids learning any particular applicant’s
race or religion? Of course not.”
Ante, at 18.
How this hypothetical proves the Court’s point
is a mystery. A person who checked that box would presumably be
black, Catholic, or both, and refusing to hire an applicant because
of race or religion is prohibited by Title VII. Rejecting
applicants who checked a box indicating that they are homosexual is
entirely different because it is impossible to tell from that
answer whether an applicant is male or female.
The Court follows this strange hypothetical with
an even stranger argument. The Court argues that an applicant could
not answer the question whether he or she is homosexual without
knowing something about sex. If the applicant was unfamiliar with
the term “homosexual,” the applicant would have to look it up or
ask what the term means. And because this applicant would have to
take into account his or her sex and that of the persons to whom he
or she is sexually attracted to answer the question, it follows,
the Court reasons, that an employer could not reject this applicant
without taking the applicant’s sex into account. See
ante,
at 18–19.
This is illogical. Just because an applicant
cannot say whether he or she is homosexual without knowing his or
her own sex and that of the persons to whom the applicant is
attracted, it does not follow that an employer cannot reject an
applicant based on homosexuality without knowing the applicant’s
sex.
While the Court’s imagined application form
proves nothing, another hypothetical case offered by the Court is
telling. But what it proves is not what the Court thinks. The Court
posits:
“Imagine an employer who has a policy of
firing any employee known to be homosexual. The employer hosts an
office holiday party and invites employees to bring their spouses.
A model employee arrives and introduces a manager to Susan, the
employee’s wife. Will that employee be fired? If the policy works
as the employer intends, the answer depends entirely on whether the
model employee is a man or a woman.”
Ante, at 11.
This example disproves the Court’s argument
because it is perfectly clear that the employer’s motivation in
firing the female employee had nothing to do with that employee’s
sex. The employer presumably knew that this employee was a woman
before she was invited to the fateful party. Yet the employer, far
from holding her biological sex against her, rated her a “model
employee.” At the party, the employer learned something new, her
sexual orientation, and it was this new information that motivated
her discharge. So this is another example showing that
discrimination because of sexual orientation does not inherently
involve discrimination because of sex.
In addition to the failed argument just
discussed, the Court makes two other arguments, more or less in
passing. The first of these is essentially that sexual orientation
and gender identity are closely related to sex. The Court argues
that sexual orientation and gender identity are “inextricably bound
up with sex,”
ante, at 10, and that discrimination on the
basis of sexual orientation or gender identity involves the
application of “sex-based rules,”
ante, at 17. This is a
variant of an argument found in many of the briefs filed in support
of the employees and in the lower court decisions that agreed with
the Court’s interpretation. All these variants stress that sex,
sexual orientation, and gender identity are related concepts. The
Seventh Circuit observed that “[i]t would require considerable
calisthenics to remove ‘sex’ from ‘sexual orientation.’ ”
Hively, 853 F. 3d, at 350.[
11] The Second Circuit wrote that sex is necessarily “a
factor in sexual orientation” and further concluded that “sexual
orientation is a function of sex.” 883 F.3d 100, 112–113 (CA2 2018)
(en banc). Bostock’s brief and those of
amici supporting his
position contend that sexual orientation is “a sex-based
consideration.”[
12] Other
briefs state that sexual orientation is “a function of
sex”[
13] or is
“intrinsically related to sex.”[
14] Similarly, Stephens argues that sex and gender
identity are necessarily intertwined: “By definition, a transgender
person is someone who lives and identifies with a sex different
than the sex assigned to the person at birth.”[
15]
It is curious to see this argument in an opinion
that purports to apply the purest and highest form of textualism
because the argument effectively amends the statutory text. Title
VII prohibits discrimination because of
sex itself, not
everything that is related to, based on, or defined with reference
to, “sex.” Many things are related to sex. Think of all the nouns
other than “orientation” that are commonly modified by the
adjective “sexual.” Some examples yielded by a quick computer
search are “sexual harassment,” “sexual assault, “sexual violence,”
“sexual intercourse,” and “sexual content.”
Does the Court really think that Title VII
prohibits discrimination on all these grounds? Is it unlawful for
an employer to refuse to hire an employee with a record of sexual
harassment in prior jobs? Or a record of sexual assault or
violence?
To be fair, the Court does not claim that Title
VII prohibits discrimination because of
everything that is
related to sex. The Court draws a distinction between things that
are “inextricably” related and those that are related in “some
vague sense.”
Ante, at 10. Apparently the Court would graft
onto Title VII some arbitrary line separating the things that are
related closely enough and those that are not.[
16] And it would do this in the name of high
textualism. An additional argument made in passing also fights the
text of Title VII and the policy it reflects. The Court proclaims
that “[a]n individual’s homosexuality or transgender status is not
relevant to employment decisions.”
Ante, at 9. That is the
policy view of many people in 2020, and perhaps Congress would have
amended Title VII to implement it if this Court had not intervened.
But that is not the policy embodied in Title VII in its current
form. Title VII prohibits discrimination based on five specified
grounds, and neither sexual orientation nor gender identity is on
the list. As long as an employer does not discriminate based on one
of the listed grounds, the employer is free to decide for itself
which characteristics are “relevant to [its] employment decisions.”
Ibid. By proclaiming that sexual orientation and gender
identity are “not relevant to employment decisions,” the Court
updates Title VII to reflect what it regards as 2020 values.
The Court’s remaining argument is based on a
hypothetical that the Court finds instructive. In this
hypothetical, an employer has two employees who are “attracted to
men,” and “
to the employer’s mind” the two employees are
“materially identical” except that one is a man and the other is a
woman.
Ante, at 9 (emphasis added). The Court reasons that
if the employer fires the man but not the woman, the employer is
necessarily motivated by the man’s biological sex.
Ante, at
9–10. After all, if two employees are identical in every respect
but sex, and the employer fires only one, what other reason could
there be?
The problem with this argument is that the Court
loads the dice. That is so because in the mind of an employer who
does not want to employ individuals who are attracted to members of
the same sex, these two employees are not materially identical in
every respect but sex. On the contrary, they differ in another way
that the employer thinks is quite material. And until Title VII is
amended to add sexual orientation as a prohibited ground, this is a
view that an employer is permitted to implement. As noted, other
than prohibiting discrimination on any of five specified grounds,
“race, color, religion, sex, [and] national origin.” 42
U. S. C. §2000e–2(a)(1), Title VII allows employers to
decide whether two employees are “materially identical.” Even
idiosyncratic criteria are permitted; if an employer thinks that
Scorpios make bad employees, the employer can refuse to hire
Scorpios. Such a policy would be unfair and foolish, but under
Title VII, it is permitted. And until Title VII is amended, so is a
policy against employing gays, lesbians, or transgender
individuals.
Once this is recognized, what we have in the
Court’s hypothetical case are two employees who differ in
two ways––sex and sexual orientation––and if the employer
fires one and keeps the other, all that can be inferred is that the
employer was motivated either entirely by sexual orientation,
entirely by sex, or in part by both. We cannot infer with any
certainty, as the hypothetical is apparently meant to suggest, that
the employer was motivated even in part by sex. The Court harps on
the fact that under Title VII a prohibited ground need not be the
sole motivation for an adverse employment action, see
ante,
at 10–11, 14–15, 21, but its example does not show that sex
necessarily played
any part in the employer’s thinking.
The Court tries to avoid this inescapable
conclusion by arguing that sex is really the only difference
between the two employees. This is so, the Court maintains, because
both employees “are attracted to men.”
Ante, at 9–10. Of
course, the employer would couch its objection to the man
differently. It would say that its objection was his sexual
orientation. So this may appear to leave us with a battle of
labels. If the employer’s objection to the male employee is
characterized as attraction to men, it seems that he is just like
the woman in all respects except sex and that the employer’s
disparate treatment must be based on that one difference. On the
other hand, if the employer’s objection is sexual orientation or
homosexuality, the two employees differ in two respects, and it
cannot be inferred that the disparate treatment was due even in
part to sex.
The Court insists that its label is the right
one, and that presumably is why it makes such a point of arguing
that an employer cannot escape liability under Title VII by giving
sex discrimination some other name. See
ante, at 14, 17.
That is certainly true, but so is the opposite. Something that is
not sex discrimination cannot be converted into sex
discrimination by slapping on that label. So the Court cannot prove
its point simply by labeling the employer’s objection as
“attract[ion] to men.”
Ante, at 9–10. Rather, the Court
needs to show that its label is the correct one.
And a labeling standoff would not help the Court
because that would mean that the bare text of Title VII does not
unambiguously show that its interpretation is right. The Court
would have no justification for its stubborn refusal to look any
further.
As it turns out, however, there is no standoff.
It can easily be shown that the employer’s real objection is not
“attract[ion] to men” but homosexual orientation.
In an effort to prove its point, the Court
carefully includes in its example just two employees, a homosexual
man and a heterosexual woman, but suppose we add two more
individuals, a woman who is attracted to women and a man who is
attracted to women. (A large employer will likely have applicants
and employees who fall into all four categories, and a small
employer can potentially have all four as well.) We now have the
four exemplars listed below, with the discharged employees crossed
out:
Man attracted to men
Woman attracted to men
Woman attracted to women
Man attracted to women
The discharged employees have one thing in
common. It is not biological sex, attraction to men, or attraction
to women. It is attraction to members of their own sex—in a word,
sexual orientation. And that, we can infer, is the employer’s real
motive.
In sum, the Court’s textual arguments fail on
their own terms. The Court tries to prove that “it is impossible to
discriminate against a person for being homosexual or transgender
without discriminating against that individual based on sex,”
ante, at 9, but as has been shown, it is entirely possible
for an employer to do just that. “[H]omosexuality and transgender
status are distinct concepts from sex,”
ante, at 19, and
discrimination because of sexual orientation or transgender status
does not inherently or necessarily constitute discrimination
because of sex. The Court’s arguments are squarely contrary to the
statutory text.
But even if the words of Title VII did not
definitively refute the Court’s interpretation, that would not
justify the Court’s refusal to consider alternative
interpretations. The Court’s excuse for ignoring everything other
than the bare statutory text is that the text is unambiguous and
therefore no one can reasonably interpret the text in any way other
than the Court does. Unless the Court has met that high standard,
it has no justification for its blinkered approach. And to say that
the Court’s interpretation is the only possible reading is
indefensible.
B
Although the Court relies solely on the
arguments discussed above, several other arguments figure
prominently in the decisions of the lower courts and in briefs
submitted by or in support of the employees. The Court apparently
finds these arguments unpersuasive, and so do I, but for the sake
of completeness, I will address them briefly.
1
One argument, which relies on our decision in
Price Waterhouse v.
Hopkins,
490
U.S. 228 (1989) (plurality opinion), is that discrimination
because of sexual orientation or gender identity violates Title VII
because it constitutes prohibited discrimination on the basis of
sex stereotypes. See 883 F. 3d, at 119–123;
Hively, 853 F.
3d, at 346; 884 F.3d 560, 576–577 (CA6 2018). The argument goes
like this. Title VII prohibits discrimination based on stereotypes
about the way men and women should behave; the belief that a person
should be attracted only to persons of the opposite sex and the
belief that a person should identify with his or her biological sex
are examples of such stereotypes; therefore, discrimination on
either of these grounds is unlawful.
This argument fails because it is based on a
faulty premise, namely, that Title VII forbids discrimination based
on sex stereotypes. It does not. It prohibits discrimination
because of “sex,” and the two concepts are not the same. See
Price Waterhouse, 490 U. S., at 251. That does not
mean, however, that an employee or applicant for employment cannot
prevail by showing that a challenged decision was based on a sex
stereotype. Such evidence is relevant to prove discrimination
because of sex, and it may be convincing where the trait that is
inconsistent with the stereotype is one that would be tolerated and
perhaps even valued in a person of the opposite sex. See
ibid.
Much of the plaintiff ’s evidence in
Price Waterhouse was of this nature. The plaintiff was a
woman who was passed over for partnership at an accounting firm,
and some of the adverse comments about her work appeared to
criticize her for being forceful and insufficiently “feminin[e].”
Id., at 235–236.
The main issue in
Price Waterhouse––the
proper allocation of the burdens of proof in a so-called mixed
motives Title VII case—is not relevant here, but the plurality
opinion, endorsed by four Justices, commented on the issue of sex
stereotypes. The plurality observed that “sex stereotypes do not
inevitably prove that gender played a part in a particular
employment decision” but “can certainly be
evidence that
gender played a part.”
Id., at 251.[
17] And the plurality made it clear that “[t]he
plaintiff must show that the employer actually relied on her gender
in making its decision.”
