NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the
United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter
of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Washington,
D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in
order that corrections may be made before the preliminary print
goes to press.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
Nos. 13–354 and 13–356
_________________
SYLVIA BURWELL, SECRETARY OF HEALTHAND
HUMAN SERVICES, et al., PETITIONERS
13–354 v.
HOBBY LOBBY STORES, INC.,
et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
courtof appeals for the tenth circuit
and
CONESTOGA WOOD SPECIALTIES
CORPORATIONet al., PETITIONERS
13–356 v.
SYLVIA BURWELL, SECRETARY OF HEALTHAND
HUMAN SERVICES, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
courtof appeals for the third circuit
[June 30, 2014]
Justice Alito
delivered the opinion of the Court.
We must decide in these
cases whether the Religious Freedom Restoration Act of 1993 (RFRA),
107Stat. 1488, 42 U. S. C. §2000bb et seq., permits the
United States Department of Health and Human Services (HHS) to
demand that three closely held corporations provide
health-insurance coverage for methods of contraception that violate
the sincerely held religious beliefs of the companies’ owners. We
hold that the regulations that impose this obligation violate RFRA,
which prohibits the Federal Government from taking any action that
substantially burdens the exercise of religion unless that action
constitutes the least restrictive means of serving a compelling
government interest.
In holding that the HHS
mandate is unlawful, we reject HHS’s argument that the owners of
the companies for-feited all RFRA protection when they decided to
organize their businesses as corporations rather than sole
proprietorships or general partnerships. The plain terms of RFRA
make it perfectly clear that Congress did not discriminate in this
way against men and women who wish to run their businesses as
for-profit corporations in the manner required by their religious
beliefs.
Since RFRA applies in
these cases, we must decide whether the challenged HHS regulations
substantially burden the exercise of religion, and we hold that
they do. The owners of the businesses have religious objections to
abortion, and according to their religious beliefs the four
contraceptive methods at issue are abortifacients. If the owners
comply with the HHS mandate, they believe they will be facilitating
abortions, and if they do not comply, they will pay a very heavy
price—as much as $1.3 million per day, or about $475 million per
year, in the case of one of the companies. If these consequences do
not amount to a substantial burden, it is hard to see what
would.
Under RFRA, a
Government action that imposes a substantial burden on religious
exercise must serve a compelling government interest, and we assume
that the HHS regulations satisfy this requirement. But in order for
the HHS mandate to be sustained, it must also constitute the least
restrictive means of serving that interest, and the mandate plainly
fails that test. There are other ways in which Congress or HHS
could equally ensure that every woman has cost-free access to the
particular contraceptives at issue here and, indeed, to all
FDA-approved contraceptives.
In fact, HHS has
already devised and implemented a system that seeks to respect the
religious liberty of religious nonprofit corporations while
ensuring that the employees of these entities have precisely the
same access to all FDA-approved contraceptives as employees of
companies whose owners have no religious objections to providing
such coverage. The employees of these religious nonprofit
corporations still have access to insurance coverage without cost
sharing for all FDA-approved contracep-tives; and according to HHS,
this system imposes no net economic burden on the insurance
companies that are required to provide or secure the coverage.
Although HHS has made
this system available to religious nonprofits that have religious
objections to the contraceptive mandate, HHS has provided no reason
why the same system cannot be made available when the owners of
for-profit corporations have similar religious objections. We
therefore conclude that this system constitutes an alternative that
achieves all of the Government’s aims while providing greater
respect for religious liberty. And under RFRA, that conclusion
means that enforcement of the HHS contraceptive mandate against the
objecting parties in these cases is unlawful.
As this description of
our reasoning shows, our holding is very specific. We do not hold,
as the principal dissent alleges, that for-profit corporations and
other commercial enterprises can “opt out of any law (saving only
tax laws) they judge incompatible with their sincerely held
religious beliefs.” Post, at 1 (opinion of Ginsburg, J.). Nor do we
hold, as the dissent implies, that such corporations have free rein
to take steps that impose “disadvantages . . . on others”
or that require “the general public [to] pick up the tab.” Post, at
1–2. And we certainly do not hold or suggest that “RFRA demands
accommodation of a for-profit corporation’s religious beliefs no
matter the impact that accommodation may have on . . .
thousands of women employed by Hobby Lobby.” Post, at 2.[
1] The effect of the HHS-created
accommodation on the women employed by Hobby Lobby and the other
companies involved in these cases would be precisely zero. Under
that accommodation, these women would still be entitled to all
FDA-approved contraceptives without cost sharing.
I
A
Congress enacted RFRA
in 1993 in order to provide very broad protection for religious
liberty. RFRA’s enactment came three years after this Court’s
decision in Employment Div., Dept. of Human Resources of Ore. v.
Smith, 494 U. S. 872 (1990) , which largely repudiated the
method of analyzing free-exercise claims that had been used in
cases like Sherbert v. Verner, 374 U. S. 398 (1963), and
Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U. S. 205 (1972) . In determining
whether challenged government actions violated the Free Exercise
Clause of the First Amendment, those decisions used a balancing
test that took into account whether the challenged action imposed a
substantial burden on the practice of religion, and if it did,
whether it was needed to serve a compelling government interest.
Applying this test, the Court held in Sherbert that an employee who
was fired for refusing to work on her Sabbath could not be denied
unemployment benefits. 374 U. S., at 408–409. And in Yoder,
the Court held that Amish children could not be required to comply
with a state law demanding that they remain in school until the age
of 16 even though their religion required them to focus on uniquely
Amish values and beliefs during their formative adolescent years.
406 U. S., at 210–211, 234–236.
In Smith, however, the
Court rejected “the balancing test set forth in Sherbert.” 494
U. S., at 883. Smith concerned two members of the Native
American Church who were fired for ingesting peyote for sacramental
purposes. When they sought unemployment benefits, the State of
Oregon rejected their claims on the ground that consumption of
peyote was a crime, but the Oregon Supreme Court, applying the
Sherbert test, held that the denial of benefits violated the Free
Exercise Clause. 494 U. S., at 875.
This Court then
reversed, observing that use of the Sherbert test whenever a person
objected on religious grounds to the enforcement of a generally
applicable law “would open the prospect of constitutionally
required religious exemptions from civic obligations of almost
every conceivable kind.” 494 U. S., at 888. The Court
therefore held that, under the First Amendment, “neutral, generally
applicable laws may be applied to religious practices even when not
supported by a compelling governmental interest.” City of Boerne v.
Flores, 521 U. S. 507, 514 (1997).
Congress responded to
Smith by enacting RFRA. “[L]aws [that are] ‘neutral’ toward
religion,” Congress found, “may burden religious exercise as surely
as laws intended to interfere with religious exercise.”
42 U. S. C. §2000bb(a)(2); see also §2000bb(a)(4).
In order to ensure broad protection for religious liberty, RFRA
provides that “Government shall not substantially burden a person’s
exercise of religion even if the burden results from a rule of
general applicability.” §2000bb–1(a).[
2] If the Government substantially burdens a person’s
exercise of religion, under the Act that person is entitled to an
exemption from the rule unless the Government “demonstrates that
application of the burden to the person—(1) is in furtherance of a
compelling governmental interest; and (2) is the least restrictive
means of furthering that compelling governmental interest.”
§2000bb–1(b).[
3]
As enacted in 1993,
RFRA applied to both the Federal Government and the States, but the
constitutional authority invoked for regulating federal and state
agencies differed. As applied to a federal agency, RFRA is based on
the enumerated power that supports the particular agency’s
work,[
4] but in attempting to
regulate the States and their subdivisions, Congress relied on its
power under Section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment to enforce the
First Amendment. 521 U. S., at 516–517. In City of Boerne,
however, we held that Congress had overstepped its Section 5
authority because “[t]he stringent test RFRA demands” “far
exceed[ed] any pattern or practice of unconstitutional conduct
under the Free Exercise Clause as interpreted in Smith.” Id., at
533–534. See also id., at 532.
