SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 18–6135
_________________
JAMES K. KAHLER, PETITIONER
v.
KANSAS
on writ of certiorari to the supreme court of
kansas
[March 23, 2020]
Justice Breyer, with whom Justice Ginsburg and
Justice Sotomayor join, dissenting.
Like the Court, I believe that the Constitution
gives the States broad leeway to define state crimes and criminal
procedures, including leeway to provide different definitions and
standards related to the defense of insanity. But here, Kansas has
not simply redefined the insanity defense. Rather, it has
eliminated the core of a defense that has existed for centuries:
that the defendant,
due to mental illness, lacked the mental
capacity necessary for his conduct to be considered morally
blameworthy. Seven hundred years of Anglo-American legal history,
together with basic principles long inherent in the nature of the
criminal law itself, convince me that Kansas’ law “ ‘offends
. . . principle[s] of justice so rooted in the traditions
and conscience of our people as to be ranked as
fundamental.’ ”
Leland v.
Oregon,
343 U.S.
790, 798 (1952) (quoting
Snyder v.
Massachusetts,
291 U.S.
97, 105 (1934)).
I
A much-simplified example will help the reader
understand the conceptual distinction that is central to this case.
Consider two similar prosecutions for murder. In Prosecution One,
the accused person has shot and killed another person. The evidence
at trial proves that, as a result of severe mental illness, he
thought the victim was a dog. Prosecution Two is similar but for
one thing: The evidence at trial proves that, as a result of severe
mental illness, the defendant thought that a dog ordered him to
kill the victim. Under the insanity defense as traditionally
understood, the government cannot convict either defendant. Under
Kansas’ rule, it can convict the second but not the first.
To put the matter in more explicitly legal
terms, consider the most famous statement of the traditional
insanity defense, that contained in
M’Naghten’s Case, 10 Cl.
& Fin. 200, 8 Eng. Rep. 718 (H. L. 1843). Lord Chief Justice
Tindal, speaking for a majority of the judges of the common-law
courts, described the insanity defense as follows:
“[T]o establish a defence on the ground of
insanity, it must be clearly proved that, at the time of the
committing of the act, the party accused was labouring under such a
defect of reason, from disease of the mind, [1] as not to know the
nature and quality of the act he was doing; or, [2] if he did know
it, that he did not know he was doing what was wrong.”
Id.,
at 210, 8 Eng. Rep., at 722.
The first prong (sometimes referred to as
“cognitive incapacity”) asks whether the defendant knew what he was
doing. This prong corresponds roughly to the modern concept of
mens rea for many offenses. The second (sometimes referred
to as “moral incapacity”) goes further. It asks, even if the
defendant knew what he was doing, did he have the capacity to know
that it was wrong? Applying this test to my example, a court would
find that both defendants successfully established an insanity
defense. Prosecution One (he thought the victim was a dog) falls
within
M’Naghten’s first prong, while Prosecution Two (he
thought the dog ordered him to do it) falls within its second
prong.
In Kansas’ early years of statehood, its courts
recognized the
M’Naghten test as the “cardinal rule of
responsibility in the criminal law.”
State v.
Nixon,
32 Kan. 205, 206, 4 P. 159, 160 (1884). Kansas “steadfastly adhered
to that test” for more than a century.
State v.
Baker, 249 Kan. 431, 449–450,
819 P.2d 1173, 1187 (1991). But in 1995, Kansas
“ ‘legislatively abolish[ed] the insanity defense.’ ”
State v.
Jorrick, 269 Kan. 72, 82, 4 P.3d 610, 617
(2000) (quoting Rosen, Insanity Denied: Abolition of the Insanity
Defense in Kansas, 8 Kan. J. L. & Pub. Pol’y 253, 254–255
(1997)). Under the new provision, a criminal defendant’s mental
disease or defect is relevant to his guilt or innocence only
insofar as it shows that he lacked the intent defined as an element
of the offense, or
mens rea. If the defendant acted with the
required level of intent, then he has no defense based on mental
illness. Kan. Stat. Ann. §21–5209 (2018 Cum. Supp.).
Under Kansas’ changed law, the defendant in
Prosecution One could defend against the charge by arguing that his
mental illness prevented him from forming the mental state required
for murder (intentional killing of a human being)—just as any
defendant may attempt to rebut the State’s prima facie case for
guilt. The defendant in Prosecution Two has no defense. Because he
acted with the requisite level of intent, he must be convicted
regardless of any role his mental illness played in his conduct.
See 307 Kan. 374, 401, 410 P.3d 105, 125 (2018) (acknowledging that
Kansas’
mens rea approach “allows conviction of an
individual who had no capacity to know that what he or she was
doing was wrong”).
I do not mean to suggest that
M’Naghten’s
particular approach to insanity is constitutionally required. As we
have said, “[h]istory shows no deference to
M’Naghten.”
Clark v.
Arizona,
548
U.S. 735, 749 (2006).
M’Naghten’s second prong is merely
one way of describing something more fundamental. Its basic insight
is that mental illness may so impair a person’s mental capacities
as to render him no more responsible for his actions than a young
child or a wild animal. Such a person is not properly the subject
of the criminal law. As I shall explain in the following section,
throughout history, the law has attempted to embody this principle
in a variety of ways. As a historical matter,
M’Naghten is
by far its most prominent expression, but not its exclusive one.