Ibid.
Plaintiffs who allege that they were treated
unfavorably because of their sexual orientation or gender identity
are not in the same position as the plaintiff in
Price
Waterhouse. In cases involving discrimination based on sexual
orientation or gender identity, the grounds for the employer’s
decision—that individuals should be sexually attracted only to
persons of the opposite biological sex or should identify with
their biological sex—apply equally to men and women.
“[H]eterosexuality is not a
female stereotype; it not a
male stereotype; it is not a
sex- specific stereotype
at all.”
Hively, 853 F. 3d, at 370 (Sykes, J.,
dissenting).
To be sure, there may be cases in which a gay,
lesbian, or transgender individual can make a claim like the one in
Price Waterhouse. That is, there may be cases where traits
or behaviors that some people associate with gays, lesbians, or
transgender individuals are tolerated or valued in persons of one
biological sex but not the other. But that is a different
matter.
2
A second prominent argument made in support of
the result that the Court now reaches analogizes discrimination
against gays and lesbians to discrimination against a person who is
married to or has an intimate relationship with a person of a
different race. Several lower court cases have held that
discrimination on this ground violates Title VII. See,
e.g.,
Holcomb v.
Iona College, 521 F.3d 130 (CA2 2008);
Parr v.
Woodmen of World Life Ins. Co., 791 F.2d 888
(CA11 1986). And the logic of these decisions, it is argued,
applies equally where an employee or applicant is treated
unfavorably because he or she is married to, or has an intimate
relationship with, a person of the same sex.
This argument totally ignores the historically
rooted reason why discrimination on the basis of an interracial
relationship constitutes race discrimination. And without taking
history into account, it is not easy to see how the decisions in
question fit the terms of Title VII.
Recall that Title VII makes it unlawful for an
employer to discriminate against an individual “because of
such
individual’s race.” 42 U. S. C. §2000e–2(a) (emphasis
added). So if an employer is happy to employ whites and blacks but
will not employ any employee in an interracial relationship, how
can it be said that the employer is discriminating against either
whites or blacks “because of such individual’s race”? This employer
would be applying the same rule to all its employees regardless of
their race.
The answer is that this employer is
discriminating on a ground that history tells us is a core form of
race discrimination.[
18] “It
would require absolute blindness to the history of racial
discrimination in this country not to understand what is at stake
in such cases . . . . A prohibition on ‘race-mixing’ was
. . . grounded in bigotry against a particular race and
was an integral part of preserving the rigid hierarchical
distinction that denominated members of the black race as inferior
to whites.” 883 F. 3d, at 158–159 (Lynch, J., dissenting).
Discrimination because of sexual orientation is
different. It cannot be regarded as a form of sex discrimination on
the ground that applies in race cases since discrimination because
of sexual orientation is not historically tied to a project that
aims to subjugate either men or women. An employer who
discriminates on this ground might be called “homophobic” or
“transphobic,” but not sexist. See
Wittmer v.
Phillips 66
Co., 915 F.3d 328, 338 (CA5 2019) (Ho, J., concurring).
3
The opinion of the Court intimates that the
term “sex” was not universally understood in 1964 to refer just to
the categories of male and female, see
ante, at 5, and while
the Court does not take up any alternative definition as a ground
for its decision, I will say a word on this subject.
As previously noted, the definitions of “sex” in
the unabridged dictionaries in use in the 1960s are reproduced in
Appendix A,
infra. Anyone who examines those definitions can
see that the primary definition in every one of them refers to the
division of living things into two groups, male and female, based
on biology, and most of the definitions further down the list are
the same or very similar. In addition, some definitions refer to
heterosexual sex acts. See Random House Dictionary 1307 (“coitus,”
“sexual intercourse” (defs. 5–6)); American Heritage Dictionary, at
1187 (“sexual intercourse” (def. 5)).[
19]
Aside from these, what is there? One definition,
“to neck passionately,” Random House Dictionary 1307 (def. 8),
refers to sexual conduct that is not necessarily heterosexual. But
can it be seriously argued that one of the aims of Title VII is to
outlaw employment discrimination against employees, whether
heterosexual or homosexual, who engage in necking? And even if
Title VII had that effect, that is not what is at issue in cases
like those before us.
That brings us to the two remaining subsidiary
definitions, both of which refer to sexual urges or instincts and
their manifestations. See the fourth definition in the American
Heritage Dictionary, at 1187 (“the sexual urge or instinct as it
manifests itself in behavior”), and the fourth definition in both
Webster’s Second and Third (“[p]henomena of sexual instincts and
their manifestations,” Webster’s New International Dictionary, at
2296 (2d ed.); Webster’s Third New International Dictionary 2081
(1966)). Since both of these come after three prior definitions
that refer to men and women, they are most naturally read to have
the same association, and in any event, is it plausible that Title
VII prohibits discrimination based on
any sexual urge or
instinct and its manifestations? The urge to rape?
Viewing all these definitions, the overwhelming
impact is that discrimination because of “sex” was understood
during the era when Title VII was enacted to refer to men and
women. (The same is true of current definitions, which are
reproduced in Appendix B,
infra.) This no doubt explains why
neither this Court nor any of the lower courts have tried to make
much of the dictionary definitions of sex just discussed.
II
A
So far, I have not looked beyond dictionary
definitions of “sex,” but textualists like Justice Scalia do not
confine their inquiry to the scrutiny of dictionaries. See Manning,
Textualism and the Equity of the Statute, 101 Colum. L. Rev. 1, 109
(2001). Dictionary definitions are valuable because they are
evidence of what people at the time of a statute’s enactment would
have understood its words to mean.
Ibid. But they are not
the only source of relevant evidence, and what matters in the end
is the answer to the question that the evidence is gathered to
resolve: How would the terms of a statute have been understood by
ordinary people at the time of enactment?
Justice Scalia was perfectly clear on this
point. The words of a law, he insisted, “mean
what they conveyed
to reasonable people at the time.” Reading Law, at 16 (emphasis
added).[
20]
Leading proponents of Justice Scalia’s school of
textualism have expounded on this principle and explained that it
is grounded on an understanding of the way language works. As Dean
John F. Manning explains, “the meaning of language depends on the
way a linguistic community uses words and phrases in context.” What
Divides Textualists From Purposivists? 106 Colum. L. Rev. 70, 78
(2006). “[O]ne can make sense of others’ communications only by
placing them in their appropriate social and
linguistic context,”
id., at 79–80, and this is no less
true of statutes than any other verbal communications. “[S]tatutes
convey meaning only because members of a relevant linguistic
community apply shared background conventions for understanding how
particular words are used in particular contexts.” Manning, The
Absurdity Doctrine, 116 Harv. L. Rev. 2387, 2457 (2003). Therefore,
judges should ascribe to the words of a statute “what a reasonable
person conversant with applicable social conventions would have
understood them to be adopting.” Manning, 106 Colum. L. Rev., at
77. Or, to put the point in slightly different terms, a judge
interpreting a statute should ask “ ‘what one would ordinarily
be understood as saying, given the circumstances in which one said
it.’ ” Manning, 116 Harv. L. Rev., at 2397–2398.
Judge Frank Easterbrook has made the same
points:
“Words are arbitrary signs, having meaning
only to the extent writers and readers share an understanding.
. . . Language in general, and legislation in particular,
is a social enterprise to which both speakers and listeners
contribute, drawing on background understandings and the structure
and circumstances of the utterance.”
Herrmann v.
Cencom
Cable Assocs.,
Inc., 978 F.2d 978, 982 (CA7 1992).
Consequently, “[s]licing a statute into phrases
while ignoring . . . the setting of the enactment
. . . is a formula for disaster.”
Ibid.; see also
Continental Can Co. v.
Chicago Truck Drivers, Helpers and
Warehouse Workers Union (Independent) Pension Fund, 916 F.2d
1154, 1157 (CA7 1990) (“You don’t have to be Ludwig Wittgenstein or
Hans-Georg Gadamer to know that successful communication depends on
meanings shared by interpretive communities”).
Thus, when textualism is properly understood, it
calls for an examination of the social context in which a statute
was enacted because this may have an important bearing on what its
words were understood to mean at the time of enactment. Textualists
do not read statutes as if they were messages picked up by a
powerful radio telescope from a distant and utterly unknown
civilization. Statutes consist of communications between members of
a particular linguistic community, one that existed in a particular
place and at a particular time, and these communications must
therefore be interpreted as they were understood by that community
at that time.
For this reason, it is imperative to consider
how Americans in 1964 would have understood Title VII’s prohibition
of discrimination because of sex. To get a picture of this, we may
imagine this scene. Suppose that, while Title VII was under
consideration in Congress, a group of average Americans decided to
read the text of the bill with the aim of writing or calling their
representatives in Congress and conveying their approval or
disapproval. What would these ordinary citizens have taken
“discrimination because of sex” to mean? Would they have thought
that this language prohibited discrimination because of sexual
orientation or gender identity?
B
The answer could not be clearer. In 1964,
ordinary Americans reading the text of Title VII would not have
dreamed that discrimination because of sex meant discrimination
because of sexual orientation, much less gender identity. The
ordinary meaning of discrimination because of “sex” was
discrimination because of a person’s biological sex, not sexual
orientation or gender identity. The possibility that discrimination
on either of these grounds might fit within some exotic
understanding of sex discrimination would not have crossed their
minds.
1
In 1964, the concept of prohibiting
discrimination “because of sex” was no novelty. It was a familiar
and well-understood concept, and what it meant was equal treatment
for men and women.
Long before Title VII was adopted, many
pioneering state and federal laws had used language substantively
indistinguishable from Title VII’s critical phrase, “discrimination
because of sex.” For example, the California Constitution of 1879
stipulated that no one, “
on account of sex, [could] be
disqualified from entering upon or pursuing any lawful business,
vocation, or profession.” Art. XX, §18 (emphasis added). It also
prohibited a student’s exclusion from any state university
department “on account of sex.” Art. IX, §9; accord, Mont. Const.,
Art. XI, §9 (1889).
Wyoming’s first Constitution proclaimed broadly
that “[b]oth male and female citizens of this state shall equally
enjoy all civil, political and religious rights and privileges,”
Art. VI, §1 (1890), and then provided specifically that “[i]n none
of the public schools . . . shall distinction or
discrimination be made
on account of sex,” Art. VII, §10
(emphasis added); see also §16 (the “university shall be equally
open to students of both sexes”). Washington’s Constitution
likewise required “ample provision for the education of all
children . . . without distinction or preference
on
account of . . .
sex.” Art. IX, §1 (1889)
(emphasis added).
The Constitution of Utah, adopted in 1895,
provided that the right to vote and hold public office “shall not
be denied or abridged
on account of sex.” Art. IV, §1
(emphasis added). And in the next sentence it made clear what “on
account of sex” meant, stating that “[b]oth male and female
citizens . . . shall enjoy equally all civil, political
and religious rights and privileges.”
Ibid.
The most prominent example of a provision using
this language was the Nineteenth Amendment, ratified in 1920, which
bans the denial or abridgment of the right to vote “on account of
sex.” U. S. Const., Amdt. 19. Similar language appeared in the
proposal of the National Woman’s Party for an Equal Rights
Amendment. As framed in 1921, this proposal forbade all “political,
civil or legal disabilities or inequalities
on account of
sex, [o]r on account of marriage.” Women Lawyers Meet:
Representatives of 20 States Endorse Proposed Equal Rights
Amendment, N. Y. Times, Sept. 16, 1921, p. 10.
Similar terms were used in the precursor to the
Equal Pay Act. Introduced in 1944 by Congresswoman Winifred C.
Stanley, it proclaimed that “[d]iscrimination against employees, in
rates of compensation paid,
on account of sex” was “contrary
to the public interest.” H. R. 5056, 78th Cong., 2d Sess.
In 1952, the new Constitution for Puerto Rico,
which was approved by Congress, 66Stat. 327, prohibited all
“discrimination . . .
on account of
. . .
sex,” Art. II, Bill of Rights §1 (emphasis
added), and in the landmark Immigration and Nationality Act of
1952, Congress outlawed discrimination in naturalization
“
because of . . .
sex.” 8
U. S. C. §1422 (emphasis added).
In 1958, the International Labour Organisation,
a United Nations agency of which the United States is a member,
recommended that nations bar employment discrimination “made
on
the basis of . . .
sex.” Convention (No. 111)
Concerning Discrimination in Respect of Employment and Occupation,
Art. 1(a), June 25, 1958, 362 U. N. T. S. 32
(emphasis added).
