NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the
United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter
of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Washington,
D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in
order that corrections may be made before the preliminary print
goes to press.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 12–1168
_________________
ELEANOR McCULLEN, et al., PETITIONERS v.
MARTHA COAKLEY, ATTORNEY GEN-ERAL of MASSACHUSETTS, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the first circuit
[June 26, 2014]
Chief Justice Roberts
delivered the opinion of the Court.
A Massachusetts statute
makes it a crime to knowingly stand on a “public way or sidewalk”
within 35 feet of an entrance or driveway to any place, other than
a hospital, where abortions are performed. Mass. Gen. Laws, ch.
266, §§120E½(a), (b) (West 2012). Petitioners are individuals who
approach and talk to women outside such facilities, attempting to
dissuade them from having abortions. The statute prevents
petitioners from doing so near the facilities’ entrances. The
question presented is whether the statute violates the First
Amendment.
I
A
In 2000, the
Massachusetts Legislature enacted the Massachusetts Reproductive
Health Care Facilities Act, Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 266, §120E½ (West
2000). The law was designed to address clashes between abortion
opponents and advocates of abortion rights that were occurring
outside clinics where abortions were performed. The Act established
a defined area with an 18-foot radius around the entrances and
driveways of such facilities. §120E½(b). Anyone could enter that
area, but once within it, no one (other than certain exempt
individuals) could knowingly approach within six feet of another
person—unless that person consented—“for the purpose of passing a
leaflet or handbill to, displaying a sign to, or engaging in oral
protest, education, or counseling with such other person.” Ibid. A
separate provision subjected to criminal punishment anyone who
“knowingly obstructs, detains, hinders, impedes or blocks another
person’s entry to or exit from a reproductive health care
facility.” §120E½(e).
The statute was modeled
on a similar Colorado law that this Court had upheld in Hill v.
Colorado, 530 U. S. 703 (2000) . Relying on Hill, the United
States Court of Appeals for the First Circuit sustained the
Massachusetts statute against a First Amendment challenge. McGuire
v. Reilly, 386 F. 3d 45 (2004) (McGuire II), cert. denied, 544
U. S. 974 (2005) ; McGuire v. Reilly, 260 F. 3d 36 (2001)
(McGuire I).
By 2007, some
Massachusetts legislators and law enforcement officials had come to
regard the 2000 statute as inadequate. At legislative hearings,
multiple witnesses recounted apparent violations of the law.
Massachusetts Attorney General Martha Coakley, for example,
testified that protestors violated the statute “on a routine
basis.” App. 78. To illustrate this claim, she played a video
depicting protestors approaching patients and clinic staff within
the buffer zones, ostensibly without the latter individuals’
consent. Clinic employees and volunteers also testified that
protestors congregated near the doors and in the driveways of the
clinics, with the result that prospective patients occasionally
retreated from the clinics rather than try to make their way to the
clinic entrances or parking lots.
Captain William B.
Evans of the Boston Police Department, however, testified that his
officers had made “no more than five or so arrests” at the Planned
Parenthood clinic in Boston and that what few prosecutions had been
brought were unsuccessful. Id., at 68–69. Witnesses attributed the
dearth of enforcement to the difficulty of policing the six-foot
no-approach zones. Captain Evans testified that the 18-foot zones
were so crowded with protestors that they resembled “a goalie’s
crease,” making it hard to determine whether a protestor had
deliberately approached a patient or, if so, whether the patient
had consented. Id., at 69–71. For similar reasons, Attorney General
Coakley concluded that the six-foot no-approach zones were
“unenforceable.” Id., at 79. What the police needed, she said, was
a fixed buffer zone around clinics that protestors could not enter.
Id., at 74, 76. Captain Evans agreed, explaining that such a zone
would “make our job so much easier.” Id., at 68.