Other ways of capturing it may well emerge in the future. The
problem with Kansas’ law is that it excises this fundamental
principle from its law entirely.
II
The Due Process Clause protects those
“ ‘principle[s] of justice so rooted in the traditions and
conscience of our people as to be ranked as fundamental.’ ”
Leland, 343 U. S., at 798. Our “primary guide” in
determining whether a principle of justice ranks as fundamental is
“historical practice.”
Montana v.
Egelhoff,
518 U.S.
37, 43 (1996) (plurality opinion). The Court contends that the
historical formulations of the insanity defense were so diverse, so
contested, as to make it impossible to discern a unified principle
that Kansas’ approach offends. I disagree.
Few doctrines are as deeply rooted in our
common-law heritage as the insanity defense. Although English and
early American sources differ in their linguistic formulations of
the legal test for insanity, with striking consistency, they all
express the same underlying idea: A defendant who, due to mental
illness, lacks sufficient mental capacity to be held morally
responsible for his actions cannot be found guilty of a crime. This
principle remained embedded in the law even as social mores shifted
and medical understandings of mental illness evolved. Early
American courts incorporated it into their jurisprudence. The
States eventually codified it in their criminal laws. And to this
day, the overwhelming majority of U. S. jurisdictions
recognize insanity as an affirmative defense that excuses a
defendant from criminal liability even where he was capable of
forming the
mens rea required for the offense. See Appendix,
infra.
A
Consider the established common-law background
of the insanity defense at and around the time the Framers wrote
the Constitution. The four preeminent common-law jurists, Bracton,
Coke, Hale, and Blackstone, each linked criminality to the presence
of reason, free will, and moral understanding. It is “will and
purpose,” wrote Henry de Bracton in his 13th-century treatise, that
“mark
maleficia [misdeeds].” 2 Bracton On Laws and Customs
of England 384 (S. Thorne transl. 1968) (Bracton); Oxford Latin
Dictionary 1067 (P. Glare ed. 1982). A “madman,” he explained, “can
no more commit an
injuria [unlawful conduct] or a felony
than a brute animal, since they are not far removed from brutes.” 2
Bracton 424; Oxford Latin Dictionary, at 914. Seizing on Bracton’s
reference to “brute animals” (sometimes translated “wild beasts”),
the Court concludes that Bracton’s approach, like Kansas’, would
excuse only those who lack capacity to form any intention at all.
See
ante, at 15. But what does it mean to be like a “brute
animal”? A brute animal may well and readily intend to commit a
violent act without being able to judge its moral nature. For
example, when a lion stalks and kills its prey, though it acts
intentionally, it does not offend against the criminal laws. See 2
Bracton 379 (noting that “murder” is defined as “by the hand of
man” to “distinguish it from the case of those slain or devoured by
beasts and animals which lack reason”).
Bracton’s other references to “madmen” shed
further light on the meaning he attached to that term. Bracton
described such persons as “without sense and reason” and “lack[ing]
animus.”
Id., at 324, 424. And he likened a “lunatic”
to an “infant,” who cannot be held liable in damages unless he “is
capable of perceiving the wrongful character of his act.”
Id., at 324; see also 4
id., at 356 (“in many ways a
minor and a madman are considered equals or not very different,
because they lack reason” (footnote omitted)). Thus, Bracton’s
“brute animal” included those who lacked the qualities of reason
and judgment that make human beings responsible moral agents. See
Platt, The Origins and Development of the “Wild Beast” Concept of
Mental Illness and Its Relation to Theories of Criminal
Responsibility, 1 Issues in Crim. 1, 6 (1965).
Leaving Bracton, let us turn to Sir Edward Coke,
writing in the early 17th century. Coke wrote that “the act and
wrong of a mad man shall not be imputed to him,” not because he
could not engage in intentional conduct (the equivalent of the
modern concept of
mens rea), but because he lacked something
more—“mind or discretion.” 2 Institutes of the Laws of England
§405, p. 247b (1628). Coke, like Bracton before him, likened a
“mad man” to an “[i]nfant,” who could not be punished as a criminal
“untill he be of the age of fourteene, which in Law is accounted
the age of discretion.”
Ibid. What is it that the “[i]nfant”
lacks? Since long before Coke’s time, English jurists and scholars
believed that it was the moral nature, not the physical nature, of
an act that a young child is unlikely to understand. See Platt
& Diamond, The Origins of the “Right and Wrong” Test of
Criminal Responsibility and Its Subsequent Development in the
United States: An Historical Survey, 54 Cal. L. Rev. 1227,
1233–1234 (1966) (Platt & Diamond).
Sir Matthew Hale also premised criminal
liability on the presence of “understanding and liberty of will,”
without which “there can be no transgression, or just reason to
incur the penalty or sanction that law instituted for the
punishment of the crimes or offenses.” 1 Pleas of the Crown, ch. 2,
pp. 14–15 (1736). Hale, too, likened insane persons to
“infants” under the age of 14, who were subject to the criminal
laws only if they “had discretion to judge between good and evil.”