In 1961, President Kennedy ordered the Civil
Service Commission to review and modify personnel policies “to
assure that selection for any career position is hereinafter made
solely on the basis of individual merit and fitness,
without
regard to sex.”[
21] He
concurrently established a “Commission on the Status of Women” and
directed it to recommend policies “for overcoming discriminations
in government and private employment
on the basis of sex.”
Exec. Order No. 10980, 3 CFR 138 (1961 Supp.) (emphasis added).
In short, the concept of discrimination “because
of,” “on account of,” or “on the basis of ” sex was well
understood. It was part of the campaign for equality that had been
waged by women’s rights advocates for more than a century, and what
it meant was equal treatment for men and women.[
22]
2
Discrimination “because of sex” was not
understood as having anything to do with discrimination because of
sexual orientation or transgender status. Any such notion would
have clashed in spectacular fashion with the societal norms of the
day.
For most 21st-century Americans, it is painful
to be reminded of the way our society once treated gays and
lesbians, but any honest effort to understand what the terms of
Title VII were understood to mean when enacted must take into
account the societal norms of that time. And the plain truth is
that in 1964 homosexuality was thought to be a mental disorder, and
homosexual conduct was regarded as morally culpable and worthy of
punishment.
In its then-most recent Diagnostic and
Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (1952) (DSM–I), the American
Psychiatric Association (APA) classified same-sex attraction as a
“sexual deviation,” a particular type of “sociopathic personality
disturbance,”
id., at 38–39, and the next edition, issued in
1968, similarly classified homosexuality as a “sexual deviatio[n],”
Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders 44 (2d ed.)
(DSM–II). It was not until the sixth printing of the DSM–II in 1973
that this was changed.[
23]
Society’s treatment of homosexuality and
homosexual conduct was consistent with this understanding. Sodomy
was a crime in every State but Illinois, see W. Eskridge,
Dishonorable Passions 387–407 (2008), and in the District of
Columbia, a law enacted by Congress made sodomy a felony punishable
by imprisonment for up to 10 years and permitted the indefinite
civil commitment of “sexual psychopath[s],” Act of June 9, 1948,
§§104, 201–207, 62Stat. 347–349.[
24]
This view of homosexuality was reflected in the
rules governing the federal work force. In 1964, federal
“[a]gencies could deny homosexual men and women employment because
of their sexual orientation,” and this practice continued until
1975. GAO, D. Heivilin, Security Clearances: Consideration of
Sexual Orientation in the Clearance Process 2 (GAO/NSIAD–95–21,
1995). See,
e.g.,
Anonymous v.
Macy, 398 F.2d
317, 318 (CA5 1968) (affirming dismissal of postal employee for
homosexual acts).
In 1964, individuals who were known to be
homosexual could not obtain security clearances, and any who
possessed clearances were likely to lose them if their orientation
was discovered. A 1953 Executive Order provided that background
investigations should look for evidence of “sexual perversion,” as
well as “[a]ny criminal, infamous, dishonest, immoral, or
notoriously disgraceful conduct.” Exec. Order No. 10450,
§8(a)(1)(iii), 3 CFR 938 (1949–1953 Comp.). “Until about 1991, when
agencies began to change their security policies and practices
regarding sexual orientation, there were a number of documented
cases where defense civilian or contractor employees’ security
clearances were denied or revoked because of their sexual
orientation.” GAO, Security Clearances, at 2. See,
e.g.,
Adams v.
Laird, 420 F.2d 230, 240 (CADC 1969)
(upholding denial of security clearance to defense contractor
employee because he had “engaged in repeated homosexual acts”); see
also
Webster v.
Doe,
486 U.S.
592, 595, 601 (1988) (concluding that decision to fire a
particular individual because he was homosexual fell within the
“discretion” of the Director of Central Intelligence under the
National Security Act of 1947 and thus was unreviewable under the
APA).
The picture in state employment was similar. In
1964, it was common for States to bar homosexuals from serving as
teachers. An article summarizing the situation
15 years
after Title VII became law reported that “[a]ll states
have statutes that permit the revocation of teaching certificates
(or credentials) for immorality, moral turpitude, or
unprofessionalism,” and, the survey added, “[h]omosexuality is
considered to fall within all three categories.”[
25]
The situation in California is illustrative.
California laws prohibited individuals who engaged in “immoral
conduct” (which was construed to include homosexual behavior), as
well as those convicted of “sex offenses” (like sodomy), from
employment as teachers. Cal. Educ. Code Ann. §§13202, 13207, 13209,
13218, 13255 (West 1960). The teaching certificates of individuals
convicted of engaging in homosexual acts were revoked. See,
e.g.,
Sarac v
. State Bd. of Ed.,
249 Cal. App. 2d 58, 62–64, 57 Cal. Rptr. 69, 72–73 (1967)
(upholding revocation of secondary teaching credential from teacher
who was convicted of engaging in homosexual conduct on public
beach), overruled in part,
Morrison v.
State Bd. of
Ed.,
1 Cal. 3d 214, 461 P.2d 375 (1969).
In Florida, the legislature enacted laws
authorizing the revocation of teaching certificates for “misconduct
involving moral turpitude,” Fla. Stat. Ann. §229.08(16) (1961), and
this law was used to target homosexual conduct. In 1964, a
legislative committee was wrapping up a 6-year campaign to remove
homosexual teachers from public schools and state universities. As
a result of these efforts, the state board of education apparently
revoked at least 71 teachers’ certificates and removed at least 14
university professors. Eskridge, Dishonorable Passions, at 103.
Individuals who engaged in homosexual acts also
faced the loss of other occupational licenses, such as those needed
to work as a “lawyer, doctor, mortician, [or] beautician.”[
26] See,
e.g.,
Florida
Bar v.
Kay,
232 So. 2d 378 (Fla. 1970) (attorney disbarred after conviction
for homosexual conduct in public bathroom).
In 1964 and for many years thereafter,
homosexuals were barred from the military. See,
e.g., Army
Reg. 635–89, §I(2) (a) (July 15, 1966) (“Personnel who voluntarily
engage in homosexual acts, irrespective of sex, will not be
permitted to serve in the Army in any capacity, and their prompt
separation is mandatory”); Army Reg. 600–443, §I(2) (April 10,
1953) (similar). Prohibitions against homosexual conduct by members
of the military were not eliminated until 2010. See Don’t Ask,
Don’t Tell Repeal Act of 2010, 124Stat. 3515 (repealing 10
U. S. C. §654, which required members of the Armed Forces
to be separated for engaging in homosexual conduct).
Homosexuals were also excluded from entry into
the United States. The Immigration and Nationality Act of 1952
(INA) excluded aliens “afflicted with psychopathic personality.” 8
U. S. C. §1182(a)(4) (1964 ed.). In
Boutilier v.
INS,
387 U.S.
118, 120–123 (1967), this Court, relying on the INA’s
legislative history, interpreted that term to encompass homosexuals
and upheld an alien’s deportation on that ground. Three Justices
disagreed with the majority’s interpretation of the phrase
“psychopathic personality.”[
27] But it apparently did not occur to anyone to argue
that the Court’s interpretation was inconsistent with the INA’s
express prohibition of discrimination “because of sex.” That was
how our society—and this Court—saw things a half century ago.
Discrimination because of sex and discrimination because of sexual
orientation were viewed as two entirely different concepts.
To its credit, our society has now come to
recognize the injustice of past practices, and this recognition
provides the impetus to “update” Title VII. But that is not our
job. Our duty is to understand what the terms of Title VII were
understood to mean when enacted, and in doing so, we must take into
account the societal norms of that time. We must therefore ask
whether ordinary Americans in 1964 would have thought that
discrimination because of “sex” carried some exotic meaning under
which private-sector employers would be prohibited from engaging in
a practice that represented the official policy of the Federal
Government with respect to its own employees. We must ask whether
Americans at that time would have thought that Title VII banned
discrimination against an employee for engaging in conduct that
Congress had made a felony and a ground for civil commitment.
The questions answer themselves. Even if
discrimination based on sexual orientation or gender identity could
be squeezed into some arcane understanding of sex discrimination,
the context in which Title VII was enacted would tell us that this
is not what the statute’s terms were understood to mean at that
time. To paraphrase something Justice Scalia once wrote, “our job
is not to scavenge the world of English usage to discover whether
there is any possible meaning” of discrimination because of sex
that might be broad enough to encompass discrimination because of
sexual orientation or gender identity.
Chisom v.
Roemer,
501 U.S.
380, 410 (1991) (dissenting opinion). Without strong evidence
to the contrary (and there is none here), our job is to ascertain
and apply the “
ordinary meaning” of the statute.
Ibid. And in 1964, ordinary Americans most certainly would
not have understood Title VII to ban discrimination because of
sexual orientation or gender identity.
The Court makes a tiny effort to suggest that at
least some people in 1964 might have seen what Title VII really
means.
Ante, at 26. What evidence does it adduce? One
complaint filed in 1969, another filed in 1974, and arguments made
in the mid-1970s about the meaning of the Equal Rights Amendment.
Ibid. To call this evidence merely feeble would be
generous.
C
While Americans in 1964 would have been
shocked to learn that Congress had enacted a law prohibiting sexual
orientation discrimination, they would have been bewildered to hear
that this law also forbids discrimination on the basis of
“transgender status” or “gender identity,” terms that would have
left people at the time scratching their heads. The term
“transgender” is said to have been coined “ ‘in the early
1970s,’ ”[
28] and the
term “gender identity,” now understood to mean “[a]n internal sense
of being male, female or something else,”[
29] apparently first appeared in an academic article
in 1964.[
30] Certainly,
neither term was in common parlance; indeed, dictionaries of the
time still primarily defined the word “gender” by reference to
grammatical classifications. See,
e.g., American Heritage
Dictionary, at 548 (def. 1(a)) (“Any set of two or more categories,
such as masculine, feminine, and neuter, into which words are
divided . . . and that determine agreement with or
the
selection of modifiers, referents, or
grammatical forms”).
While it is likely true that there have always
been individuals who experience what is now termed “gender
dysphoria,”
i.e., “[d]iscomfort or distress related to an
incongruence between an individual’s gender identity and the gender
assigned at birth,”[
31] the
current understanding of the concept postdates the enactment of
Title VII. Nothing resembling what is now called gender dysphoria
appeared in either DSM–I (1952) or DSM–II (1968). It was not until
1980 that the APA, in DSM–III, recognized two main psychiatric
diagnoses related to this condition, “Gender Identity Disorder of
Childhood” and “Transsexualism” in adolescents and adults.[
32] DSM–III, at 261–266.
The first widely publicized sex reassignment
surgeries in the United States were not performed until
1966,[
33] and the great
majority of physicians surveyed in 1969 thought that an individual
who sought sex reassignment surgery was either “ ‘severely
neurotic’ ” or “ ‘psychotic.’ ”[
34]
It defies belief to suggest that the public
meaning of discrimination because of sex in 1964 encompassed
discrimination on the basis of a concept that was essentially
unknown to the public at that time.
D
1
The Court’s main excuse for entirely ignoring
the social context in which Title VII was enacted is that the
meaning of Title VII’s prohibition of discrimination because of sex
is clear, and therefore it simply does not matter whether people in
1964 were “smart enough to realize” what its language means.
Hively, 853 F. 3d, at 357 (Posner, J., concurring).
According to the Court, an argument that looks to the societal
norms of those times represents an impermissible attempt to
displace the statutory language.
Ante, at 25–26.
The Court’s argument rests on a false premise.
As already explained at length, the text of Title VII does not
prohibit discrimination because of sexual orientation or gender
identity. And what the public thought about those issues in 1964 is
relevant and important, not because it provides a ground for
departing from the statutory text, but because it helps to explain
what the text was understood to mean when adopted.
In arguing that we must put out of our minds
what we know about the time when Title VII was enacted, the Court
relies on Justice Scalia’s opinion for the Court in
Oncale
v.
Sundowner Offshore Services, Inc.,
523 U.S.
75 (1998). But
Oncale is nothing like these cases, and
no one should be taken in by the majority’s effort to enlist
Justice Scalia in its updating project.
The Court’s unanimous decision in
Oncale
was thoroughly unremarkable. The Court held that a male employee
who alleged that he had been sexually harassed at work by other men
stated a claim under Title VII. Although the impetus for Title
VII’s prohibition of sex discrimination was to protect women,
anybody reading its terms would immediately appreciate that it
applies equally to both sexes, and by the time
Oncale
reached the Court, our precedent already established that sexual
harassment may constitute sex discrimination within the meaning of
Title VII. See
Meritor Savings Bank, FSB v.