Following our decision
in City of Boerne, Congress passed the Religious Land Use and
Institutionalized Persons Act of 2000 (RLUIPA), 114Stat. 803, 42
U. S. C. §2000cc et seq. That statute, enacted under
Congress’s Commerce and Spending Clause powers, imposes the same
general test as RFRA but on a more limited category of governmental
actions. See Cutter v. Wilkinson, 544 U. S. 709 –716 (2005).
And, what is most relevant for present purposes, RLUIPA amended
RFRA’s definition of the “exercise of religion.” See §2000bb–2(4)
(importing RLUIPA definition). Before RLUIPA, RFRA’s definition
made reference to the First Amendment. See §2000bb–2(4) (1994 ed.)
(defining “exercise of religion” as “the exercise of religion under
the First Amendment”). In RLUIPA, in an obvious effort to effect a
complete separation from First Amendment case law, Congress deleted
the reference to the First Amendment and defined the “exercise of
religion” to include “any exercise of religion, whether or not
compelled by, or central to, a system of religious belief.”
§2000cc–5(7)(A). And Congress mandated that this concept “be
construed in favor of a broad protection of religious exercise, to
the maximum extent permitted by the terms of this chapter and the
Constitution.” §2000cc–3(g).[
5]
B
At issue in these
cases are HHS regulations promul-gated under the Patient Protection
and Affordable Care Act of 2010 (ACA), 124Stat. 119. ACA generally
requires employers with 50 or more full-time employees to offer“a
group health plan or group health insurance coverage” that provides
“minimum essential coverage.” 26 U. S. C. §5000A(f)(2);
§§4980H(a), (c)(2). Any covered employer that does not provide such
coverage must pay a substantial price. Specifically, if a covered
employer provides group health insurance but its plan fails to
comply with ACA’s group-health-plan requirements, the employer may
be required to pay $100 per day for each affected “individual.”
§§4980D(a)–(b). And if the employer decides to stop providing
health insurance altogether and at least one full-time employee
enrolls in a health plan and qualifies for a subsidy on one of the
government-run ACA exchanges, the employer must pay $2,000 per year
for each of its full-time employees. §§4980H(a), (c)(1).
Unless an exception
applies, ACA requires an employer’s group health plan or
group-health-insurance coverage to furnish “preventive care and
screenings” for women without “any cost sharing requirements.” 42
U. S. C. §300gg–13(a)(4). Congress itself, however, did
not specify what types of preventive care must be covered. Instead,
Congress authorized the Health Resources and Services
Administration (HRSA), a component of HHS, to make that important
and sensitive decision. Ibid. The HRSA in turn consulted the
Institute of Medicine, a nonprofit group of volunteer advisers, in
determining which preventive services to require. See 77 Fed. Reg.
8725–8726 (2012).
In August 2011, based
on the Institute’s recommendations, the HRSA promulgated the
Women’s Preventive Services Guidelines. See id., at 8725–8726, and
n. 1; online at http://hrsa.gov/womensguidelines (all Internet
materials as visited June 26, 2014, and available in Clerk of
Court’s case file). The Guidelines provide that nonexempt employers
are generally required to provide “coverage, without cost sharing”
for “[a]ll Food and Drug Ad-ministration [(FDA)] approved
contraceptive methods, sterilization procedures, and patient
education and counseling.” 77 Fed. Reg. 8725 (internal
quotation marks omitted). Although many of the required,
FDA-approved methods of contraception work by preventing the
fertilization of an egg, four of those methods (those specifically
at issue in these cases) may have the effect of preventing an
already fertilized egg from developing any further by inhibiting
its attachment to the uterus. See Brief for HHS in No. 13–354, pp.
9–10, n. 4;[
6] FDA, Birth
Control: Medicines to Help You.[
7]
HHS also authorized the
HRSA to establish exemptions from the contraceptive mandate for
“religious employers.” 45 CFR §147.131(a). That category
encompasses “churches, their integrated auxiliaries, and
conventions or associ-ations of churches,” as well as “the
exclusively religious activities of any religious order.” See ibid
(citing 26 U. S. C. §§6033(a)(3)(A)(i), (iii)). In its
Guidelines,HRSA exempted these organizations from the requirement
to cover contraceptive services. See
http://hrsa.gov/womensguidelines.
In addition, HHS has
effectively exempted certain religious nonprofit organizations,
described under HHS regulations as “eligible organizations,” from
the contraceptive mandate. See 45 CFR §147.131(b); 78 Fed. Reg.
39874 (2013). An “eligible organization” means a nonprofit
organization that “holds itself out as a religious organi-zation”
and “opposes providing coverage for some or all of any
contraceptive services required to be covered . . . on
account of religious objections.” 45 CFR §147.131(b). To qualify
for this accommodation, an employer must certify that it is such an
organization. §147.131(b)(4). When a group-health-insurance
issuer receives notice that one of its clients has invoked this
provision, the issuer must then exclude contraceptive coverage from
the employer’s plan and provide separate payments for contraceptive
services for plan participants without imposing any cost-sharing
requirements on the eligible organization, its insurance plan, or
its employee beneficiaries. §147.131(c).[
8] Al-though this procedure requires the issuer to bear
the cost of these services, HHS has determined that this obligation
will not impose any net expense on issuers because its cost will be
less than or equal to the cost savings resulting from the services.
78 Fed. Reg. 39877.[
9]
In addition to these
exemptions for religious organizations, ACA exempts a great many
employers from most of its coverage requirements. Employers
providing “grandfathered health plans”—those that existed prior to
March 23, 2010, and that have not made specified changes after that
date—need not comply with many of the Act’s requirements, including
the contraceptive mandate. 42 U. S. C. §§18011(a), (e).
And employers with fewer than 50 employees are not required to
provide health insurance at all. 26 U. S. C.
§4980H(c)(2).
All told, the
contraceptive mandate “presently does not apply to tens of millions
of people.” 723 F. 3d 1114, 1143 (CA10 2013). This is
attributable, in large part, to grandfathered health plans: Over
one-third of the 149 million nonelderly people in America with
employer-sponsored health plans were enrolled in grandfathered
plans in 2013. Brief for HHS in No. 13–354, at 53; Kaiser Family
Foundation & Health Research & Educational Trust, Employer
Health Benefits, 2013 Annual Survey 43, 221.[
10] The count for employees working for firms
that do not have to provide insurance at all because they employ
fewer than 50 employees is 34 million workers. See The Whitehouse,
Health Reform for Small Businesses: The Affordable Care Act
Increases Choice and Saving Money for Small Businesses 1.[
11]
II
A
Norman and Elizabeth
Hahn and their three sons are devout members of the Mennonite
Church, a Christian denomination. The Mennonite Church opposes
abortion and believes that “[t]he fetus in its earliest stages
. . . shares humanity with those who conceived
it.”[
12]
Fifty years ago, Norman
Hahn started a wood-working business in his garage, and since then,
this company, Conestoga Wood Specialties, has grown and now has 950
employees. Conestoga is organized under Pennsylvania law as a
for-profit corporation. The Hahns exercise sole ownership of the
closely held business; they control its board of directors and hold
all of its voting shares. One of the Hahn sons serves as the
president and CEO.
The Hahns believe that
they are required to run their business “in accordance with their
religious beliefs and moral principles.” 917 F. Supp. 2d 394,
402 (ED Pa. 2013). To that end, the company’s mission, as they see
it, is to “operate in a professional environment founded upon the
highest ethical, moral, and Christian principles.” Ibid. (internal
quotation marks omitted). The company’s “Vision and Values
Statements” affirms that Conestoga endeavors to “ensur[e] a
reasonable profit in [a] manner that reflects [the Hahns’]
Christian heritage.” App. in No. 13–356, p. 94
(complaint).
As explained in
Conestoga’s board-adopted “Statement on the Sanctity of Human
Life,” the Hahns believe that “human life begins at conception.”
724 F. 3d 377, 382, and n. 5 (CA3 2013) (internal
quotation marks omitted). It is therefore “against [their] moral
conviction to be involved in the termination of human life” after
conception, which they believe is a “sin against God to which they
are held accountable.” Ibid. (internal quotation marks omitted).