Id., ch. 3, at 26–27;
id., ch. 4, at 30 (a person who
is “labouring under melancholy distempers hath yet ordinarily as
great understanding, as ordinarily a child of fourteen years hath,
is such a person as may be guilty of treason or felony”). Those
suffering from “total insanity” could not be guilty of capital
offenses, “for they have not the use of understanding, and act not
as reasonable creatures, but their actions are in effect in the
condition of brutes.”
Id., at 30–32.
Sir William Blackstone, whose influence on the
founding generation was the most profound, was yet more explicit. A
criminal offense, he explained, requires both a “vitious will” and
a “vitious act.” 4 Commentaries on the Laws of England 21 (1769).
Persons suffering from a “deficiency in will” arising from a
“defective or vitiated understanding” were “not [criminally]
chargeable for their own acts.”
Id., at 24. Citing Coke, he
explained that murder must be “committed by a person of sound
memory and discretion” because a “lunatic or infant” is “incapable
of committing any crime, unless in such cases where they shew a
consciousness of doing wrong, and of course a discretion, or
discernment, between good and evil.”
Id., at 195–196. And he
opined that deprivation of “the capacity of discerning right from
wrong” is necessary “to form a legal excuse.”
Id., at
189.
These four eminent jurists were not alone.
Numerous other commentators expressly linked criminal liability
with the accused’s capacity for moral agency. William Lambard’s
1581 treatise ranked a “mad man” as akin to a “childe” who had “no
knowledge of good nor evil.” Eirenarcha, ch. 21, p. 218. If
such a person killed a man, that is “no felonious acte” because
“they can[n]ot be said to have any understanding wil[l].”
Ibid. But if “upon examination” it appeared that “they knew
what they did,
[and] it was ill, the[n] seemeth it to be
otherwise.”
Ibid. (emphasis added). Michael Dalton’s 1618
manual for justices of the peace instructed that “[i]f one that is
Non compos mentis . . . kill a man, this is no
felonie; for they have no knowledge of good and evill, nor can have
a felonious intent, nor a will or mind to do harme.” The Countrey
Justice 215. William Hawkins, in 1716, wrote that “those who,” like
“[l]unaticks,” are “under a natural Disability of distinguishing
between Good and Evil . . . are not punishable by any
criminal Prosecution whatsoever.” 1 Pleas of the Crown §1,
p. 2; see also
id., at 1 (“The Guilt of offending
against any Law whatsoever . . . can never justly be
imputed to those who are either uncapable of understanding it, or
of conforming themselves to it”).
English treatises on the law of mental
disability adopted the same view. George Collinson explained that
“[t]o excuse a man in the commission of a crime, he must at the
period when he committed the offense, have been wholly incapable of
distinguishing between good and evil, or of comprehending the
nature of what he is doing.” Treatise on the Law Concerning Idiots,
Lunatics, and Other Persons Non Compotes Mentis §7, p. 474
(1812) (Collinson); see also
id., §2, at 471 (“[A]n evil
intention is implied in every offence, and constitutes the charge
of every indictment: but a non compos, not having a will of his
own, cannot have an intention morally good or bad; so that the
overt act by which alone the motives of other men are discerned,
with respect to him proves nothing”). Similarly, Leonard Shelford,
summarizing English case law, wrote that “[t]he essence of a crime
consists in the animus or intention of the person who commits it,
considered as a free agent, and in a capacity of distinguishing
between moral good and evil.” Practical Treatise on the Law
Concerning Lunatics, Idiots, and Persons of Unsound Mind 458 (1833)
(emphasis deleted).
The majority believes that I am
“cherry-pick[ing]” references to moral understanding while ignoring
references to intent and
mens rea. See
ante, at
15–17, nn. 8, 9. With respect, I disagree. The Court points
out, correctly, that many of the common-law sources state that the
insane lack
mens rea or felonious intent. But what did they
mean by that? At common law, the term
mens rea ordinarily
incorporated the notion of “general moral blameworthiness” required
for criminal punishment. Sayre, Mens Rea, 45 Harv. L. Rev. 974, 988
(1932); 3 Encyclopedia of Crime and Justice 995 (2d ed. 2002) (as
used at common law, the term
mens rea “is synonymous with a
person’s blameworthiness”). The modern meaning of
mens rea
is narrower and more technical.
Ibid. It refers to the
“state of mind or inattention that, together with its accompanying
conduct, the criminal law defines as an offense.”
Ibid. When
common-law writers speak of intent or
mens rea, we cannot
simply assume that they use those terms in the modern sense. That
is an anachronism. Instead, we must examine the context to
understand what meaning they ascribed to those terms. And when we
do so, we see that, over and over again, they link criminal intent
to the presence of free will and moral understanding. The Court
dismisses those passages as just “some ‘good and evil’ language.”
Ante, at 17, n. 9. But it fails to explain why, if
mens rea in the modern sense were sufficient, these
common-law writers discuss the role of moral agency at all, much
less why such language appears in virtually every treatise and
virtually every case. In the Court’s view, all that is just spilled
ink.
The English case law illustrates this point. In
the seminal case of
Rex v.
Arnold, 16 How. St. Tr.