To address these
concerns, the Massachusetts Legislature amended the statute in
2007, replacing the six-foot no-approach zones (within the 18-foot
area) with a 35-foot fixed buffer zone from which individuals are
categorically excluded. The statute now provides:
“No person shall knowingly enter or remain
on a public way or sidewalk adjacent to a reproductive health care
facility within a radius of 35 feet of any portion of an entrance,
exit or driveway of a reproductive health care facility or within
the area within a rectangle created by extending the outside
boundaries of any entrance, exit or driveway of a reproductive
health care facility in straight lines to the point where such
lines intersect the sideline of the street in front of such
entrance, exit or driveway.” Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 266, §120E½(b)
(West 2012).
A “reproductive health care facility,” in turn,
is defined as “a place, other than within or upon the grounds of a
hospital, where abortions are offered or performed.” §120E½(a).
The 35-foot buffer zone
applies only “during a facility’s business hours,” and the area
must be “clearly marked and posted.” §120E½(c). In practice,
facilities typically mark the zones with painted arcs and posted
signs on adjacent sidewalks and streets. A first violation of the
statute is punishable by a fine of up to $500, up to three months
in prison, or both, while a subsequent offense is punishable by a
fine of between $500 and $5,000, up to two and a half years in
prison, or both. §120E½(d).
The Act exempts four
classes of individuals: (1) “persons entering or leaving such
facility”; (2) “employees or agents of such facility acting within
the scope of their employment”; (3) “law enforcement, ambulance,
firefighting, construction, utilities, public works and other
municipal agents acting within the scope of their employment”; and
(4) “persons using the public sidewalk or street right-of-way
adjacent to such facility solely for the purposeof reaching a
destination other than such facility.” §120E½(b)(1)–(4). The
legislature also retained the separate provision from the 2000
version that proscribes the knowing obstruction of access to a
facility. §120E½(e).
B
Some of the
individuals who stand outside Massachusetts abortion clinics are
fairly described as protestors, who express their moral or
religious opposition to abortion through signs and chants or, in
some cases, more aggressive methods such as face-to-face
confrontation. Petitioners take a different tack. They attempt to
engage women approaching the clinics in what they call “sidewalk
counseling,” which involves offering information about alternatives
to abortion and help pursuing those options. Petitioner Eleanor
McCullen, for instance, will typically initiate a conversation this
way: “Good morning, may I give you my literature? Is there anything
I can do for you? I’m available if you have any questions.” App.
138. If the woman seems receptive, McCullen will provide additional
information. McCullen and the other petitioners consider it
essential to maintain a caring demeanor, a calm tone of voice, and
direct eye contact during these exchanges. Such interactions,
petitioners believe, are a much more effective means of dissuading
women from having abortions than confrontational methods such as
shouting or brandishing signs, which in petitioners’ view tend only
to antagonize their intended audience. In unrefuted testimony,
petitioners say they have collectively persuaded hundreds of women
to forgo abortions.
The buffer zones have
displaced petitioners from their previous positions outside the
clinics. McCullen offers counseling outside a Planned Parenthood
clinic in Boston, as do petitioners Jean Zarrella and Eric Cadin.
Petitioner Gregory Smith prays the rosary there. The clinic
occupies its own building on a street corner. Its main door is
recessed into an open foyer, approximately 12 feet back from the
public sidewalk. Before the Act was amended to create the buffer
zones, petitioners stood near the entryway to the foyer. Now a
buffer zone—marked by a painted arc and a sign—surrounds the
entrance. This zone extends 23 feet down the sidewalk in one
direction, 26 feet in the other, and outward just one foot short of
the curb. The clinic’s entrance adds another seven feet to the
width of the zone. Id., at 293–295. The upshot is that petitioners
are effectively excluded from a 56-foot-wide expanse of the public
sidewalk in front of the clinic.[
1]
Petitioners Mark
Bashour and Nancy Clark offer counseling and information outside a
Planned Parenthood clinic in Worcester. Unlike the Boston clinic,
the Worcester clinic sits well back from the public street and
sidewalks. Patients enter the clinic in one of two ways. Those
arriving on foot turn off the public sidewalk and walk down a
nearly 54-foot-long private walkway to the main entrance. More than
85% of patients, however, arrive by car, turning onto the clinic’s
driveway from the street, parking in a private lot, and walking to
the main entrance on a private walkway.