Vinson,
477 U.S.
57 (1986). Given these premises, syllogistic reasoning dictated
the holding.
What today’s decision latches onto are
Oncale’s comments about whether “ ‘male-on-male sexual
harassment’ ” was on Congress’s mind when it enacted Title
VII.
Ante, at 28 (quoting 523 U. S., at 79). The Court
in
Oncale observed that this specific type of behavior “was
assuredly not the
principal evil Congress was concerned with
when it enacted Title VII,” but it found that immaterial because
“statutory prohibitions often go beyond the
principal evil
to cover reasonably comparable evils, and it is ultimately the
provisions of our laws rather than the
principal concerns of
our legislators by which we are governed.” 523 U. S., at 79
(emphasis added).
It takes considerable audacity to read these
comments as committing the Court to a position on deep
philosophical questions about the meaning of language and their
implications for the interpretation of legal rules. These comments
are better understood as stating mundane and uncontroversial
truths. Who would argue that a statute applies only to the
“principal evils” and not lesser evils that fall within the plain
scope of its terms? Would even the most ardent “purposivists” and
fans of legislative history contend that congressional intent is
restricted to Congress’s “
principal concerns”?
Properly understood,
Oncale does not
provide the slightest support for what the Court has done today.
For one thing, it would be a wild understatement to say that
discrimination because of sexual orientation and transgender status
was not the “principal evil” on Congress’s mind in 1964. Whether we
like to admit it now or not, in the thinking of Congress and the
public at that time, such discrimination would not have been evil
at all.
But the more important difference between these
cases and
Oncale is that here the interpretation that the
Court adopts does not fall within the ordinary meaning of the
statutory text as it would have been understood in 1964. To decide
for the defendants in
Oncale, it would have been necessary
to carve out an exception to the statutory text. Here, no such
surgery is at issue. Even if we totally disregard the societal
norms of 1964, the text of Title VII does not support the Court’s
holding. And the reasoning of
Oncale does not preclude or
counsel against our taking those norms into account. They are
relevant, not for the purpose of creating an exception to the terms
of the statute, but for the purpose of better appreciating how
those terms would have been understood at the time.
2
The Court argues that two other
decisions––
Phillips v.
Martin Marietta Corp.,
400 U.S.
542 (1971) (
per curiam), and
Los Angeles Dept.
of Water and Power v.
Manhart,
435
U.S. 702 (1978)––buttress its decision, but those cases merely
held that Title VII prohibits employer conduct that plainly
constitutes discrimination because of biological sex. In
Philips, the employer treated women with young children less
favorably than men with young children. In
Manhart, the
employer required women to make larger pension contributions than
men. It is hard to see how these holdings assist the Court.
The Court extracts three “lessons” from
Phillips,
Manhart, and
Oncale, but none sheds
any light on the question before us. The first lesson is that “it’s
irrelevant what an employer might call its discriminatory practice,
how others might label it, or what else might motivate it.”
Ante, at 14. This lesson is obviously true but proves
nothing. As to the label attached to a practice, has anyone ever
thought that the application of a law to a person’s conduct depends
on how it is labeled? Could a bank robber escape conviction by
saying he was engaged in asset enhancement? So if an employer
discriminates because of sex, the employer is liable no matter what
it calls its conduct, but if the employer’s conduct is not sex
discrimination, the statute does not apply. Thus, this lesson
simply takes us back to the question whether discrimination because
of sexual orientation or gender identity is a form of
discrimination because of biological sex. For reasons already
discussed, see Part I–A,
supra, it is not.
It likewise proves nothing of relevance here to
note that an employer cannot escape liability by showing that
discrimination on a prohibited ground was not its sole motivation.
So long as a prohibited ground was a motivating factor, the
existence of other motivating factors does not defeat
liability.
The Court makes much of the argument that “[i]n
Phillips, the employer could have accurately spoken of its
policy as one based on ‘motherhood.’ ”
Ante, at 14; see
also
ante, at 16. But motherhood, by definition, is a
condition that can be experienced only by women, so a policy that
distinguishes between motherhood and parenthood is necessarily a
policy that draws a sex-based distinction. There was sex
discrimination in
Phillips, because women with children were
treated disadvantageously compared to men with children.
Lesson number two—“the plaintiff ’s sex
need not be the sole or primary cause of the employer’s adverse
action,”
ante, at 14—is similarly unhelpful. The standard of
causation in these cases is whether sex is necessarily a
“motivating factor” when an employer discriminates on the basis of
sexual orientation or gender identity. 42 U. S. C.
§2000e–2(m). But the essential question—whether discrimination
because of sexual orientation or gender identity constitutes sex
discrimination—would be the same no matter what causation standard
applied. The Court’s extensive discussion of causation standards is
so much smoke.
Lesson number three––“an employer cannot escape
liability by demonstrating that it treats males and females
comparably as groups,”
ante, at 15, is also irrelevant.
There is no dispute that discrimination against an individual
employee based on that person’s sex cannot be justified on the
ground that the employer’s treatment of the average employee of
that sex is at least as favorable as its treatment of the average
employee of the opposite sex. Nor does it matter if an employer
discriminates against only a subset of men or women, where the same
subset of the opposite sex is treated differently, as in
Phillips. That is not the issue here. An employer who
discriminates equally on the basis of sexual orientation or gender
identity applies the same criterion to every affected
individual regardless of sex. See Part I–A,
supra.
III
A
Because the opinion of the Court flies a
textualist flag, I have taken pains to show that it cannot be
defended on textualist grounds. But even if the Court’s textualist
argument were stronger, that would not explain today’s decision.
Many Justices of this Court, both past and present, have not
espoused or practiced a method of statutory interpretation that is
limited to the analysis of statutory text. Instead, when there is
ambiguity in the terms of a statute, they have found it appropriate
to look to other evidence of “congressional intent,” including
legislative history.
So, why in these cases are congressional intent
and the legislative history of Title VII totally ignored? Any
assessment of congressional intent or legislative history seriously
undermines the Court’s interpretation.
B
As the Court explained in
General Elec.
Co. v.
Gilbert,
429 U.S.
125, 143 (1976), the legislative history of Title VII’s
prohibition of sex discrimination is brief, but it is nevertheless
revealing. The prohibition of sex discrimination was “added to
Title VII at the last minute on the floor of the House of
Representatives,”
Meritor Savings Bank, 477 U. S., at
63, by Representative Howard Smith, the Chairman of the Rules
Committee. See 110 Cong. Rec. 2577 (1964). Representative Smith had
been an ardent opponent of the civil rights bill, and it has been
suggested that he added the prohibition against discrimination on
the basis of “sex” as a poison pill. See,
e.g.,
Ulane
v.
Eastern Airlines, Inc., 742 F.2d 1081, 1085 (CA7 1984).
On this theory, Representative Smith thought that prohibiting
employment discrimination against women would be unacceptable to
Members who might have otherwise voted in favor of the bill and
that the addition of this prohibition might bring about the bill’s
defeat.[
35] But if
Representative Smith had been looking for a poison pill,
prohibiting discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation or
gender identity would have been far more potent. However, neither
Representative Smith nor any other Member said one word about the
possibility that the prohibition of sex discrimination might have
that meaning. Instead, all the debate concerned discrimination on
the basis of biological sex.[
36] See 110 Cong. Rec. 2577–2584.
Representative Smith’s motivations are
contested, 883 F. 3d, at 139–140 (Lynch, J., dissenting), but
whatever they were, the meaning of
the adoption of the
prohibition of sex discrimination is clear. It was no accident.
It grew out of “a long history of women’s rights advocacy that had
increasingly been gaining mainstream recognition and acceptance,”
and it marked a landmark achievement in the path toward fully equal
rights for women.
Id., at 140. “Discrimination against gay
women and men, by contrast, was not on the table for public debate
. . . [i]n those dark, pre-Stonewall days.”
Ibid.
For those who regard congressional intent as the
touchstone of statutory interpretation, the message of Title VII’s
legislative history cannot be missed.
C
Post-enactment events only clarify what was
apparent when Title VII was enacted. As noted, bills to add “sexual
orientation” to Title VII’s list of prohibited grounds were
introduced in every Congress beginning in 1975, see
supra,
at 2, and two such bills were before Congress in 1991[
37] when it made major changes in
Title VII. At that time, the three Courts of Appeals to reach the
issue had held that Title VII does not prohibit discrimination
because of sexual orientation,[
38] two other Circuits had endorsed that interpretation
in dicta,[
39] and no Court
of Appeals had held otherwise. Similarly, the three Circuits to
address the application of Title VII to transgender persons had all
rejected the argument that it covered discrimination on this
basis.[
40] These were also
the positions of the EEOC.[
41] In enacting substantial changes to Title VII, the
1991 Congress abrogated numerous judicial decisions with which it
disagreed. If it also disagreed with the decisions regarding sexual
orientation and transgender discrimination, it could have easily
overruled those as well, but it did not do so.[
42]
After 1991, six other Courts of Appeals reached
the issue of sexual orientation discrimination, and until 2017,
every single Court of Appeals decision understood Title VII’s
prohibition of “discrimination because of sex” to mean
discrimination because of biological sex.
See,
e.g.,
Higgins v.
New Balance
Athletic Shoe, Inc.,
194
F.3d 252, 259 (CA1 1999);
Simonton v.
Runyon,
232
F.3d 33, 36 (CA2 2000);
Bibby v.
Philadelphia
Coca Cola Bottling Co.,
260
F.3d 257, 261 (CA3 2001), cert. denied, 534 U.S. 1155
(2002);
Wrightson v.
Pizza Hut of Am.,
Inc.,
99
F.3d 138, 143 (CA4 1996);
Hamm v.
Weyauwega Milk
Products, Inc.,
332
F.3d 1058, 1062 (CA7 2003);
Medina v.
Income
Support Div., N. M.,
413
F.3d 1131, 1135 (CA10 2005);
Evans v.
Georgia
Regional Hospital, 850 F.3d 1248, 1255 (CA11), cert.
denied, 583 U. S. ___ (2017). Similarly, the other
Circuit to formally address whether Title VII applies to claims of
discrimination based on transgender status had also rejected the
argument, creating unanimous consensus prior to the Sixth Circuit’s
decision below. See
Etsitty v.
Utah Transit
Authority, 502 F.3d 1215, 1220–1221 (CA10 2007).
The Court observes that “[t]he people are
entitled to rely on the law as written, without fearing that courts
might disregard its plain terms,”
ante, at 24, but it has no
qualms about disregarding over 50 years of uniform judicial
interpretation of Title VII’s plain text. Rather, the Court makes
the jaw-dropping statement that its decision exemplifies “judicial
humility.”
Ante, at 31. Is it humble to maintain, not only
that Congress did not understand the terms it enacted in 1964, but
that all the Circuit Judges on all the pre-2017 cases could not see
what the phrase discrimination “because of sex” really means? If
today’s decision is humble, it is sobering to imagine what the
Court might do if it decided to be bold.
IV
What the Court has done today––interpreting
discrimination because of “sex” to encompass discrimination because
of sexual orientation or gender identity––is virtually certain to
have far-reaching consequences. Over 100 federal statutes prohibit
discrimination because of sex. See Appendix C,
infra;
e.g., 20 U. S. C. §1681(a) (Title IX); 42
U. S. C. §3631 (Fair Housing Act); 15 U. S. C.
1691(a)(1) (Equal Credit Opportunity Act). The briefs in these
cases have called to our attention the potential effects that the
Court’s reasoning may have under some of these laws, but the Court
waves those considerations aside. As to Title VII itself, the Court
dismisses questions about “bathrooms, locker rooms, or anything
else of the kind.”
Ante, at 31. And it declines to say
anything about other statutes whose terms mirror Title VII’s.
The Court’s brusque refusal to consider the
consequences of its reasoning is irresponsible. If the Court had
allowed the legislative process to take its course, Congress would
have had the opportunity to consider competing interests and might
have found a way of accommodating at least some of them. In
addition, Congress might have crafted special rules for some of the
relevant statutes. But by intervening and proclaiming categorically
that employment discrimination based on sexual orientation or
gender identity is simply a form of discrimination because of sex,
the Court has greatly impeded—and perhaps effectively ended—any
chance of a bargained legislative resolution. Before issuing
today’s radical decision, the Court should have given some thought
to where its decision would lead.
As the briefing in these cases has warned, the
position that the Court now adopts will threaten freedom of
religion, freedom of speech, and personal privacy and safety. No
one should think that the Court’s decision represents an unalloyed
victory for individual liberty.