The Hahns have accordingly excluded from the group-health-insurance
plan they offer to their employees certain contraceptive methods
that they consider to be abortifacients. Id., at 382.
The Hahns and Conestoga
sued HHS and other federal officials and agencies under RFRA and
the Free Exercise Clause of the First Amendment, seeking to enjoin
application of ACA’s contraceptive mandate insofar as it requires
them to provide health-insurance coverage for four FDA-approved
contraceptives that may operate after the fertilization of an
egg.[
13] These include two
forms of emergency contraception commonly called “morning after”
pills and two types of intrauterine devices.[
14]
In opposing the
requirement to provide coverage for the contraceptives to which
they object, the Hahns argued that “it is immoral and sinful for
[them] to intentionally participate in, pay for, facilitate, or
otherwise support these drugs.” Ibid. The District Court denied a
preliminary injunction, see 917 F. Supp. 2d, at 419, and
the Third Circuit affirmed in a divided opinion, holding that
“for-profit, secular corporations cannot engage in religious
exercise” within the meaning of RFRA or the First Amendment. 724
F. 3d, at 381. The Third Circuit also rejected the claims
brought by the Hahns themselves because it concluded that the HHS
“[m]andate does not impose any requirements on the Hahns” in their
personal capacity. Id., at 389.
B
David and Barbara
Green and their three children are Christians who own and operate
two family businesses. Forty-five years ago, David Green started an
arts-and-crafts store that has grown into a nationwide chain called
Hobby Lobby. There are now 500 Hobby Lobby stores, and the company
has more than 13,000 employees. 723 F. 3d, at 1122. Hobby
Lobby is organized as a for-profit corporation under Oklahoma
law.
One of David’s sons
started an affiliated business, Mardel, which operates 35 Christian
bookstores and employs close to 400 people. Ibid. Mardel is also
organized as a for-profit corporation under Oklahoma law.
Though these two
businesses have expanded over the years, they remain closely held,
and David, Barbara, and their children retain exclusive control of
both companies. Ibid. David serves as the CEO of Hobby Lobby, and
his three children serve as the president, vice president, and vice
CEO. See Brief for Respondents in No. 13–354, p. 8.[
15]
Hobby Lobby’s statement
of purpose commits the Greens to “[h]onoring the Lord in all [they]
do by operating the company in a manner consistent with Biblical
principles.” App. in No. 13–354, pp. 134–135 (complaint). Each
family member has signed a pledge to run the businesses in
accordance with the family’s religious beliefs and to use the
family assets to support Christian ministries. 723 F. 3d, at
1122. In accordance with those commitments, Hobby Lobby and Mardel
stores close on Sundays, even though the Greens calculate that they
lose millions in sales annually by doing so. Id., at 1122; App. in
No. 13–354, at 136–137. The businesses refuse to engage in
profitable transactions that facilitate or promote alcohol use;
they contribute profits to Christian missionaries and ministries;
and they buy hundreds of full-page newspaper ads inviting people to
“know Jesus as Lord and Savior.” Ibid. (internal quotation marks
omitted).
Like the Hahns, the
Greens believe that life begins at conception and that it would
violate their religion to facilitate access to contraceptive drugs
or devices that operate after that point. 723 F. 3d, at 1122.
They specifically object to the same four contraceptive methods as
the Hahns and, like the Hahns, they have no objection to the other
16 FDA-approved methods of birth control. Id., at 1125. Although
their group-health-insurance plan predates the enactment of ACA, it
is not a grandfathered plan because Hobby Lobby elected not to
retain grandfathered status before the contraceptive mandate was
proposed. Id., at 1124.
The Greens, Hobby
Lobby, and Mardel sued HHS and other federal agencies and officials
to challenge the contraceptive mandate under RFRA and the Free
Exercise Clause.[
16] The
District Court denied a preliminary injunction, see 870 F. Supp. 2d
1278 (WD Okla. 2012), and the plaintiffs appealed, moving for
initial en banc consideration. The Tenth Circuit granted that
motion and reversed in a divided opinion. Contrary to the
conclusion of the Third Circuit, the Tenth Circuit held that the
Greens’ two for-profit businesses are “persons” within the meaning
of RFRA and therefore may bring suit under that law.
The court then held
that the corporations had established a likelihood of success on
their RFRA claim. 723 F. 3d, at 1140–1147. The court concluded
that the contraceptive mandate substantially burdened the exercise
of religion by requiring the companies to choose between
“compromis[ing] their religious beliefs” and paying a heavy
fee—either “close to $475 million more in taxes every year” if they
simply refused to provide coverage for the contraceptives at issue,
or “roughly $26 million” annually if they “drop[ped]
health-insurance benefits for all employees.” Id., at 1141.
The court next held
that HHS had failed to demonstrate a compelling interest in
enforcing the mandate against the Greens’ businesses and, in the
alternative, that HHS had failed to prove that enforcement of the
mandate was the “least restrictive means” of furthering the
Government’s asserted interests. Id., at 1143–1144 (emphasis
deleted; internal quotation marks omitted). After concluding that
the companies had “demonstrated irreparable harm,” the court
reversed and remanded for the District Court to consider the
remaining factors of the preliminary-injunction test. Id., at
1147.[
17]
We granted certiorari.
571 U. S. ___ (2013).
III
A
RFRA prohibits the
“Government [from] substantially burden[ing] a person’s exercise of
religion even if the burden results from a rule of general
applicability” unless the Government “demonstrates that application
of the burden to the person—(1) is in furtherance of a compelling
governmental interest; and (2) is the least restrictive means of
furthering that compelling governmental interest.” 42
U. S. C. §§2000bb–1(a), (b) (emphasis added). The
first question that we must address is whether this provision
applies to regulations that govern the activities of for-profit
corporations like Hobby Lobby, Conestoga, and Mardel.
HHS contends that
neither these companies nor their owners can even be heard under
RFRA. According to HHS, the companies cannot sue because they seek
to make a profit for their owners, and the owners cannotbe heard
because the regulations, at least as a formal mat-ter, apply only
to the companies and not to the ownersas individuals. HHS’s
argument would have dramatic consequences.
Consider this Court’s
decision in Braunfeld v. Brown, 366 U. S. 599 (1961)
(plurality opinion). In that case, five Orthodox Jewish merchants
who ran small retail businesses in Philadelphia challenged a
Pennsylvania Sunday closing law as a violation of the Free Exercise
Clause. Because of their faith, these merchants closed their shops
on Saturday, and they argued that requiring them to remain shut on
Sunday threatened them with financial ruin. The Court entertained
their claim (although it ruled against them on the merits), and if
a similar claim were raised today under RFRA against a jurisdiction
still subject to the Act (for example, the District of Columbia,
see 42 U. S. C. §2000bb–2(2)), the merchants would be
entitled to be heard. According to HHS, however, if these merchants
chose to incorporate their businesses—with-out in any way changing
the size or nature of their businesses—they would forfeit all RFRA
(and free-exercise) rights. HHS would put these merchants to a
difficult choice: either give up the right to seek judicial
protection of their religious liberty or forgo the benefits,
available to their competitors, of operating as corporations.
As we have seen, RFRA
was designed to provide very broad protection for religious
liberty. By enacting RFRA, Congress went far beyond what this Court
has held is constitutionally required.[
18] Is there any reason to think that the Congress
that enacted such sweeping protection put small-business owners to
the choice that HHS suggests? An examination of RFRA’s text, to
which we turn in the next part of this opinion, reveals that
Congress did no such thing.
