SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 15–6418
_________________
GREGORY WELCH, PETITIONER
v. UNITED
STATES
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the eleventh circuit
[April 18, 2016]
Justice Thomas, dissenting.
Last Term the Court held in
Johnson v.
United States, 576 U. S. ___ (2015), that because the
residual clause of the Armed Career Criminal Act of 1984 (ACCA), 18
U. S. C. §924(e)(2)(B)(ii), “combin[es] indeterminacy
about how to measure the risk posed by a crime with indeterminacy
about how much risk it takes for the crime to qualify as a violent
felony,” it is unconstitutionally vague. 576 U. S., at ___
(slip op., at 6). Federal prisoners then sought to invoke
Johnson as a basis for vacating their sentences in federal
collateral review proceedings. See 28 U. S. C.
§2255(a).
Today the Court holds that
Johnson
applies retroactively to already final sentences of federal
prisoners. Thatholding comes at a steep price. The majority ignores
an insuperable procedural obstacle: when, as here, a court fails to
rule on a claim not presented in a prisoner’s §2255 motion, there
is no error for us to reverse. The majority also misconstrues the
retroactivity framework developed in
Teague v.
Lane,
489 U. S. 288 (1989) , and its progeny, thereby undermining
any principled limitation on the finality of federal convictions. I
respectfully dissent.
I
As the majority observes with considerable
understatement, “[t]his case comes to the Court in a somewhat
un-usual procedural posture.”
Ante, at 6. This case arises
from petitioner Gregory Welch’s challenge to the Eleventh Circuit’s
denial of a certificate of appealability. §2253(c)(1). In other
words, Welch asks the Court to review the Eleventh Circuit’s
refusal to allow him to appeal the claims he raised in a motion to
vacate his sentence and lost in the District Court. But Welch never
claimed that the residual clause was unconstitutionally vague in
his §2255 motion, let alone that
Johnson applies
retroactively. Accordingly, courts below addressed neither issue.
Indeed,
Johnson was not even decided when the courts below
issued their rulings. Those deficiencies should preclude us from
deciding in this case whether
Johnson is retroactive.
Our role in reviewing the denial of a
certificate of appealability is far more circumscribed than normal
appellate review. The text of 28 U. S. C. §2253 confirms
this. Defendants can appeal their convictions and sentences as a
matter of right on direct review, but §2253 deprives courts of
appeals of jurisdiction to review the denial of a petitioner’s
motion for federal postconviction relief unless he obtains a
“certificate of appealability.” §2253(c)(1). And he can obtain that
certificate only if he makes “a substantial showing of the denial
of a constitutional right.” §2253(c)(2); see
Miller-El v.
Cockrell, 537 U. S. 322 –336 (2003).
Accordingly, this Court has instructed that
review of the denial of a certificate of appealability is a
retrospective inquiry into whether the movant’s claims, as
litigated in the district court, warrant further proceedings—not
whether there is any conceivable basis upon which the movant could
prevail. Courts must ask whether “reason-able jurists would find
the district court’s assessment ofthe constitutional claims
debatable or wrong.”
Slack v.
McDaniel, 529
U. S. 473, 484 (2000) (emphasis added). They are to “look to
the
District Court’s application of [the Antiterrorism and
Effective Death Penalty Act of 1996 (AEDPA)] to petitioner’s
constitutional claims and ask whether
that resolution was
debatable.”
Miller-El, supra, at 336 (emphasis added).
Until today, we did not require courts of
appeals to consider all possible constitutional issues that might
warrant relief as part of this inquiry. Those courts instead looked
to how the movant framed his case in his motion to vacate. Even if,
for example, a district court denies ha-beas relief based on
procedural default and never reached the merits, the movant must
establish not only that the procedural ruling is “debatable” but
also that his motion “state[d] a valid claim of the denial
of a constitutional right.”
Slack, supra, at 484.
Requiring a court of appeals to consider
arguments not raised in a §2255 motion is also at odds with how the
Court has described the certificate-of-appealability inquiry. The
Court has called the decision whether to grant a certificate of
appealability a “threshold” inquiry that “forbids” reviewing courts
to engage in “full consideration of the factual or legal bases
adduced in support of the claims.”