I will briefly note some of the potential
consequences of the Court’s decision, but I do not claim to provide
a comprehensive survey or to suggest how any of these issues should
necessarily play out under the Court’s reasoning.[
43]
“[B]athrooms, locker rooms, [and other
things] of [that] kind.” The Court may wish to avoid this
subject, but it is a matter of concern to many people who are
reticent about disrobing or using toilet facilities in the presence
of individuals whom they regard as members of the opposite sex. For
some, this may simply be a question of modesty, but for others,
there is more at stake. For women who have been victimized by
sexual assault or abuse, the experience of seeing an unclothed
person with the anatomy of a male in a confined and sensitive
location such as a bathroom or locker room can cause serious
psychological harm.[
44]
Under the Court’s decision, however, transgender
persons will be able to argue that they are entitled to use a
bathroom or locker room that is reserved for persons of the sex
with which they identify, and while the Court does not define what
it means by a transgender person, the term may apply to individuals
who are “gender fluid,” that is, individuals whose gender identity
is mixed or changes over time.[
45] Thus, a person who has not undertaken any physical
transitioning may claim the right to use the bathroom or locker
room assigned to the sex with which the individual identifies at
that particular time. The Court provides no clue why a transgender
person’s claim to such bathroom or locker room access might not
succeed.
A similar issue has arisen under Title IX, which
prohibits sex discrimination by any elementary or secondary school
and any college or university that receives federal financial
assistance.[
46] In 2016, a
Department of Justice advisory warned that barring a student from a
bathroom assigned to individuals of the gender with which the
student identifies constitutes unlawful sex
discrimination,[
47] and some
lower court decisions have agreed. See
Whitaker v.
Kenosha Unified School Dist. No. 1 Bd. of Ed., 858 F.3d
1034, 1049 (CA7 2017);
G. G. v.
Gloucester Cty. School
Bd., 822 F.3d 709, 715 (CA4 2016), vacated and remanded, 580
U. S. ___ (2017);
Adams v.
School Bd. of St. Johns
Cty., 318 F. Supp. 3d 1293, 1325 (MD Fla. 2018); cf.
Doe
v.
Boyertown Area
School Dist., 897 F.3d 518, 533 (CA3
2018), cert. denied, 587 U. S. ___ (2019).
Women’s sports. Another issue that may
come up under both Title VII and Title IX is the right of a
transgender individual to participate on a sports team or in an
athletic competition previously reserved for members of one
biological sex.[
48] This
issue has already arisen under Title IX, where it threatens to
undermine one of that law’s major achievements, giving young women
an equal opportunity to participate in sports. The effect of the
Court’s reasoning may be to force young women to compete against
students who have a very significant biological advantage,
including students who have the size and strength of a male but
identify as female and students who are taking male hormones in
order to transition from female to male. See,
e.g.,
Complaint in
Soule v.
Connecticut Assn. of Schools,
No. 3:20–cv–00201 (D Conn., Apr. 17, 2020) (challenging Connecticut
policy allowing transgender students to compete in girls’ high
school sports); Complaint in
Hecox v.
Little, No.
1:20–cv–00184 (D Idaho, Apr. 15, 2020) (challenging state law that
bars transgender students from participating in school sports in
accordance with gender identity). Students in these latter
categories have found success in athletic competitions reserved for
females.[
49]
The logic of the Court’s decision could even
affect professional sports. Under the Court’s holding that Title
VII prohibits employment discrimination because of transgender
status, an athlete who has the physique of a man but identifies as
a woman could claim the right to play on a women’s professional
sports team. The owners of the team might try to claim that
biological sex is a bona fide occupational qualification (BFOQ)
under 42 U. S. C. §2000e–2(e), but the BFOQ exception has
been read very narrowly. See
Dothard v.
Rawlinson,
433 U.S.
321, 334 (1977).
Housing. The Court’s decision may lead to
Title IX cases against any college that resists assigning students
of the opposite biological sex as roommates. A provision of Title
IX, 20 U. S. C. §1686, allows schools to maintain
“separate living facilities for the different sexes,” but it may be
argued that a student’s “sex” is the gender with which the student
identifies.[
50] Similar
claims may be brought under the Fair Housing Act. See 42
U. S. C. §3604.
Employment by religious organizations.
Briefs filed by a wide range of religious groups––Christian,
Jewish, and Muslim––express deep concern that the position now
adopted by the Court “will trigger open conflict with faith-
based employment practices of numerous churches,
synagogues, mosques, and other religious institutions.”[
51] They argue that “[r]eligious
organizations need employees who actually live the faith,”[
52] and that compelling a religious
organization to employ individuals whose conduct flouts the tenets
of the organization’s faith forces the group to communicate an
objectionable message.
This problem is perhaps most acute when it comes
to the employment of teachers. A school’s standards for its faculty
“communicate a particular way of life to its students,” and a
“violation by the faculty of those precepts” may undermine the
school’s “moral teaching.”[
53] Thus, if a religious school teaches that sex outside
marriage and sex reassignment procedures are immoral, the message
may be lost if the school employs a teacher who is in a same-sex
relationship or has undergone or is undergoing sex reassignment.
Yet today’s decision may lead to Title VII claims by such teachers
and applicants for employment.
At least some teachers and applicants for
teaching positions may be blocked from recovering on such claims by
the “ministerial exception” recognized in
Hosanna-Tabor
Evangelical Lutheran Church and School v.
EEOC,
565 U.S.
171 (2012). Two cases now pending before the Court present the
question whether teachers who provide religious instruction can be
considered to be “ministers.”[
54] But even if teachers with those responsibilities
qualify, what about other very visible school employees who may not
qualify for
the ministerial exception? Provisions of Title
VII provide exemptions for certain religious organizations and
schools “with respect to the employment of individuals of a
particular religion to perform work connected with the carrying on”
of the “activities” of the organization or school, 42
U. S. C. §2000e–1(a); see also §2000e–2(e)(2), but the
scope of these provisions is disputed, and as interpreted by some
lower courts, they provide only narrow protection.[
55]
Healthcare. Healthcare benefits may
emerge as an intense battleground under the Court’s holding.
Transgender employees have brought suit under Title VII to
challenge employer-provided health insurance plans that do not
cover costly sex reassignment surgery.[
56] Similar claims have been brought under the
Affordable Care Act (ACA), which broadly prohibits sex
discrimination in the provision of healthcare.[
57]
Such claims present difficult religious liberty
issues because some employers and healthcare providers have strong
religious objections to sex reassignment procedures, and therefore
requiring them to pay for or to perform these procedures will have
a severe impact on their ability to honor their deeply held
religious beliefs.
Freedom of speech. The Court’s decision
may even affect the way employers address their employees and the
way teachers and school officials address students. Under
established English usage, two sets of sex-specific singular
personal pronouns are used to refer to someone in the third person
(he, him, and his for males; she, her, and hers for females). But
several different sets of gender-neutral pronouns have now been
created and are preferred by some individuals who do not identify
as falling into either of the two traditional categories.[
58] Some jurisdictions, such as New
York City, have ordinances making the failure to use an
individual’s preferred pronoun a punishable offense,[
59] and some colleges have similar
rules.[
60] After today’s
decision, plaintiffs may claim that the failure to use their
preferred pronoun violates one of the federal laws prohibiting sex
discrimination. See
Prescott v.
Rady Children’s Hospital
San Diego, 265 F. Supp. 3d 1090, 1098–1100 (SD Cal. 2017)
(hospital staff ’s refusal to use preferred pronoun violates
ACA).[
61]
The Court’s decision may also pressure employers
to suppress any statements by employees expressing disapproval of
same-sex relationships and sex reassignment procedures. Employers
are already imposing such restrictions voluntarily, and after
today’s decisions employers will fear that allowing employees to
express their religious views on these subjects may give rise to
Title VII harassment claims.
Constitutional claims. Finally, despite
the important differences between the Fourteenth Amendment and
Title VII, the Court’s decision may exert a gravitational pull in
constitutional cases. Under our precedents, the Equal Protection
Clause prohibits sex-based discrimination unless a “heightened”
standard of review is met.
Sessions v.
Morales-Santana, 582 U. S. ___, ___ (2017) (slip op.,
at 8);
United States v.
Virginia,
518 U.S.
515, 532–534 (1996). By equating discrimination because of
sexual orientation or gender identity with discrimination because
of sex, the Court’s decision will be cited as a ground for
subjecting all three forms of discrimination to the same exacting
standard of review.
Under this logic, today’s decision may have
effects that extend well beyond the domain of federal anti-
discrimination statutes. This potential is illustrated by pending
and recent lower court cases in which transgender individuals have
challenged a variety of federal, state, and local laws and policies
on constitutional grounds. See,
e.g., Complaint in
Hecox, No. 1: 20–CV–00184 (state law prohibiting transgender
students from competing in school sports in accordance with their
gender identity); Second Amended Complaint in
Karnoski v.
Trump, No. 2:17–cv–01297 (WD Wash., July 31, 2019)
(military’s ban on transgender members);
Kadel v.
Folwell, ___ F. Supp. 3d ___, ___–___, 2020 WL 1169271,
*10–*11 (MDNC, Mar. 11, 2020) (state health plan’s exclusion of
coverage for sex reassignment procedures); Complaint in
Gore
v.
Lee, No. 3:19–cv–00328 (MD Tenn., Mar. 3, 2020) (change
of gender on birth certificates); Brief for Appellee in
Grimm v.
Gloucester Cty. School Bd., No. 19–1952
(CA4, Nov. 18, 2019) (transgender student forced to use gender
neutral bathrooms at school); Complaint in
Corbitt v.
Taylor, No. 2:18–cv–00091 (MD Ala., July 25, 2018)
(change of gender on driver’s licenses);
Whitaker, 858
F. 3d, at 1054 (school policy requiring students to use the
bathroom that corresponds to the sex on birth certificate);
Keohane v.
Florida Dept. of Corrections Secretary,
952 F.3d 1257, 1262–1265 (CA11 2020) (transgender prisoner denied
hormone therapy and ability to dress and groom as a female);
Edmo v.
Corizon, Inc., 935 F.3d 757, 767 (CA9 2019)
(transgender prisoner requested sex reassignment surgery); cf.
Glenn v.
Brumby, 663 F.3d 1312, 1320 (CA11 2011)
(transgender individual fired for gender non-conformity).
Although the Court does not want to think about
the consequences of its decision, we will not be able to avoid
those issues for long. The entire Federal Judiciary will be mired
for years in disputes about the reach of the Court’s reasoning.
* * *
The updating desire to which the Court
succumbs no doubt arises from humane and generous impulses. Today,
many Americans know individuals who are gay, lesbian, or
transgender and want them to be treated with the dignity,
consideration, and fairness that everyone deserves. But the
authority of this Court is limited to saying what the law
is.
The Court itself recognizes this:
“The place to make new legislation
. . . lies in Congress. When it comes to statutory
interpretation, our role is limited to applying the law’s demands
as faithfully as we can in the cases that come before us.”
Ante, at 31.
It is easy to utter such words. If only the
Court would live by them.
I respectfully dissent.
APPENDIXES
A
Webster’s New International Dictionary 2296
(2d ed. 1953):
sex (sĕks),
n. [F.
sexe,
fr. L.
sexus; prob. orig., division, and
akin to L.
secare to cut. See section.]
1. One of the two divisions of organisms formed on the
distinction of male and female; males or females collectively.
2. The sum of the peculiarities of structure and function
that distinguish a male from a female organism; the character of
being male or female, or of pertaining to the distinctive function
of the male or female in reproduction.
Conjugation, or
fertilization (union of germplasm of two individuals), a
process evidently of great but not readily explainable importance
in the perpetuation of most organisms, seems to be the function of
differentiation of sex, which occurs in nearly all organisms at
least at some stage in their life history. Sex is manifested in the
conjugating cells by the larger size, abundant food material, and
immobility of the female gamete (
egg,
egg cell, or
ovum), and the small size and the locomotive power of the
male gamete (
spermatozoon or
spermatozoid), and in
the adult organisms often by many structural, physiological, and
(in higher forms) psychological characters, aside from the
necessary modification of the reproductive apparatus. Cf.
HERMAPHRODITE, 1. In botany the term
sex is often extended
to the distinguishing peculiarities of staminate and pistillate
flowers, and hence in dioecious plants to the individuals bearing
them.
In many animals and plants the body and germ
cells have been shown to contain one or more chromosomes of a
special kind (called
sex chromosomes; idiochromosomes; accessory
chromosomes) in addition to the ordinary paired autosomes.