As we will show,
Congress provided protection for people like the Hahns and Greens
by employing a familiar legal fiction: It included corporations
within RFRA’s definition of “persons.” But it is important to keep
in mind that the purpose of this fiction is to provide protection
for human beings. A corporation is simply a form of organization
used by human beings to achieve desired ends. An established body
of law specifies the rights and obligations of the people
(including shareholders, officers, and employees) who are
associated with a corporation in one way or another. When rights,
whether constitutional or statu-tory, are extended to corporations,
the purpose is to protect the rights of these people. For example,
extending Fourth Amendment protection to corporations protects the
privacy interests of employees and others associated with the
company. Protecting corporations from government seizure of their
property without just compensation protects all those who have a
stake in the corporations’ financial well-being. And protecting the
free-exercise rights of corporations like Hobby Lobby, Conestoga,
and Mardel protects the religious liberty of the humans who own and
control those companies.
In holding that
Conestoga, as a “secular, for-profit corporation,” lacks RFRA
protection, the Third Circuit wrote as follows:
“General business corporations do not,
separate and apart from the actions or belief systems of their
individual owners or employees, exercise religion. They do not
pray, worship, observe sacraments or take other
religiously-motivated actions separate and apart from the intention
and direction of their individual actors.” 724 F. 3d, at 385
(emphasis added).
All of this is true—but quite beside the point.
Corporations, “separate and apart from” the human beings who own,
run, and are employed by them, cannot do anything at all.
B
1
As we noted above,
RFRA applies to “a person’s” exercise of religion, 42 U. S. C.
§§2000bb–1(a), (b), and RFRA itself does not define the term
“person.” We therefore look to the Dictionary Act, which we must
consult “[i]n determining the meaning of any Act of Congress,
unless the context indicates otherwise.” 1 U. S. C.
§1.
Under the Dictionary
Act, “the wor[d] ‘person’ . . . include[s] corporations,
companies, associations, firms, partnerships, societies, and joint
stock companies, as well as individuals.” Ibid.; see FCC v.
AT&T Inc., 562 U. S. ___, ___ (2011) (slip op., at 6) (“We
have no doubt that ‘person,’ in a legal setting, often refers to
artificial entities. The Dictionary Act makes that clear”). Thus,
unless there is something about the RFRA context that “indicates
otherwise,” the Dictionary Act provides a quick, clear, and
affirmative answer to the question whether the companies involved
in these cases may be heard.
We see nothing in RFRA
that suggests a congressional intent to depart from the Dictionary
Act definition, and HHS makes little effort to argue otherwise. We
have entertained RFRA and free-exercise claims brought by nonprofit
corporations, see Gonzales v. O Centro Espírita Beneficiente União
do Vegetal, 546 U. S. 418 (2006) (RFRA); Hosanna-Tabor
Evangelical Lutheran Church and School v. EEOC, 565 U. S. ___
(2012) (Free Exercise); Church of the Lukumi Babalu Aye, Inc. v.
Hialeah, 508 U. S. 520 (1993) (Free Exercise), and HHS concedes
that a nonprofit corporation can be a “person” within the meaning
of RFRA. See Brief for HHS in No. 13–354, at 17; Reply Brief in No.
13–354, at 7–8.[
19]
This concession
effectively dispatches any argument that the term “person” as used
in RFRA does not reach the closely held corporations involved in
these cases. No known understanding of the term “person” includes
some but not all corporations. The term “person” sometimes
encompasses artificial persons (as the Dictionary Act instructs),
and it sometimes is limited to natural persons. But no conceivable
definition of the term includes natural persons and nonprofit
corporations, but not for-profit corporations.[
20] Cf. Clark v. Martinez, 543 U. S. 371, 378
(2005) (“To give th[e] same words a different meaning for each
category would be to invent a statute rather than interpret
one”).
2
The principal
argument advanced by HHS and the principal dissent regarding RFRA
protection for Hobby Lobby, Conestoga, and Mardel focuses not on
the statutory term “person,” but on the phrase “exercise of
religion.” According to HHS and the dissent, these corporations are
not protected by RFRA because they cannot exercise religion.
Neither HHS nor the dissent, however, provides any persuasive
explanation for this conclusion.
Is it because of the
corporate form? The corporate form alone cannot provide the
explanation because, as we have pointed out, HHS concedes that
nonprofit corporations can be protected by RFRA. The dissent
suggests that nonprofit corporations are special because furthering
their reli-gious “autonomy . . . often furthers individual
religious freedom as well.” Post, at 15 (quoting Corporation of
Presiding Bishop of Church of Jesus Christ of Latter-day Saints v.
Amos, 483 U. S. 327, 342 (1987) (Brennan, J., concurring in
judgment)). But this principle appliesequally to for-profit
corporations: Furthering their re-ligious freedom also “furthers
individual religious freedom.” In these cases, for example,
allowing Hobby Lobby, Con-estoga, and Mardel to assert RFRA claims
protects the religious liberty of the Greens and the
Hahns.[
21]
If the corporate form
is not enough, what about the profit-making objective? In
Braunfeld, 366 U. S. 599 , we entertained the free-exercise
claims of individuals who were attempting to make a profit as
retail merchants, and the Court never even hinted that this
objective precluded their claims. As the Court explained in a later
case, the “exercise of religion” involves “not only belief and
profession but the performance of (or abstention from) physical
acts” that are “engaged in for religious reasons.” Smith,
494 U. S., at 877. Business practices that are compelled
or limited by the tenets of a religious doctrine fall comfortably
within that definition. Thus, a law that “operates so as to make
the practice of . . . religious beliefs more expensive”
in the context of business activities imposes a burden on the
exercise of religion. Braunfeld, supra, at 605; see United States
v. Lee, 455 U. S. 252, 257 (1982) (recognizing that
“compulsory participation in the social security system interferes
with [Amish employers’] free exercise rights”).
If, as Braunfeld
recognized, a sole proprietorship that seeks to make a profit may
assert a free-exercise claim,[
22] why can’t Hobby Lobby, Conestoga, and Mardel do the
same?
Some lower court judges
have suggested that RFRA does not protect for-profit corporations
because the purpose of such corporations is simply to make
money.[
23] This argument
flies in the face of modern corporate law. “Each American
jurisdiction today either expressly or by implication authorizes
corporations to be formed under its general corporation act for any
lawful purpose or business.” 1 J. Cox & T. Hazen, Treatise of
the Law of Corporations §4:1, p. 224 (3d ed. 2010) (emphasis
added); see 1A W. Fletcher, Cyclopedia of the Law of Corporations
§102 (rev. ed. 2010). While it is certainly true that a central
objective of for-profit corporations is to make money, modern
corporate law does not require for-profit corporations to pursue
profit at the expense of everything else, and many do not do so.
For-profit corporations, with ownership approval, support a wide
variety of charitable causes, and it is not at all uncommon for
such corporations to further humanitarian and other altruistic
objectives. Many examples come readily to mind. So long as its
owners agree, a for-profit corporation may take costly
pollution-control and energy-conservation measures that go beyond
what the law requires. A for-profit corporation that operates
facilities in other countries may exceed the requirements of local
law regarding working conditions and benefits. If for-profit
corporations may pursue such worthy objectives, there is no
apparent reason why they may not further religious objectives as
well.
HHS would draw a sharp
line between nonprofit corporations (which, HHS concedes, are
protected by RFRA) and for-profit corporations (which HHS would
leave unprotected), but the actual picture is less clear-cut. Not
all corporations that decline to organize as nonprofits do so in
order to maximize profit. For example, organizations with religious
and charitable aims might organize as for-profit corporations
because of the potential advantages of that corporate form, such as
the freedom to participate in lobbying for legislation or
campaigning for political candidates who promote their religious or
charitable goals.[
24] In
fact, recognizing the inherent compatibility between establishing a
for-profit corporation and pursuing nonprofit goals, States have
increasingly adopted laws formally recognizing hybrid corporate
forms. Over half of the States, for instance, now recognize the
“benefit corporation,” a dual-purpose entity that seeks to achieve
both a benefit for the public and a profit for its owners.[
25]
In any event, the
objectives that may properly be pursued by the companies in these
cases are governed by the laws of the States in which they were
incorporated—Pennsylvania and Oklahoma—and the laws of those States
permit for-profit corporations to pursue “any lawful purpose” or
“act,” including the pursuit of profit in conformity with the
owners’ religious principles. 15 Pa. Cons. Stat. §1301 (2001)
(“Corporations may be incorporated under this subpart for any
lawful purpose or purposes”); Okla. Stat., Tit. 18, §§1002, 1005
(West 2012) (“[E]very corporation, whether profit or not for
profit” may “be incorporated or organized . . . to
conduct or promote any lawful business or purposes”); see also
§1006(A)(3); Brief for State of Oklahoma as Amicus Curiae in No.