Bashour and Clark would
like to stand where the private walkway or driveway intersects the
sidewalk and offer leaflets to patients as they walk or drive by.
But a painted arc extends from the private walkway 35 feet down the
sidewalk in either direction and outward nearly to the curb on the
opposite side of the street. Another arc surrounds the driveway’s
entrance, covering more than 93 feet of the sidewalk (including the
width of the driveway) and extending across the street and nearly
six feet onto the sidewalk on the opposite side. Id., at 295–297.
Bashour and Clark must now stand either some distance down the
sidewalk from the private walkway and driveway or across the
street.
Petitioner Cyril Shea
stands outside a Planned Parenthood clinic in Springfield, which,
like the Worcester clinic, is set back from the public streets.
Approximately 90% of patients arrive by car and park in the private
lots surrounding the clinic. Shea used to position himself at an
entrance to one of the five driveways leading to the parking lots.
Painted arcs now surround the entrances, each spanning
approximately 100 feet of the sidewalk parallel to the street
(again, including the width of the driveways) and extending outward
well into the street. Id., at 297–299. Like petitioners at the
Worcester clinic, Shea now stands far down the sidewalk from the
driveway entrances.
Petitioners at all
three clinics claim that the buffer zones have considerably
hampered their counseling efforts. Although they have managed to
conduct some counseling and to distribute some literature outside
the buffer zones—particularly at the Boston clinic—they say they
have had many fewer conversations and distributed many fewer
leaflets since the zones went into effect. Id., at 136–137, 180,
200.
The second statutory
exemption allows clinic employees and agents acting within the
scope of their employment to enter the buffer zones. Relying on
this exemption, the Boston clinic uses “escorts” to greet women as
they approach the clinic, accompanying them through the zones to
the clinic entrance. Petitioners claim that the escorts sometimes
thwart petitioners’ attempts to communicate with patients by
blocking petitioners from handing literature to patients, telling
patients not to “pay any attention” or “listen to” petitioners, and
disparaging petitioners as “crazy.” Id., at 165, 178.
C
In January 2008,
petitioners sued Attorney General Coakley and other Commonwealth
officials. They sought to enjoin enforcement of the Act, alleging
that it violates the First and Fourteenth Amendments, both on its
face and as applied to them. The District Court denied petitioners’
facial challenge after a bench trial based on a stipulated record.
573 F. Supp. 2d 382 (Mass. 2008).
The Court of Appeals
for the First Circuit affirmed. 571 F. 3d 167 (2009). Relying
extensively on its previous decisions upholding the 2000 version of
the Act, see McGuire II, 386 F. 3d 45; McGuire I, 260
F. 3d 36, the court upheld the 2007 version as a reasonable
“time, place, and manner” regulation under the test set forth in
Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781 (1989) . 571
F. 3d, at 174–181. It also rejected petitioners’ arguments
that the Act was substantially overbroad, void for vagueness, and
an impermissible prior restraint. Id., at 181–184.
The case then returned
to the District Court, which held that the First Circuit’s decision
foreclosed all but one of petitioners’ as-applied challenges. 759
F. Supp. 2d 133 (2010). After another bench trial, it denied
the remain-ing as-applied challenge, finding that the Act left
petitioners ample alternative channels of communication. 844
F. Supp. 2d 206 (2012). The Court of Appeals once again
affirmed. 708 F. 3d 1 (2013).
We granted certiorari.
570 U. S. ___ (2013).
II
By its very terms,
the Massachusetts Act regulates access to “public way[s]” and
“sidewalk[s].” Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 266, §120E½(b) (Supp. 2007).
Such areas occupy a “special position in terms of First Amendment
protection” because of their historic role as sites for discussion
and debate. United States v. Grace, 461 U. S. 171, 180 (1983)
. These places—which we have labeled “traditional public
fora”—“ ‘have immemorially been held in trust for the use of
the public and, time out of mind, have been used for purposes of
assembly, communicating thoughts between citizens, and discussing
public questions.’ ” Pleasant Grove City v. Summum, 555
U. S. 460, 469 (2009) (quoting Perry Ed. Assn. v. Perry Local
Educators’ Assn., 460 U. S. 37, 45 (1983) ).