Miller-El,
supra,
at 336. That is because, in the Court’s view, the point of “[t]he
[certificate of appealability] process [is to] scree[n] out issues
unworthy of judicial time and attention and ensur[e] that frivolous
claims are not assigned to merits panels.”
Gonzalez v.
Thaler, 565 U. S. 134, 145 (2012) . There would be no
surer way to transform this determination into a full-blown merits
appeal than to require courts of appeals to consider all
conceivable bases for relief that the movant failed to raise.
Welch’s failure to raise any
Johnson-related claim in the District Court should,
therefore, bar the Eleventh Circuit and this Court from addressing
whether
Johnson applies retroactively. Welch’s §2255 motion
omitted any claim
that his sentence was invalid because the ACCA’s
residual clause is unconstitutionally vague.[
1]* Unsurprisingly, the District Court did not
address a vagueness claim that Welch had not raised. Nor did (or
could) the District Court assess whether
Johnson applies
retroactively, for we decided
Johnson after the District
Court ruling. In sum, when Welch raised the vagueness of the
residual clause for the first time in his Eleventh Circuit
application for a certificate of appealability, it was too
late.
The Government responds to this issue by
attempting, in its reply brief in this Court, to “expressly waiv[e]
any procedural default defense against petitioner on his
Johnson claim.” Reply Brief for United States 22. But this
case has not been framed as one involving a “procedural default,”
which ordinarily refers to the affirmative defense that a
petitioner defaulted his claim in some earlier proceeding. See
McCleskey v.
Zant, 499 U. S. 467, 490 (1991)
(describing, in the context of a federal habeas petition brought by
a state prisoner, “procedural default” as the “presumption against
[federal] habeas adjudication . . . of claims defaulted
in state court”); see also,
e.g., Jenkins v.
Anderson, 447 U. S. 231, 234, n. 1 (1980) (noting that
procedural default is an affirmative defense that must be raised);
28 U. S. C. §2254 Rule 5 (requiring the Government to
“state whether any claim in the petition is barred by a
. . . procedural bar” in the answer to the motion).
Welch instead failed to raise that claim in
this proceeding by failing to present it in his motion to
vacate his sentence. And the Court of Appeals, when deciding
whether to grant a certificate of appealability,
cannot be expected to look beyond the claims presented in that
motion in conducting its threshold inquiry about whether
“reasonable jurists would find
the district court’s
assessment of the constitutional claims debatable or wrong.”
Slack, 529 U. S., at 484 (emphasis added). Although the
Government purports to waive any forfeiture defense now, it cannot
alter what was before the Court of Appeals. After Welch failed to
raise a
Johnson claim in his §2255 motion and the Eleventh
Circuit denied a certificate of appealability, the Government could
not inject the claim into the case.
Rather than grappling with these issues, the
majority distorts the standard for reviewing certificates of
appeal-ability by asking whether reasonable jurists would debate
the “conclusion” that Welch “failed to show any entitlement to
relief.”
Ante, at 7. The majority thereby transforms what
should be a quick “overview of the
claims in the habeas
petition,”
Miller-El, 537 U. S.
, at 336
(emphasis added), to a searching review of the “
conclusion”
that a prisoner is not entitled “
any” collateral relief.
Ante, at 7 (emphasis added). That is preposterous. The
Eleventh Circuit, according to the majority, erred by denying Welch
the opportunity to “appeal” a claim that he failed to raise, in
part because a decision that did not yet exist when the Eleventh
Circuit ruled may entitle him to relief. The majority’s view of
AEDPA demands judicial clairvoyance; Courts of Appeals can avoid
reversal only by inventing arguments on the movant’s behalf.
II
After bypassing what should have been an
insurmountable procedural hurdle, the majority then gets the merits
wrong. The retroactivity rules the Court adopted in
Teague
v.
Lane, 489 U. S. 288 , generally foreclose prisoners
from collaterally challenging their convictions based on new
decisions that postdate their convictions and sentences. The only
exceptions to that bar are for decisions that announce a new
substantive rule or a new “watershed” procedural rule. See
ante, at 7–8. All agree that
Johnson announced a new
rule and that it is not a “watershed” procedural rule. See
ante, at 8. But the rule in
Johnson also does not
satisfy our criteria for substantive rules. The majority concludes
otherwise,
ante, at 8–9, but its approach fails under
Teague’s own terms and erodes any meaningful limits on what
a “substantive” rule is.