These special chromosomes serve to determine sex. In the simplest
case, the male germ cells are of two types, one with and one
without a single extra chromosome (
X chromosome, or
monosome). The egg cells in this case all possess an
X chromosome, and on fertilization by the two types
of sperm, male and female zygotes result, of respective
constitution
X, and
XX. In many other animals and
plants (probably including man) the male organism produces two
types of gametes, one possessing an
X chromosome, the other
a
Y chromosome, these being visibly different members of a
pair of chromosomes present in the diploid state. In this case
also, the female organism is
XX, the eggs
X, and the
zygotes respectively male (
XY) and female (
XX). In
another type of sex determination, as in certain moths and possibly
in the fowl, the female produces two kinds of eggs, the male only
one kind of sperm. Each type of egg contains one member of a pair
of differentiated chromosomes, called respectively
Z
chromosomes and
W chromosomes, while all the sperm cells
contain a
Z chromosome. In fertilization, union of a
Z with a
W gives rise to a female, while union of two
Z chromosomes produces a male. Cf. secondary sex
character.
3. a The sphere of behavior dominated by
the relations between male and female.
b
Psychoanalysis. By extension, the whole sphere of behavior
related even indirectly to the sexual functions and embracing all
affectionate and pleasure-seeking conduct.
4. Phenomena of sexual instincts and
their manifestations.
5. Sect;—a confused use.
Syn.—Sex, gender. Sex refers to
physiological distinctions; GENDER, to distinctions in grammar.
—the sex. The female sex;
women, in general.
sex, adj. Based on or appealing
to sex.
sex, v. t. To determine the sex
of, as skeletal remains.
Webster’s Third New International Dictionary
2081 (1966):
1sex \‘seks\ n
–es
often attrib [ME, fr. L
sexus; prob. akin to L
secare to cut–more at saw]
1: one of the two
divisions of organic esp. human beings respectively designated male
or female
2: the sum of the morphological, physiological,
and behavioral peculiarities of living beings that subserves
biparental reproduction with its concomitant genetic segregation
and recombination which underlie most evolutionary change, that in
its typical dichotomous occurrence is usu. genetically controlled
and associated with special sex chromosomes, and that is typically
manifested as maleness and femaleness with one or the other of
these being present in most higher animals though both may occur in
the same individual in many plants and some invertebrates and
though no such distinction can be made in many lower forms (as some
fungi, protozoans, and possibly bacteria and viruses) either
because males and females are replaced by mating types or because
the participants in sexual reproduction are
indistinguishable—compare heterothallic, homothallic;
fertilization, meio- sis, mendel’s law; freemartin, hermaphrodite,
intersex
3: the sphere of interpersonal behavior esp.
between male and female most directly associated with, leading up
to, substituting for, or resulting from genital union
4: the
phenomena of sexual instincts and their manifestations ;
specif: sexual intercourse
2sex \“\
vt –ED/–ING/–ES
1: to determine the sex of (an organic being) —compare
autosexing
2 a: to increase the sexual appeal or attraction
of—usu. used with
up b: to arouse the sexual
instincts or desires of—usu. used with
up
9 Oxford English Dictionary 577–578
(1933):
Sex (seks),
sb. Also 6–7 sexe, (6
seex, 7 pl. sexe, 8
poss. sexe’s). [ad. L.
sexus
(
u-stem), whence also F.
sexe (12th c.), Sp., Pg.
sexo, It.
sesso. Latin had also a form
secus
neut. (indeclinable).]
1. Either of the two divisions of
organic beings distinguished as male and female respectively; the
males or the females (of a species, etc., esp. of the human race)
viewed collectively.
1382 Wyclif
Gen. vi. 19 Of alle
thingis hauynge sowle of ony flehs, two thow shalt brynge into the
ark, that maal sex and femaal lyuen with thee.
1532 More
Confut. Tindale II. 152, I had as leue he bare them both a
bare cheryte, as wyth the frayle feminyne sexe fall to far in loue.
1559 Alymer
Harborowe E 4 b, Neither of them debarred
the heires female .. as though it had ben .. vnnatural for that
sexe to gouern.
1576 Gascoigne
Philomene xcviii, I
speake against my sex.
a 1586 Sidney
Arcadia
II. (1912) 158 The sexe of womankind of all other is most bound to
have regardfull eie to mens judgements.
1600 Nashe
Summer’s Last Will F 3 b, A woman they imagine her to be,
Because that sexe keepes nothing close they heare.
1615
Crooke
Body of Man 274 If wee respect the .. conformation of
both the Sexes, the Male is sooner perfected .. in the wombe.
1634 Sir T. Herbert
Trav. 19 Both sexe goe naked.
1667 Milton
P. L. IX, 822 To add what wants In Femal
Sex.
1671—Samson 774 It was a weakness In me, but
incident to all our sex.
1679 Dryden
Troilus &
Cr. I. ii, A strange dissembling sex we women are.
1711
Addison
Spect. No. 10 ¶ 6 Their Amusements .. are more
adapted to the Sex than to the Species.
1730 Swift
Let.
to Mrs. Whiteway 28 Dec., You have neither the scrawl nor the
spelling of your sex.
1742 Gray
Propertius II. 73 She
.. Condemns her fickle Sexe’s fond Mistake.
1763 G. Williams
in Jesse
Selwyn & Contemp. (1843) I. 265 It would
astonish you to see the mixture of sexes at this place.
1780
Bentham
Princ. Legisl. VI. §35 The sensibility of the female
sex appears .. to be greater than that of the male.
1814
Scott
Ld. of Isles VI. iii, Her sex’s dress regain’d.
1836 Thirlwall
Greece xi. II. 51 Solon also made
regulations for the government of the other sex.
1846
Ecclesiologist Feb. 41 The propriety and necessity of
dividing the sexes during the publick offices of the Church.
1848 Thackeray
Van. Fair xxv, She was by no means so
far superior to her sex as to be above jealousy.
1865
Dickens
Mut. Fr. II. i, It was a school for both sexes.
1886 Mabel Collins
Prettiest Woman ii, Zadwiga had
not yet given any serious attention to the other sex.
b. collect. followed by plural
verb.
rare.
1768 Goldsm.
Good. n. Man IV.
(Globe) 632/2 Our sex are like poor tradesmen.
1839 Malcom
Trav. (1840) 40/I Neither sex tattoo any part of their
bodies.
c. The fair(er), gentle(r), soft(er),
weak(er) sex; the devout sex;
the second sex; †
the
woman sex: the female sex, women.
The †
better,
sterner sex: the male sex, men.
[
1583 Stubbes
Anat. Abus. E vij
b, Ye magnificency & liberalitie of that gentle sex.
1613 Purchas
Pilgrimage (1614) 38 Strong Sampson and
wise Solomon are witnesses, that the strong men are slaine by this
weaker sexe.]
1641 Brome
Jovial Crew III.
(1652) H 4, I am bound by a strong vow to kisse all of the woman
sex I meet this morning.
1648 J. Beaumont
Psyche XIV.
I, The softer sex, attending Him And his still-growing woes.
1665 Sir T. Herbert
Trav. (1677) 22 Whiles the better
sex seek prey abroad, the women (therein like themselves) keep home
and spin.
1665 Boyle
Occas. Refl. v. ix. 176 Persons
of the fairer Sex. a
1700 Evelyn
Diary 12 Nov. an.
1644, The Pillar .. at which the devout sex are always rubbing
their chaplets.
1701 Stanhope
St. Aug. Medit. I.
xxxv. (1704) 82, I may .. not suffer my self to be outdone by the
weaker Sex.
1732 [see FAIR a. I b].
1753 Hogarth
Anal. Beauty x. 65 An elegant degree of plumpness peculiar
to the skin of the softer sex.
1820 Byron
Juan IV.
cviii, Benign Ceruleans of the second sex! Who advertise new poems
by your looks.
1838 Murray’s Hand-bk. N. Germ. 430 It
is much frequented by the fair sex.
1894 C. D. Tyler in
Geog. Jrnl. III. 479 They are beardless, and usually wear a
shock of unkempt hair, which is somewhat finer in the gentler
sex.
¶d. Used occas. with extended notion.
The third sex: eunuchs. Also
sarcastically (see quot.
1873).
1820 Byron
Juan IV. lxxxvi, From
all the Pope makes yearly, ‘twould perplex To find three perfect
pipes of the third sex.
Ibid. V. xxvi, A black old neutral
personage Of the third sex stept up. [
1873 Ld. Houghton
Monogr. 280 Sydney Smith .. often spoke with much bitterness
of the growing belief in three Sexes of Humanity—Men, Women, and
Clergymen.]
e. The sex: the female sex. [F.
le sexe.] Now
rare.
1589 Puttenham
Eng. Poesie III.
xix. (Arb.) 235 As he that had tolde a long tale before certaine
noble women, of a matter somewhat in honour touching the Sex.
1608 D. T[uvill]
Ess. Pol. & Mor. 101 b, Not yet
weighing with himselfe, the weaknesse and imbecillitie of the sex.
1631 Massinger
Emperor East I. ii, I am called The
Squire of Dames, or Servant of the Sex.
1697 Vanbrugh
Prov. Wife II. ii, He has a strange penchant to grow fond of
me, in spite of his aversion to the sex.
1760-2 Goldsm.
Cit. W. xcix, The men of Asia behave with more deference to
the sex than you seem to imagine.
1792 A. Young
Trav.
France I. 220 The sex of Venice are undoubtedly of a
distinguished beauty.
1823 Byron
Juan XIII. lxxix, We
give the sex the
pas.
1863 R. F. Burton
W.
Africa I. 22 Going ‘up stairs’, as the sex says, at 5 a.m. on
the day after arrival, I cast the first glance at Funchal.
f. Without
the, in predicative
quasi-adj. use=feminine.
rare.
a 1700 Dryden
Cymon &
Iph. 368 She hugg’d th’ Offender, and forgave th’ Offence, Sex
to the last!
2. Quality in respect of being male or
female.
a. With regard to persons or
animals.
1526 Pilgr. Perf. (W. de. W.
1531) 282 b, Ye bee, whiche neuer gendreth with ony make of his
kynde, nor yet hath ony distinct sex.
1577 T. Kendall
Flowers of Epigr. 71 b, If by corps supposd may be her seex,
then sure a virgin she.
1616 T. Scott
Philomythie I.
(ed. 2) A 3 Euen as Hares change shape and sex, some say Once euery
yeare.
1658 Sir T. Browne
Hydriot. iii. 18 A critical
view of bones makes a good distinction of sexes.
a 1665
Digby
Chym. Secrets (1682) II. 225 Persons of all Ages and
Sexes.
1667 Milton
P. L. I. 424 For Spirits when they
please can either Sex assume, or both.
1710-11 Swift
Jrnl. to Stella 7 Mar., I find I was mistaken in the sex,
‘tis a boy.
1757 Smollett
Reprisal IV. v, As for me,
my sex protects me.
1825 Scott
Betrothed xiii, I am
but a poor and neglected woman, feeble both from sex and age.
1841 Elphinstone
Hist. India I. 349 When persons of
different sexes walk together, the woman always follows the man.
1882 Tension-Woods
Fish N. S. Wales 116 Oysters are
of distinct sexes.
b. with regard to plants (see Female
a. 2, Male
a. 2).
1567 Maplet
Gr. Forest 28 Some
seeme to haue both sexes and kindes: as the Oke, the Lawrell and
such others.
1631 Widdowes
Nat. Philos. (ed. 2) 49
There be sexes of hearbes .. namely, the Male or Female.
1720 P. Blair
Bot. Ess. iv. 237 These being very
evident Proofs of a necessity of two Sexes in Plants as well as in
Animals.
1790 Smellie
Philos. Nat. Hist. I. 245 There
is not a notion more generally adopted, that that vegetables have
the distinction of sexes.
1848 Lindley
Introd. Bot.
(ed. 4) II. 80 Change of Sex under the influence of external
causes.
3. The distinction between male and
female in general. In recent use often with more explicit notion:
The sum of those differences in the structure and function of the
reproductive organs on the ground of which beings are distinguished
as male and female, and of the other physiological differences
consequent on these; the class of phenomena with which these
differences are concerned.
Organs of sex: the reproductive organs
in sexed animals or plants.
a 1631 Donne
Songs &
Sonn., The Printrose Poems 1912 I. 61 Should she Be more then
woman, she would get above All thought of sexe, and think to move
My heart to study her, and not to love.
a 1643
Cartwright
Siedge III. vi, My Soul’s As Male as yours;
there’s no Sex in the mind.
1748 Melmoth
Fitzosborne
Lett. lxii. (1749) II. 119 There may be a kind of sex in the
very soul.