695 (1724), the defendant stood accused of shooting Lord Onslow
while laboring under the insane delusion that Onslow had bewitched
him.
Id., at 699, 721. The Court emphasizes Justice Tracy’s
statement to the jury that if a man is “ ‘deprived of his
reason, and consequently of his intention, he cannot be
guilty,’ ” concluding that the court adopted a modern
mens
rea test.
Ante, at 16. But in the passage immediately
preceding that statement, Justice Tracy explained that the
defendant’s intent to shoot was clearly proved, and that the only
remaining question was whether his mental illness excused him from
blame:
“That he shot, and that wilfully [is
proved]: but whether maliciously, that is the thing: that is the
question; whether this man hath the use of his reason and sense? If
he was under the visitation of God, and could not distinguish
between good and evil, and did not know what he did, though he
committed the greatest offence, yet he could not be guilty of any
offence against any law whatsoever; for guilt arises from the mind,
and the wicked will and intention of the man. If a man be
deprived of his reason, and consequently of his intention, he
cannot be guilty; and if that be the case, though he had
actually killed my lord Onslow, he is exempted from punishment.” 16
How. St. Tr., at 764 (emphasis added; brackets in original).
See also
ibid. (summarizing the testimony
of one Mr. Coe, who testified that he went to the defendant three
days after the shooting “and asked him, If he intended to kill my
lord Onslow? and he said, Yes, to be sure”). On the next page,
Justice Tracy concluded that the jury must determine whether the
evidence “doth shew a man, who knew what he was doing, and was able
to distinguish whether he was doing good or evil, and understood
what he did.”
Id., at 765.
Likewise, in the case of
Rex v.
Lord
Ferrers, 19 How. St. Tr. 886 (1760), the solicitor general
instructed the members of the House of Lords to consider the
“ ‘capacity and intention’ ” of the accused, to be sure,
ante, at 17, but what did he mean by those terms? The
ultimate question of insanity, he explained, depended on the
defendant’s capacity at the time of the offense to distinguish
right from wrong:
“My lords, the question therefore must be
asked; is the noble prisoner at the bar to be acquitted from the
guilt of murder, on account of insanity? It is not pretended to be
a constant general insanity. Was he under the power of it, at the
time of the offence committed? Could he, did he, at that time,
distinguish between good and evil?” 19 How. St. Tr., at 948.
In summation, the solicitor general argued that
Lord Ferrers’ own witnesses failed to provide any testimony “which
proves his lunacy or insanity at any time.”
Id., at 952.
Reviewing the pertinent evidence, he noted that one witness
testified that he “had observed great oddities in my lord,” but
acknowledged that he “never saw him in such a situation, as not to
be capable of distinguishing between good and evil, and not to
know, that murder was a great crime.”
Ibid. Another admitted
under questioning by the Lords that “he thought lord Ferrers
capable of distinguishing between moral and immoral actions.”
Ibid. The defendant’s brother was the only witness to
testify that “at particular times, the noble lord might not be able
to distinguish between moral good and evil,” but even he, the
solicitor general argued, had been unable to testify to “any
instance within his own recollection.”
Id., at 953. If Lord
Ferrers’ bare intention to kill were sufficient to convict, why the
extensive discussion of the evidence concerning his capacity for
moral understanding?
These examples reflect the prevailing view of
the law around the time of the founding. Judges regularly
instructed juries that the defendant’s criminal liability depended
on his capacity for moral responsibility. See,
e.g.,
Trial of Samuel Burt (July 19, 1786), in 6 Old Bailey
Proceedings 875 (E. Hodgson ed. 1788) (to acquit based on insanity,
it must be shown that the mental disorder “takes away from the
party all moral agency and accountability,” and “destroys in them,
for the time at least, all power of judging between right and
wrong”);
Trial of Francis Parr (Jan. 15, 1787), 2
id., at 228 (jury must “judge whether at the moment of
committing [the offense] he was not a moral agent, capable of
discerning between good and evil, and of knowing the consequences
of what he did”);
Bowler’s Case, 1 Collinson 673–674, n.
(judge “concluded by observing to the jury, that it was for them to
determine whether the Prisoner, when he committed the offence with
which he stood charged, was or was not incapable of distinguishing
right from wrong”). The government’s attorneys agreed that this was
the proper inquiry. See,
e.g.,
Parker’s Case, 1
id., at 479–480 (the Attorney General argued that “the jury
must be perfectly satisfied, that at the time when the crime was
committed, the prisoner did not really know right from wrong”).
In none of the common-law cases was the judge’s
reference to the defendant’s capacity for moral agency simply a
proxy for the narrow modern notion of
mens rea. See
ante, at 17. Something more was required. Consider
Bellingham’s Case, 1 Collinson 636. The defendant stood
accused of the murder of Spencer Perceval, the Chancellor of the
Exchequer, in the lobby of the House of Commons.
Ibid. The
Court emphasizes Chief Justice Mansfield’s statement that one who
could not distinguish right from wrong “ ‘could have no
intention at all,’ ” concluding that Chief Justice Mansfield
viewed moral incapacity as a symptom of cognitive breakdown rather
than a test of insanity.