It is no accident that
public streets and sidewalks have developed as venues for the
exchange of ideas. Even today, they remain one of the few places
where a speaker can be confident that he is not simply preaching to
the choir. With respect to other means of communication, an
individual confronted with an uncomfortable message can always turn
the page, change the channel, or leave the Web site. Not so on
public streets and sidewalks. There, a listener often encounters
speech he might otherwise tune out. In light of the First
Amendment’s purpose “to preserve an uninhibited marketplace of
ideas in which truth will ultimately prevail,” FCC v. League of
Women Voters of Cal., 468 U. S. 364, 377 (1984) (internal
quotation marks omitted), this aspect of traditional public fora is
a virtue, not a vice.
In short, traditional
public fora are areas that have historically been open to the
public for speech activities. Thus, even though the Act says
nothing about speech on its face, there is no doubt—and respondents
do not dispute—that it restricts access to traditional public fora
and is therefore subject to First Amendment scrutiny. See Brief for
Respondents 26 (although “[b]y its terms, the Act regulates only
conduct,” it “incidentally regulates the place and time of
protected speech”).
Consistent with the
traditionally open character of public streets and sidewalks, we
have held that the government’s ability to restrict speech in such
locations is “very limited.” Grace, supra, at 177. In particular,
the guiding First Amendment principle that the “government has no
power to restrict expression because of its message, its ideas, its
subject matter, or its content” applies with full force in a
traditional public forum. Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley, 408
U. S. 92, 95 (1972) . As a general rule, in such a forum the
government may not “selectively . . . shield the public
from some kinds of speech on the ground that they are more
offensive than others.” Erznoznik v. Jacksonville, 422 U. S.
205, 209 (1975) .
We have, however,
afforded the government somewhat wider leeway to regulate features
of speech unrelated to its content. “[E]ven in a public forum the
government may impose reasonable restrictions on the time, place,
or manner of protected speech, provided the restrictions ‘are
justified without reference to the content of the regulated speech,
that they are narrowly tailored to serve a significant governmental
interest, and that they leave open ample alternative channels for
communication of the information.’ ” Ward, 491 U. S., at
791 (quoting Clark v. Community for Creative Non-Violence, 468
U. S. 288, 293 (1984) ).[
2]
While the parties agree
that this test supplies theproper framework for assessing the
constitutionality of the Massachusetts Act, they disagree about
whether the Act satisfies the test’s three requirements.
III
Petitioners contend
that the Act is not content neutral for two independent reasons:
First, they argue that it discriminates against abortion-related
speech because it establishes buffer zones only at clinics that
perform abortions. Second, petitioners contend that the Act, by
exempting clinic employees and agents, favors one viewpoint about
abortion over the other. If either of these arguments is correct,
then the Act must satisfy strict scrutiny—that is, it must be the
least restrictive means of achieving a compelling state interest.
See United States v. Playboy Entertainment Group, Inc., 529
U. S. 803, 813 (2000) . Respondents do not argue that the Act
can survive this exacting standard.
Justice Scalia objects
to our decision to consider whether the statute is content based
and thus subject to strict scrutiny, given that we ultimately
conclude that it is not narrowly tailored. Post, at 2 (opinion
concurring in judgment). But we think it unexceptional to perform
the first part of a multipart constitutional analysis first. The
content-neutrality prong of the Ward test is logically antecedent
to the narrow-tailoring prong, because it determines the
appropriate level of scrutiny. It is not unusual for the Court to
proceed sequentially in applying a constitutional test, even when
the preliminary steps turn out not to be dispositive. See, e.g.,
Bartnicki v. Vopper, 532 U. S. 514 –527 (2001); Holder v.
Humanitarian Law Project, 561 U. S. 1 –28 (2010) (concluding
that a law was content based even though it ultimately survived
strict scrutiny).
The Court does
sometimes assume, without deciding, that a law is subject to a less
stringent level of scrutiny, as we did earlier this Term in
McCutcheon v. Federal Election Commission, 572 U. S. ___, ___
(2014) (plurality opinion) (slip op., at 10). But the distinction
between that case and this one seems clear: Applying any standard
of review other than intermediate scrutiny in McCutcheon—the
standard that was assumed to apply—would have required overruling a
precedent. There is no similar reason to forgo the ordinary order
of operations in this case.