A
The Court has identified two types of
substantive rules, and
Johnson’s rule of decision fits
neither description. It is not a new substantive constitutional
rule, nor does it narrow the scope of a criminal statute through
statutory construction.
1
Time and again, the Court has articulated the
test for defining a substantive constitutional rule as follows: The
rule must “place particular conduct or persons covered by the
statute beyond the State’s power to punish.”
Schriro v.
Summerlin, 542 U. S. 348, 352 (2004) ; see also
Beard v.
Banks, 542 U. S. 406, 416 (2004)
(similar);
Penry v.
Lynaugh, 492 U. S. 302, 330
(1989) (rule is substantive if “the Constitution itself deprives
the State of the power to impose a certain penalty”). This is also
the test the Court has purported to apply in case after case. See,
e.g., Sawyer v.
Smith, 497 U. S. 227, 233, 241
(1990) (prohibiting prosecutors from misleading the jury to believe
that it was not responsible for a death sentence was a
nonsubstantive rule that did not “place an entire category of
primary conduct beyond the reach of the criminal law” or “prohibit
imposition of a certain type of punishment for a class of
defendants because of their status or offense”). Our precedents
thus make clear the distinction between substantive and
nonsubstantive constitutional rules. A rule that “
because [a
State] has made a certain fact essential to the death penalty, that
fact must be found by a jury,” is not substantive; it had no effect
on the “range of conduct a State may criminalize.”
Schriro,
542 U. S., at 353–354. But a rule in which this Court “ma[de]
a certain fact essential to the death penalty . . . would
be substantive”; it would change the range of conduct warranting a
death sentence.
Id., at 354.
Under these principles,
Johnson announced
a new constitutional rule, but it is not substantive.
Johnson’s new constitutional rule is that a law is
unconstitutionally vague if it “requires a court to picture the
kind of conduct that the crime involves in ‘the ordinary case,’ and
to judge whether that abstraction presents a serious potential
risk” of some result. 576 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 4). Such
laws are vague because they simultaneously create “indeterminacy
about how to measure the risk posed by a crime with indeterminacy
about how much risk it takes for the crime to qualify” as the
described offense.
Id., at ___ (slip op., at 6). Together,
those two indeterminacies “produc[e] more unpredictability and
arbitrariness than the Due Process Clause tolerates.”
Ibid.
But that rule is not substantive under our
precedents. It does not preclude the Government from prohibiting
particular conduct or deem any conduct constitutionally protected.
The Government remains as free to enhance sentences for federal
crimes based on the commission of previous violent felonies after
Johnson as it was before. Cf.
Butler v.
McKellar, 494 U. S. 407, 415 (1990) (deciding that a
new rule was not substantive because “[t]he proscribed conduct” was
“capital murder, the prosecution of which is, to put it mildly, not
prohibited by the rule”). Nor does
Johnson’s vagueness rule
place any class of persons or punishment off limits. There is no
category of offender that Congress cannot subject to an enhanced
sentence after
Johnson. See
James v.
United
States, 550 U. S. 192, 230 (2007) (Scalia, J., dissenting)
(Congress “very easily” could “subjec[t] all repeat offenders to a
15-year manda-tory minimum prison term” in differently worded
statute (emphasis deleted)). The only constraint
Johnson
imposes is on the
manner in which the Government can punish
offenders. To avoid “fail[ing] to give ordinary people fair notice”
or “invit[ing] arbitrary enforcement,” 576 U. S., at ___ (slip
op., at 3), Congress must be clearer in describ-ing what conduct
“otherwise . . . presents a serious potential risk of
physical injury to another.” 18 U. S. C.
§924(e)(2)(B)(ii).
2
Johnson also does not fit within the
second type of substantive rule this Court has recognized, which
consists of “decisions that narrow the scope of a criminal
statuteby interpreting its terms.”
Schriro, 542 U. S.,
at 351;see
id., at 351–352 (contrasting these rules with
“constitutional determinations” that rule out punishing conduct or
persons).
The Court has invoked this subset of new rules
just once, in
Bousley v.