1751 Harris
Hermes Wks. (1841) 129 Besides
number, another characteristic, visible in substances, is that of
sex.
1878 Gladstone
Prim. Homer 68 Athenè .. has
nothing of sex except the gender, nothing of the woman except the
form.
1887 K. Pearson
Eth. Freethought xv. (1888) 429
What is the true type of social (moral) action in matters of sex?
1895 Crackanthorpe in 19
th Cent. Apr. 607 (art.) Sex
in modern literature.
Ibid. 614 The writers and readers who
have strenuously refused to allow to sex its place in creative art.
1912 H. G. Wells
Marriage ii. § 6. 72 The young need
.. to be told .. all we know of three fundamental things; the first
of which is God, .. and the third Sex.
¶ 4. Used, by confusion, in senses of
Sect (q. v. I, 4 b, 7, and cf. I d
note).
1575-85 Abp. Sandys
Serm. xx. 358
So are all sexes and sorts of people called vpon.
1583
Melbancke
Philotimus L iij b, Whether thinkest thou better
sporte & more absurd, to see an Asse play on an harpe contrary
to his sex, or heare [etc.].
1586 J. Hooker
Hist.
Irel. 180/2 in
Holinshed, The whole sex of the
Oconhours.
1586 T. B.
La Primaud. Fr. Acad. I. 359 O
detestable furie, not to be found in most cruell beasts, which
spare the blood of their sexe.
a 1704 T Brown
Dial. Dead,
Friendship Wks. 1711 IV. 56 We have had enough of these
Christians, and sure there can be no worse among the other Sex of
Mankind [i.e. Jews and Turks]?
1707 Atterbury
Large Vind.
Doctr. 47 Much less can I imagine, why a Jewish Sex (whether of
Pharisees or Saducees) should be represented, as [etc.].
5. attrib. and
Comb., as
sex-distinction, function, etc.;
sex-abusing,
transforming adjs.; sex-cell, a reproductive cell, with either
male or female function; a sperm-cell or an egg-cell.
1642 H. More
Song of Soul I. III.
lxxi, Mad-making waters, sex trans-forming springs.
1781
Cowper
Expost. 415 Sin, that in old time Brought fire from
heav’n, the sex-abusing crime.
1876 Hardy
Ethelberta
xxxvii, You cannot have celebrity and sex-privilege both.
1887 Jrnl. Educ. No. 210. 29 If this examination
craze is to prevail, and the sex-abolitionists are to have their
way.
1889 Geddes & Thomson
Evol. Sex 91 Very
commonly the sex-cells originate in the ectoderm and ripen there.
1894 H. Drummond
Ascent of Man 317 The
sex-distinction slowly gathers definition.
1897 J.
Hutchinson
in Arch. Surg. VIII. 230 Loss of Sex
Function.
Sex (seks),
v. [f. Sex
sb.]
trans. To determine the sex of, by anatomical
examination; to label as male or female.
1884 Gurney
Diurnal Birds Prey
173 The specimen is not sexed, neither is the sex noted on the
drawing.
1888 A. Newton in
Zoologist Ser. 111. XII.
101 The .. barbarous phrase of ‘collecting a specimen’ and then of
‘sexing’ it.
Concise Oxford Dictionary of Current English
1164 (5th ed. 1964):
sĕx, n. Being male or female or
hermaphrodite (
what is its ~?; ~ does not matter; without
distinction of age or ~), whence ~’LESS a., ~’
lėssNESS
n., ~’Y2 a., immoderately concerned with ~; males or females
collectively (
all ranks & both ~es; the fair, gentle,
softer, weaker, ~, & joc.
the ~, women;
the
sterner ~, men;
is the fairest of her ~); (attrib.)
arising from difference, or consciousness, of ~ (~
antagonism, ~
instinct, ~
urge); ~
appeal, attractiveness arising from difference of ~. [f. L
sexus –ūs; partly thr. F]
Random House Dictionary of the English
Language 1307 (1966):
sex (seks),
n. 1. The
fact or character of being either male or female:
persons of
different sex. 2. either of the two groups of
persons exhibiting this character:
the stronger sex; the gentle
sex. 3. the sum of the structural and functional
differences by which the male and female are distinguished, or the
phenomena or behavior dependent on these differences.
4. the
instinct or attraction drawing one sex toward another, or its
manifestation in life and conduct.
5. coitus.
6. to have
sex, Informal. to engage in sexual intercourse.
–
v.t. 7. to ascertain the sex of, esp. of newly
hatched chicks.
8. sex it up, Slang. to neck
passionately:
They were really sexing it up last night.
9. sex up, Informal. a. to arouse
sexually:
She certainly knows how to sex up the men.
b. to increase the appeal of; to make more interesting,
attractive, or exciting:
We’ve decided to sex up the movie with
some battle scenes. [ME < L
sex(
us), akin to
secus, deriv. of
secāre to cut, divide; see
SECTION]
American Heritage Dictionary 1187
(1969):
sex (sĕks)
n. 1. a.
The property or quality by which organ-isms are classified
according to their reproductive functions.
b. Either of two
divisions, designated
male and
female, of this
classification.
2. Males or females collectively.
3.
The condition or character of being male or female; the
physiological, functional, and psychological differences that
distinguish the male and the female.
4. The sexual urge or
instinct as it manifests itself in behavior.
5. Sexual
intercourse. –
tr.v. sexed, sexing, sexes. To
determine the sex of (young chickens). [Middle English, from Old
French
sexe, from Latin
sexus†.]
B
Webster’s Third New International Dictionary
2081 (2002):
1sex \‘seks\ n –es
often
attrib [ME, fr. L
sexus; prob. akin to L
secare
to cut—more at saw]
1: one of the two divisions of organic
esp. human beings respectively designated male or female
2:
the sum of the morphological, physiological, and behavioral
peculiarities of living beings that subserves biparental
reproduction with its concomitant genetic segregation and
recombination which underlie most evolutionary change, that in its
typical dichotomous occurrence is usu. genetically controlled and
associated with special sex chromosomes, and that is typically
manifested as maleness and femaleness with one or the other of
these being present in most higher animals though both may occur in
the same individual in many plants and some invertebrates and
though no such distinction can be made in many lower forms (as some
fungi, protozoans, and possibly bacteria and viruses) either
because males and females are replaced by mating types or because
the participants in sexual reproduction are
indistinguishable—compare heterothallic, homothallic;
fertilization, meiosis, mendel’s law; freemartin, hermaphrodite,
intersex
3: the sphere of interpersonal behavior esp.
between male and female most directly associated with, leading up
to, substituting for, or resulting from genital union
4: the
phenomena of sexual instincts and their manifestations ;
specif: sexual intercourse
2sex \“\
vt –ed/–ing/–es
1: to determine the sex of (an organic being) —compare
autosexing
2 a: to increase the sexual appeal or attraction
of—usu. used with
up b: to arouse the sexual
instincts or desires of—usu. used with
up
Random House Webster’s Unabridged Dictionary
1754 (2d ed. 2001):
Sex (seks),
n.
1. either
the male or female division of a species, esp. as differentiated
with reference to the reproductive functions.
2. the sum of
the structural and functional differences by which the male and
female are distinguished, or the phenomena or behavior dependent on
these differences.
3. the instinct or attraction drawing one
sex toward another, or its manifestation in life and conduct.
4. coitus.
5. genitalia.
6.
to have
sex, to engage in sexual intercourse. –
v.t. 7.
to ascertain the sex of, esp. of newly-hatched chicks.
8.
sex up,
Informal.
a. to arouse sexually:
The only intent of that show was to sex up the audience.
b. to increase the appeal of; to make more interesting,
attractive, or exciting:
We’ve decided to sex up the movie with
some battle scenes. [1350–1400; ME < L
Sexus, perh.
akin to
secāre to divide (see section)]
American Heritage Dictionary 1605 (5th ed.
2011):
Sex (seks)
n.
1a. Sexual
activity, especially sexual intercourse:
hasn’t had sex in
months.
b. The sexual urge or instinct as it manifests
itself in behavior:
motivated by sex.
2a. Either of
the two divisions, designated female and male, by which most
organisms are classified on the basis of their reproductive organs
and functions:
How do you determine the sex of a lobster?
b. The fact or condition of existing in these two divisions,
especially the collection of characteristics that distinguish
female and male:
the evolution of sex in plants; a study that
takes sex into account. See Usage Note at
gender. 3.
Females or males considered as a group:
dormitories that house
only one sex. 4. One’s identity as either female or
male.
5. The genitals.
⸭ tr.v. sexed,
sex-ing, sex-es 1. To determine the sex of (an organism).
2. Slang a. To arouse sexually. Often used
with
up.
b. To increase the appeal or attractiveness
of. Often used with
up [Middle English < Latin
sexus.]
C
Statutes Prohibiting Sex
Discrimination
2 U. S. C. §658a(2) (Congressional
Budget and Fiscal Operations; Federal Mandates)
2 U. S. C. §1311(a)(1) (Congressional
Accountability; Extension of Rights and Protections)
2 U. S. C. §1503(2) (Unfunded
Mandates Reform)
3 U. S. C. §411(a)(1) (Presidential
Offices; Employment Discrimination)
5 U. S. C. §2301(b)(2) (Merit System
Principles)
5 U. S. C. §2302(b)(1) (Prohibited
Personnel Practices)
5 U. S. C. §7103(a)(4)(A)
(Labor-Management Relations; Definitions)
5 U. S. C. §7116(b)(4)
(Labor-Management Relations; Unfair Labor Practices)
5 U. S. C. §7201(b)
(Antidiscrimination Policy; Minority Recruitment Program)
5 U. S. C. §7204(b)
(Antidiscrimination; Other Prohibitions)
6 U. S. C. §488f(b) (Secure Handling
of Ammonium Nitrate; Protection From Civil Liability)
7 U. S. C. §2020(c)(1) (Supplemental
Nutrition Assistance Program)
8 U. S. C. §1152(a)(1)(A)
(Immigration; Numerical Limitations on Individual Foreign
States)
8 U. S. C. §1187(c)(6) (Visa Waiver
Program for Certain Visitors)
8 U. S. C. §1522(a)(5) (Authorization
for Programs for Domestic Resettlement of and Assistance to
Refugees)
10 U. S. C. §932(b)(4) (Uniform Code
of Military Justice; Article 132 Retaliation)
10 U. S. C. §1034(j)(3) (Protected
Communications; Prohibition of Retaliatory Personnel Actions)
12 U. S. C. §302 (Directors of
Federal Reserve Banks; Number of Members; Classes)
12 U. S. C. §1735f–5(a) (Prohibition
Against Discrimination on Account of Sex in Extension of Mortgage
Assistance)
12 U. S. C. §1821(d)(13)(E)(iv)
(Federal Deposit Insurance Corporation; Insurance Funds)
12 U. S. C. §1823(d)(3)(D)(iv)
(Federal Deposit Insurance Corporation; Corporation Moneys)
12 U. S. C. §2277a–10c(b)(13)(E)(iv)
(Farm Credit System Insurance Corporation; Corporation as
Conservator or Receiver; Certain Other Powers)
12 U. S. C. §3015(a)(4) (National
Consumer Cooperative Bank; Eligibility of Cooperatives)
12 U. S. C. §§3106a(1)(B) and (2)(B)
(Foreign Bank Participation in Domestic Markets)
12 U. S. C. §4545(1) (Fair
Housing)
12 U. S. C. §5390(a)(9)(E)(v) (Wall
Street Reform and Consumer Protection; Powers and Duties of the
Corporation)
15 U. S. C. §631(h) (Aid to Small
Business)
15 U. S. C. §633(b)(1) (Small
Business Administration)
15 U. S. C. §719 (Alaska Natural Gas
Transportation; Civil Rights)
15 U. S. C. §775 (Federal Energy