At the same time, there
is good reason to address content neutrality. In discussing whether
the Act is narrowly tailored, see Part IV, infra, we identify a
number of less-restrictive alternative measures that the
Massachusetts Legislature might have adopted. Some apply only at
abortion clinics, which raises the question whether those
provisions are content neutral. See infra, at 12–15. While we need
not (and do not) endorse any of those measures, it would be odd to
consider them as possible alternatives if they were presumptively
unconstitutional because they were content based and thus subject
to strict scrutiny.
A
The Act applies only
at a “reproductive health care facility,” defined as “a place,
other than within or upon the grounds of a hospital, where
abortions are offered or performed.” Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 266,
§120E½(a). Given this definition, petitioners argue, “virtually all
speech affected by the Act is speech concerning abortion,” thus
rendering the Act content based. Brief for Petitioners 23.
We disagree. To begin,
the Act does not draw content-based distinctions on its face.
Contrast Boos v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312, 315 (1988) (ordinance
prohibiting the display within 500 feet of a foreign embassy of any
sign that tends to bring the foreign government into “ ‘public
odium’ ” or “ ‘public disrepute’ ”); Carey v. Brown,
447 U. S. 455, 465 (1980) (statute prohibiting all residential
picketing except “peaceful labor picketing”). The Act would be
content based if it required “enforcement authorities” to “examine
the content of the message that is conveyed to determine whether” a
violation has occurred. League of Women Voters of Cal., supra, at
383. But it does not. Whether petitioners violate the Act “depends”
not “on what they say,” Humanitarian Law Project, supra, at 27, but
simply on where they say it. Indeed, petitioners can violate the
Act merely by standing in a buffer zone, without displaying a sign
or uttering a word.
It is true, of course,
that by limiting the buffer zones to abortion clinics, the Act has
the “inevitable effect” of restricting abortion-related speech more
than speech on other subjects. Brief for Petitioners 24 (quoting
United States v. O’Brien, 391 U. S. 367, 384 (1968) ). But a
facially neutral law does not become content based simply be-cause
it may disproportionately affect speech on certain topics. On the
contrary, “[a] regulation that serves purposes unrelated to the
content of expression is deemed neutral, even if it has an
incidental effect on some speakers or messages but not others.”
Ward, supra, at 791. The question in such a case is whether the law
is “ ‘justified without reference to the content of the
regulated speech.’ ” Renton v. Playtime Theatres, Inc., 475
U. S. 41, 48 (1986) (quoting Virginia Pharmacy Board v.
Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, Inc., 425 U. S. 748, 771
(1976) ; emphasis deleted).
The Massachusetts Act
is. Its stated purpose is to “increase forthwith public safety at
reproductive health care facilities.” 2007 Mass. Acts p. 660.
Respondents have articulated similar purposes before this
Court—namely, “public safety, patient access to healthcare, and the
unobstructed use of public sidewalks and roadways.” Brief for
Respondents 27; see, e.g., App. 51 (testimony of Attorney General
Coakley); id., at 67–70 (testimony of Captain William B. Evans of
the Boston Police); id., at 79–80 (testimony of Mary Beth
Heffernan, Undersecretary for Criminal Justice); id., at 122–124
(affidavit of Captain Evans). It is not the case that “[e]very
objective indication shows that the provision’s primary purpose is
to restrict speech that opposes abortion.” Post, at 7.
We have previously
deemed the foregoing concerns to be content neutral. See Boos, 485
U. S., at 321 (identifying “congestion,” “interference with
ingress or egress,” and “the need to protect . . .
security” as content-neutral concerns). Obstructed access and
congested sidewalks are problems no matter what caused them. A
group of individuals can obstruct clinic access and clog sidewalks
just as much when they loiter as when they protest abortion or
counsel patients.