Ante, at 18. But, as in
Rex
v.
Arnold, see
supra, at 9–10, the defendant’s
intention to shoot Perceval was not seriously in dispute. 1
Collinson 670. Instead, his guilt or innocence turned on his
capacity for moral blame. The “single question” for the jury,
charged the Chief Justice, “was whether, when [the defendant]
committed the offence charged upon him, he had sufficient
understanding to distinguish good from evil, right from wrong, and
that murder was a crime not only against the law of God, but
against the law of his Country.”
Id., at 673. Lord
Lyndhurst, presiding over the case of
Rex v.
Offord,
5 Car. & P. 168, 172 Eng. Rep. 924 (N. P. 1831), certainly
understood that inquiry to be the crux of Chief Justice Mansfield’s
charge. Citing
Bellingham’s Case, he instructed the jury
that “[t]he question was, did [the accused] know that he was
committing an offence against the laws of God and nature?” 5 Car.
& P., at 168, 172 Eng. Rep., at 925.
The Court dismisses other common-law cases as
failing to articulate a clear legal standard. See
ante, at
18–19. But these cases, too, required more than bare intent. In
Hadfield’s Case, 27 How. St. Tr. 1281 (1800), the defendant
was acquitted after the prosecution conceded that he was “in a
deranged state of mind” when he shot at King George III.
Id., at 1353. And in
Regina v.
Oxford, 9 Car.
& P. 525, 173 Eng. Rep. 941 (N. P. 1840), the court observed
that a “person may commit a criminal act, and yet not be
responsible.”
Id., at 546, 173 Eng. Rep., at 950. Although
it acknowledged the difficulty of “lay[ing] down the rule of the
English law on the subject,” it summed up the inquiry as “whether
the prisoner was labouring under that species of insanity which
satisfies you that he was quite unaware of the nature, character,
and consequences of the act he was committing, or, in other words,
whether he was under the influence of a diseased mind, and was
really unconscious at the time he was committing the act, that it
was a crime.”
Id., at 546–547, 173 Eng. Rep., at 950.
Although these and other English cases discuss insanity in terms
that are less precise than our modern taxonomy of mental states,
their lesson is clear. To be guilty of a crime, the accused must
have something more than bare ability to form intentions and carry
them out.
B
These fundamental principles of criminal
responsibility were incorporated into American law from the early
days of the Republic. Early American commentaries on the criminal
law generally consisted of abridgments of the works of prominent
English jurists. As early as 1792, one such abridgment instructed
that “lunaticks, who are under a natural disability of
distinguishing between good and evil are not punishable by any
criminal prosecution.” R. Burn, Abridgment, or the American Justice
300; see also W. Stubbs, Crown Circuit Companion 288 (1 Am. ed.
1816) (“If one that is
non compos mentis . . .
kill a man, this is no felony; for they have not knowledge of good
and evil, nor can have a felonious intent, nor a will or mind to do
harm”). And an influential founding-era legal dictionary described
the “general rule” that lunatics, “being by reason of their natural
disabilities incapable of judging between good and evil, are
punishable by no criminal prosecution whatsoever.” 2 T. Cunningham,
New and Complete Law Dictionary (2d corr. ed. 1771). Similarly, the
first comprehensive American text on forensic medicine, published
in 1823, cited Chief Justice Mansfield’s charge to the jury in
Bellingham’s Case for the proposition that “[s]o long as
they could distinguish good from evil, so long would they be
answerable for their conduct.” 1 T. Beck, Elements of Medical
Jurisprudence 369. These principles, it concluded, “are doubtless
correct, and conducive to the ends of justice.”
Id., at
370.
Early American jurists closely hewed to these
principles. In case after case, judges instructed juries that they
must inquire into the defendant’s capacity for moral understanding.
See,
e.g.,
Meriam’s Case, 7 Mass. 168 (1810), 6
N. Y. City-Hall Recorder 162 (1822) (whether the defendant was
“at the time, capable of distinguishing good from evil”);
Clark’s Case, 1 N. Y. City-Hall Recorder 176, 177
(1816) (same);
Ball’s Case, 2 N. Y. City-Hall Recorder
85, 86 (1817) (same);
United States v.
Clarke, 25 F.
Cas. 454 (No. 14,811) (CC DC 1818) (whether defendant was “in such
a state of mental insanity . . . as not to have been
conscious of the moral turpitude of the act”);
Cornwell v.
State, 8 Tenn. 147, 155 (1827) (whether the prisoner “had
not sufficient understanding to know right from wrong”).
C
As the foregoing demonstrates, by the time the
House of Lords articulated the
M’Naghten test in 1843, its
“essential concept and phraseology” were “already ancient and
thoroughly embedded in the law.” Platt & Diamond 1258; see also
1 W. Russell, Crimes and Misdemeanors 8–14 (3d ed. 1843)
(summarizing the pre-
M’Naghten English case law and
concluding that the key questions were whether “there be thought
and design, a faculty to distinguish the nature of actions, [and]
to discern the difference between moral good and evil”). Variations
on the
M’Naghten rules soon became the predominant standard
in the existing states of the United States. Platt & Diamond
1257. That tradition has continued, almost without exception, to
the present day.