13–354.
3
HHS and the principal
dissent make one additional argument in an effort to show that a
for-profit corporation cannot engage in the “exercise of religion”
within the meaning of RFRA: HHS argues that RFRA did no more than
codify this Court’s pre-Smith Free Exercise Clause precedents, and
because none of those cases squarely held that a for-profit
corporation has free-exercise rights, RFRA does not confer such
protection. This argument has many flaws.
First, nothing in the
text of RFRA as originally enacted suggested that the statutory
phrase “exercise of religion under the First Amendment” was meant
to be tied to this Court’s pre-Smith interpretation of that
Amendment. When first enacted, RFRA defined the “exercise of
religion” to mean “the exercise of religion under the First
Amendment”—not the exercise of religion as recognized only by
then-existing Supreme Court precedents. 42 U. S. C.
§2000bb–2(4) (1994 ed.). When Congress wants to link the meaning of
a statutory provision to a body of this Court’s case law, it knows
how to do so. See, e.g., Antiterrorism and Effective Death Penalty
Act of 1996, 28 U. S. C. §2254(d)(1) (authorizing habeas
relief from a state-court decision that “was contrary to, or
involved an unreasonable application of, clearly established
Federal law, as determined by the Supreme Court of the United
States”).
Second, if the original
text of RFRA was not clear enough on this point—and we think it
was—the amendment of RFRA through RLUIPA surely dispels any doubt.
That amendment deleted the prior reference to the First Amendment,
see 42 U. S. C. §2000bb–2(4) (2000 ed.) (incorporating
§2000cc–5), and neither HHS nor the principal dissent can explain
why Congress did this if it wanted to tie RFRA coverage tightly to
the specific holdings of our pre-Smith free-exercise cases.
Moreover, as discussed, the amendment went further, providing that
the exercise of religion “shall be construed in favor of a broad
protection of religious exercise, to the maximum extent permitted
by the terms of this chapter and the Constitution.” §2000cc–3(g).
It is simply not possible to read these provisions as restricting
the concept of the “exercise of religion” to those practices
specifically addressed in our pre-Smith decisions.
Third, the one
pre-Smith case involving the free-exercise rights of a for-profit
corporation suggests, if anything, that for-profit corporations
possess such rights. In Gallagher v. Crown Kosher Super Market of
Mass., Inc., 366 U. S. 617 (1961) , the Massachusetts Sunday
closing law was challenged by a kosher market that was organized as
a for-profit corporation, by customers of the market, and by a
rabbi. The Commonwealth argued that the corporation lacked
“standing” to assert a free-exercise claim,[
26] but not one member of the Court expressed
agreement with that argument. The plurality opinion for four
Justices rejected the First Amendment claim on the merits based on
the reasoning in Braunfeld, and reserved decision on the question
whether the corporation had “standing” to raise the claim. See 366
U. S., at 631. The three dissenters, Justices Douglas,
Brennan, and Stewart, found the law unconstitutional as applied to
the corporation and the other challengers and thus implicitly
recognized their right to assert a free-exercise claim. See id., at
642 (Brennan, J., joined by Stewart, J., dissenting); McGowan v.
Maryland, 366 U. S. 420 –579 (1961) (Douglas, J., dissenting
as to related cases including Gallagher). Fi-nally, Justice
Frankfurter’s opinion, which was joined by Justice Harlan, upheld
the Massachusetts law on the merits but did not question or reserve
decision on the issue of the right of the corporation or any of the
other challengers to be heard. See McGowan, 366 U. S., at
521–522. It is quite a stretch to argue that RFRA, a law enacted to
provide very broad protection for religious liberty,left for-profit
corporations unprotected simply because in Gallagher—the only
pre-Smith case in which the issue was raised—a majority of the
Justices did not find it necessary to decide whether the kosher
market’s corporate status barred it from raising a free-exercise
claim.
Finally, the
results would be absurd if RFRA merely restored this Court’s
pre-Smith decisions in ossified form and did not allow a plaintiff
to raise a RFRA claim unless that plaintiff fell within a category
of plaintiffs one of whom had brought a free-exercise claim that
this Court entertained in the years before Smith. For example, we
are not aware of any pre-Smith case in which this Court entertained
a free-exercise claim brought by a resident noncitizen. Are such
persons also beyond RFRA’s protective reach simply because the
Court never addressed their rights before Smith?
Presumably in
recognition of the weakness of this argument, both HHS and the
principal dissent fall back on the broader contention that the
Nation lacks a tradition of exempting for-profit corporations from
generally applicable laws. By contrast, HHS contends, statutes like
Title VII, 42 U. S. C. §2000e–19(A), expressly exempt
churches and other nonprofit religious institutions but not
for-profit corporations. See Brief for HHS in No. 13–356,
p. 26. In making this argument, however, HHS did not call to
our attention the fact that some federal statutes do exempt
categories of entities that include for-profit corporations from
laws that would otherwise require these entities to engage in
activities to which they object on grounds of conscience. See,
e.g., 42 U. S. C. §300a–7(b)(2); §238n(a).[
27] If Title VII and similar laws show
anything, it isthat Congress speaks with specificity when it
intends a religious accommodation not to extend to
for-profitcorporations.
4
Finally, HHS contends
that Congress could not have wanted RFRA to apply to for-profit
corporations because it is difficult as a practical matter to
ascertain the sincere “beliefs” of a corporation. HHS goes so far
as to raise the specter of “divisive, polarizing proxy battles over
the religious identity of large, publicly traded corporations such
as IBM or General Electric.” Brief for HHS in No. 13–356, at
30.
These cases, however,
do not involve publicly traded corporations, and it seems unlikely
that the sort of corporate giants to which HHS refers will often
assert RFRA claims. HHS has not pointed to any example of a
publicly traded corporation asserting RFRA rights, and numerous
practical restraints would likely prevent that from occurring. For
example, the idea that unrelated shareholders—including
institutional investors with their own set of stakeholders—would
agree to run a corporation under the same religious beliefs seems
improbable. In any event, we have no occasion in these cases to
consider RFRA’s applicability to such companies. The companies in
the cases before us are closely held corporations, each owned and
controlled by members of a single family, and no one has disputed
the sincerity of their religious beliefs.[
28]
HHS has also provided
no evidence that the purported problem of determining the sincerity
of an asserted religious belief moved Congress to exclude
for-profit corporations from RFRA’s protection. On the contrary,
the scope of RLUIPA shows that Congress was confident of the
ability of the federal courts to weed out insincere claims. RLUIPA
applies to “institutionalized persons,” a category that consists
primarily of prisoners, and by the time of RLUIPA’s enactment, the
propensity of some prisoners to assert claims of dubious sincerity
was well documented.[
29]
Nevertheless, after our decision in City of Boerne, Congress
enacted RLUIPA to preserve the right of prisoners to raise
religious liberty claims. If Congress thought that the federal
courts were up to the job of dealing with insincere prisoner
claims, there is no reason to believe that Congress limited RFRA’s
reach out of concern for the seem-ingly less difficult task of
doing the same in corporate cases. And if, as HHS seems to concede,
Congress wanted RFRA to apply to nonprofit corporations, see, Reply
Brief in No. 13–354, at 7–8, what reason is there to think that
Congress believed that spotting insincere claims wouldbe tougher in
cases involving for-profits?
HHS and the principal
dissent express concern about the possibility of disputes among the
owners of corporations, but that is not a problem that arises
because of RFRA or that is unique to this context. The owners of
closely held corporations may—and sometimes do—disagree about the
conduct of business. 1 Treatise of the Law of Corporations §14:11.