United States, 523
U. S. 614 (1998) .
Bousley held that
Bailey v.
United States, 516 U. S. 137 (1995) , which interpreted
a federal firearms sentencing enhancement to require proof of
“ ‘active employment of the firearm’ ” as an element,
applied retroactively. 523 U. S., at 616–617. The Court
explained that
Teague’s bar on retroactively applying
“procedural rules” is “inapplic-able to the situation in which this
Court decides the meaning of a criminal statute enacted by
Congress.” 523 U. S., at 620. Moreover, the Court reasoned,
“decisions of this Court holding that a substantive federal
criminal statute does not reach certain conduct” share a key
commonality with “decisions placing conduct beyond the power of the
criminal law-making authority to proscribe”: both “necessarily
carry a significant risk that a defendant stands convicted of an
act that the law does not make criminal.”
Ibid. (internal
quotation marks omitted). The Court thus classified decisions
“holding that a substantive federal criminal statute does not reach
certain conduct” as substantive.
Ibid.
I would not so readily assume that
Bousley applies here. Until today,
Bousley applied
only to new rules reinterpreting the text of federal criminal
statutes in a way that narrows their reach.
Johnson
announced no such rule. It announced only that there is no way in
which to narrow the reach of the residual clause without running
afoulof the Due Process Clause. 576 U. S., at ___–___ (slip
op., at 10–12).
The majority protests that applying different
retroactivity principles to constitutional and statutory rules
pro-duces “unusual outcomes” because a decision interpreting a
statute’s text to narrow its scope may be retroactive, while a
decision declaring the provision unconstitutional might not be.
Ante, at 14. But such outcomes are an inevitable byproduct
of the Court’s retroactivity jurisprudence, not a unique
consequence of this case. Take a statute allowing the Federal
Government to prosecute defendants for “serious crimes involving
interstate commerce” of which they were acquitted in state court.
See
Bartkus v.
Illinois, 359 U. S. 121 (1959)
(no double jeopardy bar to such prosecutions). Suppose the Court,
concerned that there might be a double jeopardy problem after all,
narrowed the meaning of “serious crimes involving interstate
commerce” to encompass only felonies that would be subject to a
statutory maximum sentence of life imprisonment. Anyone acquitted
of a minor felony by the State but convicted by the Federal
Government before this Court’s narrowing construction could, in the
majority’s view, seek relief on collateral review under
Bousley. See
ante, at 14. But if the Court ruled that
the Double Jeopardy Clause bars
all federal reprosecutions,
I doubt that rule would be retroactive. That rule dictates
when a defendant may be tried and convicted of certain
conduct—not the substance of the crime for which the defendant is
tried, or the punishment imposed.
The Court’s historical justifications for
retroactivity underscore the reasons for treating statutory and
constitutional rules differently. The Court in the 1950’s
“extend[ed] the scope of habeas to all alleged constitutional
errors” to “forc[e] trial and appellate courts in both the federal
and state system to toe the constitutional mark” in the face of
perceived systemic violations.
Mackey v.
United
States, 401 U. S. 667, 687 (1971) (Harlan, J.,
concurringin judgments in part and dissenting in part). That
development led to the
Teague framework allowing
retroactivity for certain types of constitutional rules. See
Montgomery v.
Louisiana, 577 U. S. ___, ___–___
(2016) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (slip op., at 2–3) (recounting
history). But this Court has never suggested that lower courts had
similar difficulties in interpreting the reach of criminal
statutes, such that the retroactivity rules should be the same.
Rather, the history suggests that the failure to apply a narrowing
construction of a criminal statute is a qualitatively different
type of error.
B
The majority instead determines whether a rule
is substantive by looking to the “function of the rule,”
ante, at 10, and asking “whether the new rule itself has a
procedural function or a substantive function,”
ante, at 11.
This apparently means that courts should divine the
effect
of a new rule and decide whether that effect alters the substantive
elements of a crime or sentence. All that matters, the majority
says, is that the vagueness rule announced in
Johnson had
the
effect of invalidating the residual clause and, as a
result of its invalidation, the residual clause “can no longer
mandate or authorize any sentence.”
Ante, at 9 (“striking
down the residual clause” is what “changed the substantive reach of
[ACCA]”).