Administration; Sex Discrimination; Enforcement; Other Legal
Remedies)
15 U. S. C. §1691(a)(1) (Equal Credit
Opportunity Act)
15 U. S. C. §1691d(a) (Equal Credit
Opportunity Act)
15 U. S. C. §3151(a) (Full Employment
and Balanced Growth; Nondiscrimination)
18 U. S. C. §246 (Deprivation of
Relief Benefits)
18 U. S. C. §3593(f ) (Special
Hearing To Determine Whether a Sentence of Death Is Justified)
20 U. S. C. §1011(a) (Higher
Education Resources and Student Assistance; Antidiscrimination)
20 U. S. C. §1011f(h)(5)(D)
(Disclosures of Foreign Gifts)
20 U. S. C. §1066c(d) (Historically
Black College and University Capital Financing; Limitations on
Federal Insurance Bonds Issued by Designated Bonding Authority)
20 U. S. C. §1071(a)(2) (Federal
Family Education Loan Program)
20 U. S. C. §1078(c)(2)(F) (Federal
Payments To Reduce Student Interest Costs)
20 U. S. C. §1087–1(e) (Federal
Family Education Loan Program; Special Allowances)
20 U. S. C. §1087–2(e) (Student Loan
Marketing Association)
20 U. S. C. §1087–4 (Discrimination
in Secondary Markets Prohibited)
20 U. S. C. §1087tt(c) (Discretion of
Student Financial Aid Administrators)
20 U. S. C. §1231e(b)(2) (Education
Programs; Use of Funds Withheld)
20 U. S. C. §1681 (Title IX of the
Education Amendments of 1972)
20 U. S. C. §1701(a)(1) (Equal
Educational Opportunities; Congressional Declaration of Policy)
20 U. S. C. §1702(a)(1) (Equal
Educational Opportunities; Congressional Findings)
20 U. S. C. §1703 (Denial of Equal
Educational Opportunity Prohibited)
20 U. S. C. §1705 (Assignment on
Neighborhood Basis Not a Denial of Equal Educational
Opportunity)
20 U. S. C. §1715 (District
Lines)
20 U. S. C. §1720 (Equal Educational
Opportunities; Definitions)
20 U. S. C. §1756 (Remedies With
Respect to School District Lines)
20 U. S. C. §2396 (Career and
Technical Education; Federal Laws Guaranteeing Civil Rights)
20 U. S. C. §3401(2) (Department of
Education; Congressional Findings)
20 U. S. C. §7231d(b)(2)(C) (Magnet
Schools Assistance; Applications and Requirements)
20 U. S. C. §7914 (Strengthening and
Improvement of Elementary and Secondary Schools; Civil Rights)
22 U. S. C. §262p–4n (Foreign
Relations and Intercourse; Equal Employment Opportunities)
22 U. S. C. §2304(a)(1) (Human Rights
and Security Assistance)
22 U. S. C. §2314(g) (Furnishing of
Defense Articles or Related Training or Other Defense Service on
Grant Basis)
22 U. S. C. §2426 (Discrimination
Against United States Personnel)
22 U. S. C. §2504(a) (Peace Corps
Volunteers)
22 U. S. C. §2661a (Foreign Contracts
or Arrangements; Discrimination)
22 U. S. C. §2755 (Discrimination
Prohibited if Based on Race, Religion, National Origin, or Sex)
22 U. S. C. §3901(b)(2) (Foreign
Service; Congressional Findings and Objectives)
22 U. S. C. §3905(b)(1) (Foreign
Service; Personnel Actions)
22 U. S. C. §4102(11)(A) (Foreign
Service; Definitions)
22 U. S. C. §4115(b)(4) (Foreign
Service; Unfair Labor Practices)
22 U. S. C. §6401(a)(3)
(International Religious Freedom; Findings; Policy)
22 U. S. C. §8303(c)(2) (Office of
Volunteers for Prosperity)
23 U. S. C. §140(a) (Federal-Aid
Highways; Nondiscrimination)
23 U. S. C. §324 (Highways;
Prohibition of Discrimination on the Basis of Sex)
25 U. S. C. §4223(d)(2) (Housing
Assistance for Native Hawaiians)
26 U. S. C. §7471(a)(6)(A) (Tax
Court; Employees)
28 U. S. C. §994(d) (Duties of the
United States Sentencing Commission)
28 U. S. C. §1862 (Trial by Jury;
Discrimination Prohibited)
28 U. S. C. §1867(e) (Trial by Jury;
Challenging Compliance With Selection Procedures)
29 U. S. C. §206(d)(1) (Equal Pay Act
of 1963)
29 U. S. C. §§2601(a)(6) and (b)(4)
(Family and Medical Leave; Findings and Purposes)
29 U. S. C. §2651(a) (Family and
Medical Leave; Effect on Other Laws)
29 U. S. C. §3248 (Workforce
Development Opportunities; Nondiscrimination)
30 U. S. C. §1222(c) (Research Funds
to Institutes)
31 U. S. C. §732(f ) (Government
Accountability Office; Personnel Management System)
31 U. S. C. §6711 (Federal Payments;
Prohibited Discrimination)
31 U. S. C. §6720(a)(8) (Federal
Payments; Definitions, Application, and Administration)
34 U. S. C. §10228(c) (Prohibition of
Federal Control Over State and Local Criminal Justice Agencies;
Prohibition of Discrimination)
34 U. S. C. §11133(a)(16) (Juvenile
Justice and Delinquency Prevention; State Plans)
34 U. S. C. §12161(g) (Community
Schools Youth Services and Supervision Grant Program)
34 U. S. C. §12361 (Violent Crime
Control and Law Enforcement; Civil Rights for Women)
34 U. S. C. §20110(e) (Crime Victims
Fund; Administration Provisions)
34 U. S. C. §50104(a) (Emergency
Federal Law Enforcement Assistance)
36 U. S. C. §20204(b) (Air Force
Sergeants Association; Membership)
36 U. S. C. §20205(c) (Air Force
Sergeants Association; Governing Body)
36 U. S. C. §21003(a)(4) (American GI
Forum of the United States; Purposes)
36 U. S. C. §21004(b) (American GI
Forum of the United States; Membership)
36 U. S. C. §21005(c) (American GI
Forum of the United States; Governing Body)
36 U. S. C. §21704A (The American
Legion)
36 U. S. C. §22703(c) (Amvets;
Membership)
36 U. S. C. §22704(d) (Amvets;
Governing Body)
36 U. S. C. §60104(b) (82nd Airborne
Division Association, Incorporated; Membership)
36 U. S. C. §60105(c) (82nd Airborne
Division Association, Incorporated; Governing Body)
36 U. S. C. §70104(b) (Fleet Reserve
Association; Membership)
36 U. S. C. §70105(c) (Fleet Reserve
Association; Governing Body)
36 U. S. C. §140704(b) (Military
Order of the World Wars; Membership)
36 U. S. C. §140705(c) (Military
Order of the World Wars; Governing Body)
36 U. S. C. §154704(b) (Non
Commissioned Officers Association of the United States of America,
Incorporated; Membership)
36 U. S. C. §154705(c) (Non
Commissioned Officers Association of the United States of America,
Incorporated; Governing Body)
36 U. S. C. §190304(b) (Retired
Enlisted Association, Incorporated; Membership)
36 U. S. C. §190305(c) (Retired
Enlisted Association, Incorporated; Governing Body)
36 U. S. C. §220522(a)(8) and (9)
(United States Olympic Committee; Eligibility Requirements)
36 U. S. C. §230504(b) (Vietnam
Veterans of America, Inc.; Membership)
36 U. S. C. §230505(c) (Vietnam
Veterans of America, Inc.; Governing Body)
40 U. S. C. §122(a) (Federal Property
and Administrative Services; Prohibition on Sex Discrimination)
40 U. S. C. §14702 (Appalachian
Regional Development; Nondiscrimination)
42 U. S. C. §213(f ) (Military
Benefits)
42 U. S. C. §290cc–33(a) (Projects
for Assistance in Transition From Homelessness)
42 U. S. C. §290ff–1(e)(2)(C)
(Children With Serious Emotional Disturbances; Requirements With
Respect to Carrying Out Purpose of Grants)
42 U. S. C. §295m (Public Health
Service; Prohibition Against Discrimination on Basis of Sex)
42 U. S. C. §296g (Public Health
Service; Prohibition Against Discrimination by Schools on Basis of
Sex)
42 U. S. C. §300w–7(a)(2) (Preventive
Health and Health Services Block Grants; Nondiscrimination
Provisions)
42 U. S. C. §300x–57(a)(2) (Block
Grants Regarding Mental Health and Substance Abuse;
Nondiscrimination)
42 U. S. C. §603(a)(5)(I)(iii) (Block
Grants to States for Temporary Assistance for Needy Families)
42 U. S. C. §708(a)(2) (Maternal and
Child Health Services Block Grant; Nondiscrimination
Provisions)
42 U. S. C. §1975a(a) (Duties of
Civil Rights Commission)
42 U. S. C. §2000c(b) (Civil Rights;
Public Education; Definitions)
42 U. S. C. §2000c–6(a)(2) (Civil
Rights; Public Education; Civil Actions by the Attorney
General)
42 U. S. C. §2000e–2 (Equal
Employment Opportunities; Unlawful Employment Practices)
42 U. S. C. §2000e–3(b) (Equal
Employment Opportunities; Other Unlawful Employment Practices)
42 U. S. C. §2000e–16(a) (Employment
by Federal Government)
42 U. S. C. §2000e–16a(b) (Government
Employee Rights Act of 1991)
42 U. S. C. §2000e–16b(a)(1)
(Discriminatory Practices Prohibited)
42 U. S. C. §2000h–2 (Intervention by
Attorney General; Denial of Equal Protection on Account of Race,
Color, Religion, Sex or National Origin)
42 U. S. C. §3123 (Discrimination on
Basis of Sex Prohibited in Federally Assisted Programs)
42 U. S. C. §3604 (Fair Housing Act;
Discrimination in the Sale or Rental of Housing and Other
Prohibited Practices)
42 U. S. C. §3605 (Fair Housing Act;
Discrimination in Residential Real Estate-Related Transactions)
42 U. S. C. §3606 (Fair Housing Act;
Discrimination in the Provision of Brokerage Services)
42 U. S. C. §3631 (Fair Housing Act;
Violations; Penalties)
42 U. S. C. §4701 (Intergovernmental
Personnel Program; Congressional Findings and Declaration of
Policy)
42 U. S. C. §5057(a)(1) (Domestic
Volunteer Services; Nondiscrimination Provisions)
42 U. S. C. §5151(a)
(Nondiscrimination in Disaster Assistance)
42 U. S. C. §5309(a) (Community
Development; Nondiscrimination in Programs and Activities)
42 U. S. C. §5891 (Development of
Energy Sources; Sex Discrimination Prohibited)
42 U. S. C. §6709 (Public Works
Employment; Sex Discrimination; Prohibition; Enforcement)
42 U. S. C. §6727(a)(1) (Public Works
Employment; Nondiscrimination)
42 U. S. C. §6870(a) (Weatherization
Assistance for Low-Income Persons)
42 U. S. C. §8625(a) (Low-Income Home
Energy Assistance; Nondiscrimination Provisions)
42 U. S. C. §9821 (Community Economic
Development; Nondiscrimination Provisions)
42 U. S. C. §9849 (Head Start
Programs; Nondiscrimination Provisions)
42 U. S. C. §9918(c)(1) (Community
Services Block Grant Program; Limitations on Use of Funds)
42 U. S. C. §10406(c)(2)(B)(i)
(Family Violence Prevention and Services; Formula Grants to
States)
42 U. S. C. §11504(b) (Enterprise
Zone Development; Waiver of Modification of Housing and Community
Development Rules in Enterprise Zones)
42 U. S. C. §12635(a)(1) (National
and Community Service State Grant Program; Nondiscrimination)
42 U. S. C. §12832 (Investment in
Affordable Housing; Nondiscrimination)
43 U. S. C. §1747(10) (Loans to
States and Political Subdivisions; Discrimination Prohibited)
43 U. S. C. §1863 (Outer Continental
Shelf Resource Management; Unlawful Employment Practices;
Regulations)
47 U. S. C. §151 (Federal
Communications Commission)
47 U. S. C. §398(b)(1) (Public
Broadcasting; Equal Opportunity Employment)
47 U. S. C. §§554(b) and (c) (Cable
Communications; Equal Employment Opportunity)
47 U. S. C. §555a(c) (Cable
Communications; Limitation of Franchising Authority Liability)
48 U. S. C. §1542(a) (Virgin Islands;
Voting Franchise; Discrimination Prohibited)
48 U. S. C. §1708 (Discrimination
Prohibited in Rights of Access to, and Benefits From, Conveyed
Lands)
49 U. S. C. §306(b) (Duties of the
Secretary of Transportation; Prohibited Discrimination)
49 U. S. C. §5332(b) (Public
Transportation; Nondiscrimination)
49 U. S. C. §40127 (Air Commerce and
Safety; Prohibitions on Discrimination)
49 U. S. C. §47123(a) (Airport
Improvement; Nondiscrimination)
50 U. S. C. §3809(b)(3) (Selective
Service System)
50 U. S. C. §4842(a)(1)(B)
(Anti-Boycott Act of 2018)
D