And even if RFRA did not exist, the owners of a company might well
have a dispute relating to religion. For example, some might want a
company’s stores to remain open on the Sabbath in order to make
more money, and others might want the stores to close for religious
reasons. State corporate law provides a ready means for resolving
any conflicts by, for example, dictating how a corporation can
establish its governing structure. See, e.g., ibid; id., §3:2; Del.
Code Ann., Tit. 8, §351 (2011) (providing that certificate of
incorporation may provide how “the business of the corporation
shall be managed”). Courts will turn to that structure and the
underlying state law in resolving disputes.
For all these reasons,
we hold that a federal regulation’s restriction on the activities
of a for-profit closely held corporation must comply with
RFRA.[
30]
IV
Because RFRA applies
in these cases, we must next ask whether the HHS contraceptive
mandate “substantially burden[s]” the exercise of religion. 42
U. S. C. §2000bb–1(a). We have little trouble concluding
that it does.
A
As we have noted, the
Hahns and Greens have a sincere religious belief that life begins
at conception. They therefore object on religious grounds to
providing health insurance that covers methods of birth control
that, as HHS acknowledges, see Brief for HHS in No. 13–354, at 9,
n. 4, may result in the destruction of an embryo. By requiring
the Hahns and Greens and their companies to arrange for such
coverage, the HHS mandate demands that they engage in conduct that
seriously violates their religious beliefs.
If the Hahns and Greens
and their companies do not yield to this demand, the economic
consequences will be severe. If the companies continue to offer
group health plans that do not cover the contraceptives at issue,
they will be taxed $100 per day for each affected individual. 26
U. S. C. §4980D. For Hobby Lobby, the bill could amount
to $1.3 million per day or about $475 million per year; for
Conestoga, the assessment could be $90,000 per day or $33 million
per year; and for Mardel, it could be $40,000 per day or about $15
million per year. These sums are surely substantial.
It is true that the
plaintiffs could avoid these assessments by dropping insurance
coverage altogether and thus forcing their employees to obtain
health insurance on one of the exchanges established under ACA. But
if at least one of their full-time employees were to qualify for a
subsidy on one of the government-run exchanges, this course would
also entail substantial economic consequences. The companies could
face penalties of $2,000 per employee each year. §4980H. These
penalties would amount to roughly $26 million for Hobby Lobby, $1.8
million for Conestoga, and $800,000 for Mardel.
B
Although these totals
are high, amici supporting HHS have suggested that the $2,000
per-employee penalty is actually less than the average cost of
providing health insurance, see Brief for Religious Organizations
22, and therefore, they claim, the companies could readily
eliminate any substantial burden by forcing their employees to
obtain insurance in the government exchanges. We do not generally
entertain arguments that were not raised below and are not advanced
in this Court by any party, see United Parcel Service, Inc. v.
Mitchell, 451 U. S. 56 , n. 2 (1981); Bell v. Wolfish,
441 U. S. 520 , n. 13 (1979); Knetsch v. United States,
364 U. S. 361, 370 (1960) , and there are strong reasons to
adhere to that practice in these cases. HHS, which presumably could
have compiled the relevant statistics, has never made this
argument—not in its voluminous briefing or at oral argument in this
Court nor, to our knowledge, in any of the numerous cases in which
the issue now before us has been litigated around the country. As
things now stand, we do not even know what the Government’s
position might be with respect to these amici’s intensely empirical
argument.[
31] For this same
reason, the plaintiffs have never had an opportunity to respond to
this novel claim that—contrary to their longstanding practice and
that of most large employers—they would be better off discarding
their employer insurance plans altogether.
Even if we were to
reach this argument, we would find it unpersuasive. As an initial
matter, it entirely ignores the fact that the Hahns and Greens and
their companies have religious reasons for providing
health-insurance coverage for their employees. Before the advent of
ACA, they were not legally compelled to provide insurance, but they
nevertheless did so—in part, no doubt, for conventional business
reasons, but also in part because their religious beliefs govern
their relations with their employees. See App. to Pet. for Cert. in
No. 13–356, p. 11g; App. in No. 13–354, at 139.
Putting aside the
religious dimension of the decision to provide insurance, moreover,
it is far from clear that the net cost to the companies of
providing insurance is more than the cost of dropping their
insurance plans and paying the ACA penalty. Health insurance is a
benefit that employees value. If the companies simply eliminated
that benefit and forced employees to purchase their own insurance
on the exchanges, without offering additional compensation, it is
predictable that the companies would face a competitive
disadvantage in retaining and attracting skilled workers. See App.
in No. 13–354, at 153.
The companies could
attempt to make up for the elimination of a group health plan by
increasing wages, but this would be costly. Group health insurance
is generally less expensive than comparable individual coverage, so
the amount of the salary increase needed to fully compensate for
the termination of insurance coverage may well exceed the cost to
the companies of providing the insurance. In addition, any salary
increase would have to take into account the fact that employees
must pay income taxes on wages but not on the value of
employer-provided health insurance. 26 U. S. C. §106(a).
Likewise, employers can deduct the cost of providing health
insurance, see §162(a)(1), but apparently cannot deduct the amount
of the penalty that they must pay if insurance is not pro-vided;
that difference also must be taken into account. Given these
economic incentives, it is far from clear that it would be
financially advantageous for an employer to drop coverage and pay
the penalty.[
32]
In sum, we refuse to
sustain the challenged regulations on the ground—never maintained
by the Government—that dropping insurance coverage eliminates the
substantial burden that the HHS mandate imposes. We doubt that the
Congress that enacted RFRA—or, for that matter, ACA—would have
believed it a tolerable result to put family-run businesses to the
choice of violating their sincerely held religious beliefs or
making all of their employees lose their existing healthcare
plans.
C
In taking the
position that the HHS mandate does not impose a substantial burden
on the exercise of religion, HHS’s main argument (echoed by the
principal dissent) is basically that the connection between what
the objecting parties must do (provide health-insurance coverage
for four methods of contraception that may operate after the
fertilization of an egg) and the end that they find to be morally
wrong (destruction of an embryo) is simply too attenuated. Brief
for HHS in 13–354, pp. 31–34; post, at 22–23. HHS and the dissent
note that providing the coverage would not itself result in the
destruction of an embryo; that would occur only if an employee
chose to take advantage of the coverage and to use one of the four
methods at issue.[
33]
Ibid.
This argument dodges
the question that RFRA presents (whether the HHS mandate imposes a
substantial burden on the ability of the objecting parties to
conduct business in accordance with their religious beliefs) and
instead addresses a very different question that the federal courts
have no business addressing (whether the religious belief asserted
in a RFRA case is reasonable). The Hahns and Greens believe that
providing the coverage demanded by the HHS regulations is connected
to the destruction of an embryo in a way that is sufficient to make
it immoral for them to provide the coverage. This belief implicates
a difficult and important question of religion and moral
philosophy, namely, the circumstances under which it is wrong for a
person to perform an act that is innocent in itself but that has
the effect of enabling or facilitating the commission of an immoral
act by another.[
34]
Arrogating the authority to provide a binding national answer to
this religious and philosophical question, HHS and the principal
dissent in effect tell the plaintiffs that their beliefs are
flawed. For good reason, we have repeatedly refused to take such a
step. See, e.g., Smith, 494 U. S., at 887 (“Repeatedly and in
many different contexts, we have warned that courts must not
presume to determine . . . the plausibility of a
religious claim”); Hernandez v. Commissioner, 490 U. S. 680,
699 (1989) ; Presbyterian Church in U. S. v. Mary Elizabeth
Blue Hull Memorial Presbyterian Church, 393 U. S. 440, 450
(1969) .
Moreover, in Thomas v.