That approach is untenable. It brushes aside the
rule of decision, which is where all of our prior precedents begin
and end for purposes of applying
Teague. When deciding
whether rules are substantive, our cases have homed in on the rule
that would apply not just to the specific statute at hand, but in
similar, future circumstances. Thus, just this Term, the Court
defined the rule announced in
Miller v.
Alabama, 567
U. S. ___ (2012), as: The Eighth Amendment “prohibit[s]
. . . mandatory life without parole for juvenile
offenders”—not that Alabama’s juvenile-sentencing statute flouts
the Eighth Amendment.
Montgomery,
supra, at ___ (slip
op., at 14). Likewise, the rule announced in
Ring v.
Arizona, 536 U. S. 584 (2002) , was that “a sentencing
judge, sitting without a jury, [may not] find an aggravating
circumstance necessary for imposition of the death penalty”—not
that provisions of Arizona’s death penalty statute violate the
Sixth Amendment.
Schriro, 542 U. S., at 353 (internal
quotation marks omitted; alteration in original). By jettisoning
that approach and focusing solely on
Johnson’s effect (the
invalidationof the residual clause), the majority departs from our
precedents.
The majority’s focus on the
effect of a
decision breaks down all meaningful distinctions between “new” and
“old” rules, or “substantive” and “procedural” ones. The first step
of the
Teague inquiry assesses whether the ruleis “new” by
looking to whether prior precedents dictated the rule of
decision—not its effects. See,
e.g., Chaidez v.
United
States, 568 U. S. ___, ___ (2013) (slip op., at 4)
(internal quotation marks omitted). But if, as the majority
contends, the “function of the rule,”
ante, at 10, is the
relevant baseline, then
every case invalidating a statute or
a sentence establishes a “new” rule. The law’s invalidation would
be a departure from any prior decision that interpreted the law as
if it were operative. Likewise, if any decision has the effect of
invalidating substantive provisions of a criminal statute, it is a
substantive rule under the majority’s approach no matter what the
reason for the statute’s invalidation.
The majority denies that “every decision
striking down a statute is
ipso facto a substantive
decision,” saying that only when a decision invalidates a provision
that “regulates conduct and prescribes punishment” is it
retroactive.
Ante, at 14. But that still transforms
innumerable procedural rules into substantive ones. Take a state
law that defines the crime of robbery and specifies that only 10 of
the 12 jurors need to vote to convict someone of that crime. If
this Court were to reverse
Apodaca v.
Oregon, 406
U. S. 404 (1972) , and hold that the Sixth Amendment requires
unanimous jury verdicts, the portion of the statute allowing
nonunanimity would be invalid. But assume that the state statute
was nonseverable: the Court’s jury unanim-ity rule, undoubtedly
“procedural,” would have the effect of invalidating not only the
portion of the state statute regarding unanimity but also the
provision defining the crime of robbery, a provision that
“regulates conduct.”
Ante, at 14. To the majority, these
effects would make the rule substantive. That approach is mistaken,
and would also produce arbitrary results. Suppose most States had
similar statutes, but that some had robust severability provisions
and others did not. In some States, the decision would be
procedural; elsewhere, it would be substantive, producing a
patchwork of statute-specific outcomes.
Finally, the majority flips
Teague on its
head with its alternative contention that
Johnson must have
announced a substantive rule because it is “not a procedural
decision.”
Ante, at 9.
Teague is a general rule
against retroactivity, see
ante, at 7–8, and all new rules
are barred unless they fit within the exceptions for substantive or
“watershed” procedural rules. 489 U. S., at 310–311 (plurality
opinion). To say that a rule is “not . . . procedural” is
not enough. And even if it were, the rule in
Johnson fits
better within the Court’s descriptions of procedural rules than
substantive ones. “Procedural rules . . . are designed to
enhance the accuracy of a conviction or sentence by regulating
‘
the manner of determining the defendant’s
culpability.’ ”
Montgomery, 577 U. S., at ___
(slip op., at 9) (quoting
Schriro,
supra, at 353).
And the rule in
Johnson regulates only the manner in which
Congress defined a sentencing enhancement, not the conduct that
triggers the punishment.
E.g., Smith v.