It is true that, even following
M’Naghten, States continued to experiment with different
formulations of the insanity defense. See
ante, at 19–20.
Some adopted the volitional incapacity, or “irresistible-impulse,”
test. But those States understood that innovation to expand, not
contract, the scope of the insanity defense, excusing not only
defendants who met some variant of the traditional
M’Naghten
test but also those who understood that their conduct was wrong but
were incapable of restraint. See,
e.g.,
Parsons v.
State, 81 Ala. 577, 584–585, 2 So. 854, 858–859 (1887);
Bradley v.
State, 31 Ind. 492, 507–508 (1869);
State v.
Felter, 25 Iowa 67, 82–83 (1868);
Hopps v.
People, 31 Ill. 385, 391–392 (1863).
So too, the “offspring” or “product” test, which
asks whether the defendant’s conduct was attributable to mental
disease or defect. The States that adopted this test did so out of
the conviction that the
M’Naghten test was too restrictive
in its approach to assessing the accused’s capacity for criminal
responsibility. See
Durham v.
United States, 214 F.2d
862, 874 (CADC 1954) (“We conclude that a broader test should be
adopted”);
State v.
Pike, 49 N. H. 399, 441–442
(1870); see also Reid, Understanding the New Hampshire Doctrine of
Criminal Insanity, 69 Yale L. J. 367, 386 (1960) (“[T]he New
Hampshire doctrine . . . is more liberal and has a wider
range than
M’Naghten rules”). Even as States experimented
with broader insanity rules, they retained the core of the
traditional common-law defense.
In the early 20th century, several States
attempted to break with that tradition. The high courts of those
States quickly struck down their restrictive laws. As one justice
of the Mississippi Supreme Court wrote in 1931: The “common law
proceeds upon an idea that before there can be a crime there must
be an intelligence capable of comprehending the act prohibited, and
the probable consequence of the act, and that the act is wrong.”
Sinclair v.
State, 161 Miss. 142, 158, 132 So. 581,
583 (Ethridge, J., concurring). Accordingly, Justice Ethridge said,
insanity “has always been a complete defense to all crimes from the
earliest ages of the common law.”
Ibid.;
State v.
Strasburg, 60 Wash. 106, 116, 110 P. 1020, 1022–1023 (1910);
cf.
State v.
Lange, 168 La. 958, 965, 123 So. 639,
642 (1929).
Today, 45 States, the Federal Government, and
the District of Columbia continue to recognize an insanity defense
that retains some inquiry into the blameworthiness of the accused.
Seventeen States and the Federal Government use variants of the
M’Naghten test, with its alternative cognitive and moral
incapacity prongs. Three States have adopted
M’Naghten plus
the volitional test. Ten States recognize a defense based on moral
incapacity alone. Thirteen States and the District of Columbia have
adopted variants of the Model Penal Code test, which combines
volitional incapacity with an expanded version of moral incapacity.
See Appendix,
infra. New Hampshire alone continues to use
the “product” test, asking whether “a mental disease or defect
caused the charged conduct.”
State v.
Fichera, 153
N. H. 588, 593, 903 A.2d 1030, 1035 (2006). This broad test
encompasses “ ‘whether the defendant knew the difference
between right and wrong and whether the defendant acted
impulsively,’ ” as well as “ ‘whether the defendant was
suffering from delusions or hallucinations.’ ”
State v.
Cegelis, 138 N. H. 249, 255, 638 A.2d 783, 786 (1994).
And North Dakota uses a unique formulation that asks whether the
defendant “lacks substantial capacity to comprehend the harmful
nature or consequences of the conduct, or the conduct is the result
of a loss or serious distortion of the individual’s capacity to
recognize reality.” N. D. Cent. Code Ann. §12.1–04.1–01(1)
(2012).
Of the States that have adopted the
M’Naghten or Model Penal Code tests, some interpret
knowledge of wrongfulness to refer to moral wrong, whereas others
hold that it means legal wrong. See
ante, at 2–3,
20–22
. While there is, of course, a logical distinction
between those interpretations, there is no indication that it makes
a meaningful difference in practice. The two inquiries are closely
related and excuse roughly the same universe of defendants. See
State v.
Worlock, 117 N. J. 596, 609–611,
569 A.2d 1314, 1321–1322 (1990) (“In most instances, legal
wrong is coextensive with moral wrong”);
State v.
Crenshaw,
98 Wash. 2d 789, 799,
659 P.2d 488, 494 (1983) (“ ‘[S]ince by far the vast majority
of cases in which insanity is pleaded as a defense to criminal
prosecutions involves acts which are universally recognized as
morally wicked as well as illegal, the hair-splitting distinction
between legal and moral wrong need not be given much attention’ ”);
People v.
Schmidt, 216 N.Y. 324, 340, 110 N.E. 945,
949 (1915) (Cardozo, J.) (“Knowledge that an act is forbidden by
law will in most cases permit the inference of knowledge that,
according to the accepted standards of mankind, it is also
condemned as an offense against good morals”); see also ALI, Model
Penal Code §4.01, Explanatory Note, p. 164 (1985) (explaining that
“few cases are likely to arise in which the variation will be
determinative”).