Review Bd. of Indiana Employment Security Div., 450 U. S. 707
(1981) , we considered and rejected an argument that is nearly
identical to the one now urged by HHS and the dissent. In Thomas, a
Jehovah’s Witness was initially employed making sheet steel for a
variety of industrial uses, but he was later transferred to a job
making turrets for tanks. Id., at 710. Because he objected on
religious grounds to participating in the manufacture of weapons,
he lost his job and sought unemployment compensation. Ruling
against the em-ployee, the state court had difficulty with the line
thatthe employee drew between work that he found to be con-sistent
with his religious beliefs (helping to manufacture steel that was
used in making weapons) and work that he found morally
objectionable (helping to make the weapons themselves). This Court,
however, held that “it is not for us to say that the line he drew
was an unreasonable one.” Id., at 715.[
35]
Similarly, in these
cases, the Hahns and Greens and their companies sincerely believe
that providing the insurance coverage demanded by the HHS
regulations lies on the forbidden side of the line, and it is not
for us to say that their religious beliefs are mistaken or
insubstantial. Instead, our “narrow function . . . in
this context is to determine” whether the line drawn reflects “an
honest conviction,” id., at 716, and there is no dispute that it
does.
HHS nevertheless
compares these cases to decisions in which we rejected the argument
that the use of general tax revenue to subsidize the secular
activities of religious institutions violated the Free Exercise
Clause. See Tilton v. Richardson, 403 U. S. 672, 689 (1971)
(plurality); Board of Ed. of Central School Dist. No. 1 v. Allen,
392 U. S. 236 –249 (1968). But in those cases, while the
subsidies were clearly contrary to the challengers’ views on a
secular issue, namely, proper church-state relations, the
challengers never articulated a religious objection to the
subsidies. As we put it in Tilton, they were “unable to identify
any coercion directed at the practice or exercise of their
religious beliefs.” 403 U. S., at 689 (plurality opinion); see
Allen, supra, at 249 (“[A]ppellants have not contended that the New
York law in any way coerces them as individuals in the practice of
their religion”). Here, in contrast, the plaintiffs do assert that
funding the specific contraceptive methods at issue violates their
religious beliefs, and HHS does not question their sincerity.
Because the contraceptive mandate forces them to pay an enormous
sum of money—as much as $475 million per year in the case of Hobby
Lobby—if they insist on providing insurance coverage in accordance
with their religious beliefs, the mandate clearly imposes a
substantial burden on those beliefs.
V
Since the HHS
contraceptive mandate imposes a substantial burden on the exercise
of religion, we must move on and decide whether HHS has shown that
the mandate both “(1) is in furtherance of a compelling
governmental interest; and (2) is the least restrictive means of
furthering that compelling governmental interest.” 42
U. S. C. §2000bb–1(b).
A
HHS asserts that the
contraceptive mandate serves a variety of important interests, but
many of these are couched in very broad terms, such as promoting
“public health” and “gender equality.” Brief for HHS in No. 13–354,
at 46, 49. RFRA, however, contemplates a “more focused” inquiry: It
“requires the Government to demonstrate that the compelling
interest test is satisfied through application of the challenged
law ‘to the person’—the particular claimant whose sincere exercise
of religion is being substantially burdened.” O’Centro, 546
U. S., at 430–431 (quoting §2000bb–1(b)). This requires us to
“loo[k] beyond broadly formulated interests” and to “scrutiniz[e]
the asserted harm of granting specific exemptions to particular
religious claimants”—in other words, to look to the marginal
interest in enforcing the contraceptive mandate in these cases. O
Centro, supra, at 431.
In addition to
asserting these very broadly framed interests, HHS maintains that
the mandate serves a compelling interest in ensuring that all women
have access to all FDA-approved contraceptives without cost
sharing. See Brief for HHS in No. 13–354, at 14–15, 49; see Brief
for HHS in No. 13–356, at 10, 48. Under our cases, women (and men)
have a constitutional right to obtain contraceptives, see Griswold
v. Connecticut, 381 U. S. 479 –486 (1965), and HHS tells us
that “[s]tudies have demonstrated that even moderate copayments for
preventive services can deter patients from receiving those
services.” Brief for HHS in No. 13–354, at 50 (internal quotation
marks omitted).
The objecting parties
contend that HHS has not shown that the mandate serves a compelling
government interest, and it is arguable that there are features of
ACA that support that view. As we have noted, many employees—those
covered by grandfathered plans and those who work for employers
with fewer than 50 employees—may have no contraceptive coverage
without cost sharing at all.
HHS responds that many
legal requirements have exceptions and the existence of exceptions
does not in itself indicate that the principal interest served by a
law is not compelling. Even a compelling interest may be outweighed
in some circumstances by another even weightier consideration. In
these cases, however, the interest served by one of the biggest
exceptions, the exception for grandfathered plans, is simply the
interest of employers in avoiding the inconvenience of amending an
existing plan. Grandfathered plans are required “to comply with a
subset of the Affordable Care Act’s health reform provisions” that
provide what HHS has described as “particularly significant
protections.” 75 Fed. Reg. 34540 (2010). But the contraceptive
mandate is expressly excluded from this subset. Ibid.
We find it unnecessary
to adjudicate this issue. We will assume that the interest in
guaranteeing cost-free access to the four challenged contraceptive
methods is compelling within the meaning of RFRA, and we will
proceed to consider the final prong of the RFRA test, i.e., whether
HHS has shown that the contraceptive mandate is “the least
restrictive means of furthering that compelling governmental
interest.” §2000bb–1(b)(2).
B
The
least-restrictive-means standard is exceptionally demanding, see
City of Boerne, 521 U. S., at 532, and it is not satisfied
here. HHS has not shown that it lacks other means of achieving its
desired goal without imposing a substantial burden on the exercise
of religion by the objecting parties in these cases. See
§§2000bb–1(a), (b) (requiring the Government to “demonstrat[e] that
application of [a substantial] burden to the person . . .
is the least restrictive means of furthering [a] compelling
governmental interest” (emphasis added)).
The most
straightforward way of doing this would be for the Government to
assume the cost of providing the four contraceptives at issue to
any women who are unable to obtain them under their
health-insurance policies due to their employers’ religious
objections. This would certainly be less restrictive of the
plaintiffs’ religious liberty, and HHS has not shown, see
§2000bb–1(b)(2), that this is not a viable alternative. HHS has not
provided any estimate of the average cost per employee of providing
access tothese contraceptives, two of which, according to the FDA,
are designed primarily for emergency use. See Birth Control:
Medicines to Help You, online at
http://www.fda.gov/forconsumers/byaudience/forwomen/freepublications/ucm313215.htm.
Nor has HHS provided any statistics regarding the number of
employees who might be affected because they work for corporations
like Hobby Lobby, Conestoga, and Mardel. Nor has HHS told us that
it is unable to provide such statistics. It seems likely, however,
that the cost of providing the forms of contraceptives at issue in
these cases (if not all FDA-approved contraceptives) would be minor
when compared with the overall cost of ACA. According to one of the
Congressional Budget Office’s most recent forecasts, ACA’s
insurance-coverage provisions will cost the Federal Government more
than $1.3 trillion through the next decade. See CBO, Updated
Estimates of the Effects of the Insurance Coverage Provisions of
the Affordable Care Act, April 2014, p. 2.[
36] If, as HHS tells us, providing all women
with cost-free access to all FDA-approved methods of contraception
is a Government interest of the highest order, it is hard to
understand HHS’s argument that it cannot be required under RFRA to
pay anything in order to achieve this important goal.
HHS contends that RFRA
does not permit us to take this option into account because “RFRA
cannot be used to require creation of entirely new programs.” Brief
for HHS in 13–354, at 15.[
37] But we see nothing in RFRA that supports this
argument, and drawing the line between the “creation of an entirely
new program” and the modification of an existing program (which
RFRA surely allows) would be fraught with problems. We do not doubt
that cost may be an important factor in the least-restrictive-means
analysis, but both RFRA and its sister statute, RLUIPA, may in some
circumstances require the Government to expend additional funds to
accommodate citizens’ religious beliefs. Cf. §2000cc–3(c) (RLUIPA:
“[T]his chapter may require a government to incur expenses in its
own operations to avoid imposing a substantial burden on religious
exercise.”). HHS’s view that RFRA can never require the Government
to spend even a small amount reflects a judgment about the
importance of religious liberty that was not shared by the Congress
that enacted that law.