Goguen, 415
U. S. 566 –573 (1994) (vagueness doctrine “requires
legislatures to set reasonably clear guidelines” to give “fair
notice or warning” and “prevent arbitrary and discriminatory
enforcement” (internal quotation marks omitted)).
III
Today’s opinion underscores a larger problem
with our retroactivity doctrine: The Court’s retroactivity rules
have become unmoored from the limiting principles that the Court
invoked to justify the doctrine’s existence. Under
Teague
itself, the question whether
Johnson applies retroactively
would be a straightforward “No.” If this question is close now,
that is only because the Court keeps moving the goalposts.
As the majority observes, the foundations of our
approach to retroactivity in collateral review come from Justice
Harlan’s separate opinions in
Desist v.
United
States, 394 U. S. 244 (1969) , and
Mackey v.
United States, 401 U. S. 667 .
Ante, at 7.
There, Justice Harlan con-fronted a now-familiar problem: how to
address the con-sequences of an ever-evolving Constitution. He
responded with an approach to retroactivity that placed at the
forefront the need for finality in the criminal process. See,
e.g, 401 U. S., at 682–683. In his view, very few rules
that emerged after a prisoner’s conviction—including constitutional
rules—warranted disturbing that conviction. See
id., at
686–692. Justice Harlan saw only “two exceptions”: “bedrock
procedural” rules,
id., at 692–693, and “[n]ew ‘substantive
due process’ rules” removing “certain kinds of primary, private
individual conduct beyond the power of the criminal law-making
authority to proscribe,”
id., at 692. As examples of the
latter category, he cited such rules as that the First Amendment
forbids criminalizing flag burning, that the right to privacy
precludes the Government from prosecuting distributors of
contraception, and that the “freedom to marry” and equal protection
principles immunize couples from being punished for entering into
interracial marriages.
Id., at 692, n. 7. These
“ ‘substantive due process’ rules,” Justice Harlan explained,
were “on a different footing” because “the writ has historically
been available for attacking convictions on such grounds.”
Id., at 692–693. Moreover, society has an “obvious interest
in freeing individuals for punishment for conduct that is
constitutionally protected.”
Id., at 693. And granting
relief for such claims would not require retrials.
Ibid.
When
Teague adopted Justice Harlan’s
approach, see 489 U. S., at 310 (plurality opinion), it agreed
that to preserve “the principle of finality which is essential to
the operation of our criminal justice system,”
id., at 309,
“new rules generally should not be applied retroactively to cases
on collateral review,”
id., at 305.
Teague thus
adopted Justice Harlan’s two exceptions for “watershed rules of
criminal procedure” and rules that “accord constitutional
protection to . . . primary activity.”
Id., at
311; see
id., at 310.
The Court then swiftly discarded the limitations
that
Teague adopted.
Penry proclaimed the
retroactivity of rules barring certain
punishments, even
though the Court’s constant revision of the Eighth Amendment
produces an “ever-moving target of impermissible punishments.”
Montgomery, 577 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 11)
(Scalia, J., dissenting) (emphasis deleted); see
id., at
___–___ (slip op., at 10–11).
Bousley extended retroactive
relief for federal prisoners raising statutory claims, not just
constitutional ones. See 523 U. S., at 616–617, 620–621.
Montgomery extended
Teague to state postconviction
proceedings, enshrined
Teague as a constitutional command,
and redefined substantive rules to include rules that require
sentencers to follow certain procedures in punishing juveniles. Now
the majority collapses
Teague’s substantive-procedural
distinction further, allowing any rule that has the incidental
effect of invalidating substantive provisions of a criminal statute
to become a substantive rule.
Today’s decision, like those that preceded it,
professes to venerate Justice Harlan’s theory of retroactivity. See
ante, at 7;
Montgomery,
supra, at ___ (slip
op., at 8–10). This rings hollow; these decisions spell its ruin.
The Court adopted Justice Harlan’s approach to retroactivity
because it shared his conviction that “there [must] be a visible
end to the litigable aspect of the criminal process.”
Mackey,
supra, at 690; see
Teague,
supra, at 310 (plurality opinion) (similar). With the
Court’s unprincipled expansion of
Teague, every end is
instead a new beginning.
* * *
For these reasons, I respectfully dissent.