III
A
Consider the basic reason that underlies and
explains this long legal tradition. That reason reveals that more
is at stake than its duration alone. The tradition reflects the
fact that a community’s moral code informs its criminal law. As
Henry Hart stated it, the very definition of crime is conduct that
merits “a formal and solemn pronouncement of the moral condemnation
of the community.” The Aims of the Criminal Law, 23 Law &
Contemp. Prob. 401, 405 (1958).
The criminal law does not adopt, nor does it
perfectly track, moral law. It is no defense simply to claim that
one’s criminal conduct was morally right. But the criminal law
nonetheless tries in various ways to prevent the distance between
criminal law and morality from becoming too great. In the words of
Justice Holmes, a law that “punished conduct [that] would not be
blameworthy in the average member of the community would be too
severe for that community to bear.” O. Holmes, The Common Law 50
(1881); see also
ibid. (“[T]o deny that criminal liability
. . . is founded on blameworthiness . . . would
shock the moral sense of any civilized community”).
Sometimes the criminal law seeks to keep its
strictures roughly in line with the demands of morality through
grants of discretion that will help it to reach appropriate results
in individual cases, including special instances where the law
points one way and morality the other. Thus, prosecutors need not
prosecute. Jurors (however instructed) may decide to acquit. Judges
may exercise the discretion the law allows them to impose a lenient
sentence. Executives may grant clemency.
And sometimes the law attempts to maintain this
balance by developing and retaining a “collection of interlocking
and overlapping concepts,” including defenses, that will help
“assess the moral accountability of an individual for his
antisocial deeds.”
Powell v.
Texas,
392 U.S.
514, 535–536 (1968) (plurality opinion). These concepts and
defenses include “
actus reus,
mens rea, insanity,
mistake, justification, and duress.”
Id., at 536.
As we have recognized, the “process of
adjustment” within and among these overlapping legal concepts “has
always been thought to be the province of the States.”
Ibid.
Matters of degree, specific content, and aptness of application all
may be, and have always been, the subject of legal dispute. But the
general purpose—to ensure a rough congruence between the criminal
law and widely accepted moral sentiments—persists. To gravely
undermine the insanity defense is to pose a significant obstacle to
this basic objective.
The majority responds that Kansas has not
removed the element of blameworthiness from its treatment of
insanity; it has simply made a different judgment about what
conduct is blameworthy. See
ante, at 13,
n. 7
. That is not how the Kansas Supreme Court has
characterized its law. See
State v.
Bethel, 275 Kan.
456, 472, 66 P.3d 840, 850 (2003) (holding that Kansas law provides
for “no consideration,” at the guilt phase, “of whether
wrongfulness was inherent in the defendant’s intent”). In any
event, as the Court acknowledges, the States’ discretion in this
area must be constrained within “broad limits,”
ante, at 7,
which are derived from history and tradition. The question is
whether Kansas’ approach transgresses those limits. I doubt that
the Court would declare, for example, that a State may do away with
the defenses of duress or self-defense on the ground that, in its
idiosyncratic judgment, they are not required. With respect to the
defense of insanity, I believe that our history shows clearly that
the criminal law has always required a higher degree of individual
culpability than the modern concept of
mens rea. See Part
II,
supra. And in my view, Kansas’ departure from this long
uniform tradition poses a serious problem.
B
To see why Kansas’ departure is so serious, go
back to our two simplified prosecutions: the first of the defendant
who, because of serious mental illness, believes the victim is a
dog; the second of a defendant who, because of serious mental
illness, believes the dog commanded him to kill the victim. Now
ask, what moral difference exists between the defendants in the two
examples? Assuming equivalently convincing evidence of mental
illness, I can find none at all. In both cases, the defendants
differ from ordinary persons in ways that would lead most of us to
say that they should not be held morally responsible for their
acts. I cannot find one defendant more responsible than the other.
And for centuries, neither has the law.
More than that, scholars who have studied this
subject tell us that examples of the first kind are rare. See Brief
for 290 Criminal Law and Mental Health Law Professors as
Amici
Curiae 12. Others repeat this claim. See Slobogin, An End to
Insanity: Recasting the Role of Mental Disability in Criminal
Cases, 86 Va. L. Rev. 1199, 1205 (2000); Morse, Mental Disorder and
Criminal Law, 101 J. Crim. L. & C. 885, 933 (2011). That is
because mental illness typically does not deprive individuals of
the ability to form intent. Rather, it affects their
motivations for forming such intent. Brief for 290 Criminal
Law and Mental Health Law Professors as
Amici Curiae 12. For
example, the American Psychiatric Association tells us that
individuals suffering from mental illness may experience
delusions—erroneous perceptions of the outside world held with
strong conviction. They may believe, incorrectly, that others are
threatening them harm (persecutory delusions), that God has
commanded them to engage in certain conduct (religious delusions),
or that they or others are condemned to a life of suffering
(depressive delusions). Brief for American Psychiatric Association
et al. as
Amici Curiae 25–26. Such delusions may, in
some cases, lead the patient to behave violently.
Id., at
28. But they likely would not interfere with his or her perception
in such a way as to negate
mens rea. See H. R. Rep. No.