In the end, however, we
need not rely on the option of a new, government-funded program in
order to conclude that the HHS regulations fail the
least-restrictive-means test. HHS itself has demonstrated that it
has at its disposal an approach that is less restrictive than
requiring employers to fund contraceptive methods that violate
their religious beliefs. As we explained above, HHS has already
established an accommodation for nonprofit organizations with
religious objections. See supra, at 9–10, and nn. 8–9. Under
that accommodation, the organization can self-certify that it
opposes providing coverage for particular contraceptive services.
See 45 CFR §§147.131(b)(4), (c)(1); 26 CFR §§54.9815–2713A(a)(4),
(b). If the organization makes such a certification, the
organization’s insurance issuer or third-party administrator must
“[e]xpressly exclude contraceptive coverage from the group health
insurance coverage provided in connection with the group health
plan” and “[p]rovide separate payments for any contraceptive
services required to be covered” without imposing “any cost-sharing
requirements . . . on the eligible organization, the
group health plan, or plan participants or beneficiaries.” 45 CFR
§147.131(c)(2); 26 CFR §54.9815–2713A(c)(2).[
38]
We do not decide today
whether an approach of this type complies with RFRA for purposes of
all religious claims.[
39] At
a minimum, however, it does not impinge on the plaintiffs’
religious belief that providing insurance coverage for the
contraceptives at issue here violates their religion, and it serves
HHS’s stated interests equally well.[
40]
The principal dissent
identifies no reason why this accommodation would fail to protect
the asserted needs of women as effectively as the contraceptive
mandate, and there is none.[
41] Under the accommodation, the plaintiffs’ female
employees would continue to receive contraceptive coverage without
cost sharing for all FDA-approved contraceptives, and they would
continue to “face minimal logistical and administrative obstacles,”
post, at 28 (internal quotation marks omitted), because their
employers’ insurers would be responsible for providing information
and coverage, see, e.g., 45 CFR §§147.131(c)–(d); cf. 26 CFR
§§54.9815–2713A(b), (d). Ironically, it is the dissent’s approach
that would “[i]mped[e] women’s receipt of benefits by ‘requiring
them to take steps to learn about, and to sign up for, a new
government funded and administered health benefit,’ ” post, at
28, because the dissent would effectively compel religious
employers to drop health-insurance coverage altogether, leaving
their employees to find individual plans on government-run
exchanges or elsewhere. This is indeed “scarcely what Congress
contemplated.” Ibid.
C
HHS and the principal
dissent argue that a ruling in favor of the objecting parties in
these cases will lead to a flood of religious objections regarding
a wide variety of medical procedures and drugs, such as
vaccinations and blood transfusions, but HHS has made no effort to
substantiate this prediction.[
42] HHS points to no evidence that insurance plans in
existence prior to the enactment of ACA excluded coverage for such
items. Nor has HHS provided evidence that any significant number of
employers sought exemption, on religious grounds, from any of ACA’s
coverage requirements other than the contraceptive mandate.
It is HHS’s apparent
belief that no insurance-coverage mandate would violate RFRA—no
matter how significantly it impinges on the religious liberties of
employers—that would lead to intolerable consequences. Under HHS’s
view, RFRA would permit the Government to require all employers to
provide coverage for any medical procedure allowed by law in the
jurisdiction in question—for instance, third-trimester abortions or
assisted suicide. The owners of many closely held corporations
could not in good conscience provide such coverage, and thus HHS
would effectively exclude these people from full participation in
the economic life of the Nation. RFRA was enacted to prevent such
an outcome.
In any event, our
decision in these cases is concerned solely with the contraceptive
mandate. Our decision should not be understood to hold that an
insurance-coverage mandate must necessarily fall if it conflicts
with an employer’s religious beliefs. Other coverage requirements,
such as immunizations, may be supported by different interests (for
example, the need to combat the spread of infectious diseases) and
may involve different arguments about the least restrictive means
of providing them.
The principal dissent
raises the possibility that discrimination in hiring, for example
on the basis of race, might be cloaked as religious practice to
escape legal sanction. See post, at 32–33. Our decision today
provides no such shield. The Government has a compelling interest
in providing an equal opportunity to participate in the workforce
without regard to race, and prohibitions on racial discrimination
are precisely tailored to achieve that critical goal.
HHS also raises for the
first time in this Court the argument that applying the
contraceptive mandate to for-profit employers with sincere
religious objections is essential to the comprehensive
health-insurance scheme that ACA establishes. HHS analogizes the
contraceptive mandate to the requirement to pay Social Security
taxes, which we upheld in Lee despite the religious objection of an
employer, but these cases are quite different. Our holding in Lee
turned primarily on the special problems associated with a national
system of taxation. We noted that “[t]he obligation to pay the
social security tax initially is not fundamentally different from
the obligation to pay income taxes.” 455 U. S., at 260. Based
on that premise, we explained that it was untenable to allow
individuals to seek exemptions from taxes based on religious
objections to particular Government expenditures: “If, for example,
a religious adherent believes war is a sin, and if a certain
percentage of the federal budget can be identified as devoted to
war-related activities, such individuals would have a similarly
valid claim to be exempt from paying that percentage of the income
tax.” Ibid. We observed that “[t]he tax system could not function
if denominations were allowed to challenge the tax system because
tax payments were spent in a manner that violates their religious
belief.” Ibid.; see O Centro, 546 U. S., at 435.
Lee was a
free-exercise, not a RFRA, case, but if the issue in Lee were
analyzed under the RFRA framework, the fundamental point would be
that there simply is no less restrictive alternative to the
categorical requirement to pay taxes. Because of the enormous
variety of government expenditures funded by tax dollars, allowing
tax-payers to withhold a portion of their tax obligations on
religious grounds would lead to chaos. Recognizingexemptions from
the contraceptive mandate is very different. ACA does not create a
large national pool of tax revenue for use in purchasing healthcare
coverage. Rather, individual employers like the plaintiffs purchase
insurance for their own employees. And contrary to the principal
dissent’s characterization, the employers’ contributions do not
necessarily funnel into “undifferentiated funds.” Post, at 23. The
accommodation established by HHS requires issuers to have a
mechanism by which to “segregate premium revenue collected from the
eligible organization from the monies used to provide payments for
contraceptive services.” 45 CFR §147.131(c)(2)(ii). Recognizing a
religious accommodation under RFRA for particular coverage
requirements, therefore, does not threaten the viability of ACA’s
comprehensive scheme in the way that recognizing religious
objections to particular expenditures from general tax revenues
would.[
43]
In its final pages, the
principal dissent reveals that its fundamental objection to the
claims of the plaintiffs is an objection to RFRA itself. The
dissent worries about forcing the federal courts to apply RFRA to a
host of claims made by litigants seeking a religious exemption from
generally applicable laws, and the dissent expresses a desire to
keep the courts out of this business. See post, at 32–35. In making
this plea, the dissent reiterates a point made forcefully by the
Court in Smith. 494 U. S., at 888–889 (applying the Sherbert
test to all free-exercise claims “would open the prospect of
constitutionally required religious exemptions from civic
obligations of almost every conceivable kind”). But Congress, in
enacting RFRA, took the position that “the compelling interest test
as set forth in prior Federal court rulings is a workable test
forstriking sensible balances between religious liberty and
competing prior governmental interests.” 42 U. S. C.
§2000bb(a)(5). The wisdom of Congress’s judgment on this matter is
not our concern. Our responsibility is to enforce RFRA as written,
and under the standard that RFRA prescribes, the HHS contraceptive
mandate is unlawful.
* * *
The contraceptive
mandate, as applied to closely held corporations, violates RFRA.
Our decision on that statutory question makes it unnecessary to
reach the First Amendment claim raised by Conestoga and the
Hahns.
The judgment of the
Tenth Circuit in No. 13–354 is affirmed; the judgment of the Third
Circuit in No. 13–356 is reversed, and that case is remanded for
further proceedings consistent with this opinion.
It is so ordered.