98–577, p. 15 n. 23 (1984) (“Mental illness rarely, if ever,
renders a person incapable of understanding what he or she is
doing. Mental illness does not, for example, alter the perception
of shooting a person to that of shooting a tree.”).
Kansas’ abolition of the second part of the
M’Naghten test requires conviction of a broad swath of
defendants who are obviously insane and would be adjudged not
guilty under any traditional form of the defense. This result
offends deeply entrenched and widely recognized moral principles
underpinning our criminal laws. See,
e.g., National Comm’n
on Reform of Fed. Crim. Laws, Final Report, Proposed New Fed. Crim.
Code §503, pp. 40–41 (1971) (to attribute guilt to a
“manifestly psychotic person” would “be immoral and inconsistent
with the aim of a criminal code”); H. R. Rep. No. 98–577,
at 7–8 (“[T]he abolition of the affirmative insanity defense
would alter that fundamental basis of Anglo-American criminal law:
the existence of moral culpability as a prerequisite for
punishment”); ABA Criminal Justice Mental Health Standards §7–6.1,
pp. 336–338 (1989) (rejecting the
mens rea approach
“out of hand” as “a jarring reversal of hundreds of years of moral
and legal history” that “inhibits if not prevents the exercise of
humane judgment that has distinguished our criminal law
heritage”).
By contrast, the rule adopted by some States
that a defendant must be acquitted if he was unable to appreciate
the
legal wrongfulness of his acts, see
ante,
at 20–22, would likely lead to acquittal in the mine run of
such cases. See
supra, at 17. If that is so, then that rule
would not pose the same due process problem as Kansas’ approach.
That issue is not before us, as Kansas’ law does not provide even
that protection to mentally ill defendants.
C
Kansas and the Solicitor General, in their
efforts to justify Kansas’ change, make four important arguments.
First, they point to cases in this Court in which we have said that
the States have broad leeway in shaping the insanity defense. See
Leland,
343 U.S.
790;
Clark,
548 U.S.
735. In
Leland, we rejected the defendant’s argument
that the Constitution required the adoption of the
“ ‘irresistible impulse’ ” test. 343 U. S., at
800–801. Similarly, in
Clark, we upheld Arizona’s effort to
eliminate the first part of the
M’Naghten rule, applicable
to defendants whose mental illness deprived them of the ability to
know the “ ‘nature and quality of the act,’ ” 548
U. S., at 747–748. If Arizona can eliminate the first prong of
M’Naghten, Kansas asks, why can Kansas not eliminate the
second part?
The answer to this question lies in the fact
that Arizona, while amending the insanity provisions of its
criminal code, did not in practice eliminate the traditional
insanity defense in any significant part. See 548 U. S., at
752, n. 20 (reserving the question whether “the Constitution
mandates an insanity defense”). As we pointed out, “cognitive
incapacity is itself enough to demonstrate moral incapacity.”
Id., at 753. Evidence that the defendant did not know what
he was doing would also tend to establish that he did not know that
it was wrong.
Id., at 753–754. And Prosecution One (he
thought the victim was a dog) would still fail. The ability of the
States to refuse to adopt other insanity tests, such as the
“irresistible impulse” test or the “product of mental illness” test
are also beside the point. See
Leland, 343 U. S., at
800–801. Those tests both
expand upon
M’Naghten’s
principles. Their elimination would cut the defense back to what it
traditionally has been, not, as here, eliminate its very
essence.
Second, the United States as
amicus
curiae suggests that the insanity defense is simply too
difficult for juries to administer. Brief for United States as
Amicus Curiae 12–13. Without doubt, assessing the
defendant’s claim of insanity is difficult. That is one reason I
believe that States must remain free to refine and redefine their
insanity rules within broad bounds. But juries have been making
that determination for centuries and continue to do so in 45
States. And I do not see how an administrative difficulty can
justify abolishing the heart of the defense.
Third, Kansas argues that it has not abolished
the insanity defense or any significant part of it. It has simply
moved the stage at which a defendant can present the full range of
mental-capacity evidence to sentencing. See Brief for Respondent 8;
ante, at 4–5. But our tradition demands that an insane
defendant should not be found guilty in the first place. Moreover,
the relief that Kansas offers, in the form of sentencing discretion
and the possibility of commitment in lieu of incarceration, is a
matter of judicial discretion, not of right. See
State v.
Maestas, 298 Kan. 765, 316 P.3d 724 (2014). The insane
defendant is, under Kansas law, exposed to harsh criminal sanctions
up to and including death. And Kansas’ sentencing provisions do
nothing to alleviate the stigma and the collateral consequences of
a criminal conviction.
Finally, Kansas argues that the insane, provided
they are capable of intentional action, are culpable and should be
held liable for their antisocial conduct. Brief for Respondent 40.
To say this, however, is simply to restate the conclusion for which
Kansas argues in this case. It is a conclusion that in my view runs
contrary to a legal tradition that embodies a fundamental precept
of our criminal law and that stretches back, at least, to the
origins of our Nation.
For these reasons, with respect, I dissent.
APPENDIX
M’Naghten
M’Naghten plus volitional incapacity
Moral incapacity
Model Penal Code
Unique formulation