To be clear, the Act
would not be content neutral if it were concerned with undesirable
effects that arise from “the direct impact of speech on its
audience” or “[l]isteners’ reactions to speech.” Ibid. If, for
example, the speech outside Massachusetts abortion clinics caused
offense or made listeners uncomfortable, such offense or discomfort
would not give the Commonwealth a content-neutral justification to
restrict the speech. All of the problems identified by the
Commonwealth here, however, arise irrespective of any listener’s
reactions. Whether or not a single person reacts to abortion
protestors’ chants or petitioners’ counseling, large crowds outside
abortion clinics can still compromise public safety, impede access,
and obstruct sidewalks.
Petitioners do not
really dispute that the Commonwealth’s interests in ensuring safety
and preventing obstruction are, as a general matter, content
neutral. But petitioners note that these interests “apply outside
every building in the State that hosts any activity that might
occasion protest or comment,” not just abortion clinics. Brief for
Petitioners 24. By choosing to pursue these interests only at
abortion clinics, petitioners argue, the Massachusetts Legislature
evinced a purpose to “single[ ] out for regulation speech about one
particular topic: abortion.” Reply Brief 9.
We cannot infer such a
purpose from the Act’s limited scope. The broad reach of a statute
can help confirm that it was not enacted to burden a narrower
category of disfavored speech. See Kagan, Private Speech, Public
Purpose: The Role of Governmental Motive in First Amendment
Doctrine, 63 U. Chi. L. Rev. 413, 451–452 (1996). At the same
time, however, “States adopt laws to address the problems that
confront them. The First Amendment does not require States to
regulate for problems that do not exist.” Burson v. Freeman, 504
U. S. 191, 207 (1992) (plurality opinion). The Massachusetts
Legislature amended the Act in 2007 in response to a problem that
was, in its experience, limited to abortion clinics. There was a
record of crowding, obstruction, and even violence outside such
clinics. There were apparently no similar recurring problems
associated with other kinds of healthcare facilities, let alone
with “every building in the State that hosts any activity that
might occasion protest or comment.” Brief for Petitioners 24. In
light of the limited nature of the problem, it was reasonable for
the Massachusetts Legislature to enact a limited solution. When
selecting among various options for combating a particular problem,
legislatures should be encouraged to choose the one that restricts
less speech, not more.
Justice Scalia objects
that the statute does restrict more speech than necessary, because
“only one [Massachusetts abortion clinic] is known to have been
beset by the problems that the statute supposedly addresses.” Post,
at 7. But there are no grounds for inferring content-based
discrimination here simply because the legislature acted with
respect to abortion facilities generally rather than proceeding on
a facility-by-facility basis. On these facts, the poor fit noted by
Justice Scalia goes to the question of narrow tailoring, which we
consider below. See infra, at 26–28.
B
Petitioners also
argue that the Act is content based because it exempts four classes
of individuals, Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 266, §§120E½(b)(1)–(4), one of
which comprises “employees or agents of [a reproductive healthcare]
facil-ity acting within the scope of their employment.”
§120E½(b)(2). This exemption, petitioners say, favors one side in
the abortion debate and thus constitutes viewpoint
discrimination—an “egregious form of content discrimination,”
Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U. S.
819, 829 (1995) . In particular, petitioners argue that the
exemption allows clinic employees and agents—including the
volunteers who “escort” patients arriving at the Boston clinic—to
speak inside the buffer zones.
It is of course true
that “an exemption from an otherwise permissible regulation of
speech may represent a governmental ‘attempt to give one side of a
debatable public question an advantage in expressing its views to
the people.’ ” City of Ladue v. Gilleo, 512 U. S. 43, 51
(1994) (quoting First Nat. Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435
U. S. 765 –786 (1978)). At least on the record before us,
however, the statutory exemption for clinic employees and agents
acting within the scope of their employment does not appear to be
such an attempt.
There is nothing
inherently suspect about providing some kind of exemption to allow
individuals who work at the clinics to enter or remain within the
buffer zones. In particular, the exemption cannot be regarded as
simply a carve-out for the clinic escorts; it also covers employees
such as the maintenance worker shoveling a snowy sidewalk or the
security guard patrolling a clinic entrance, see App. 95 (affidavit
of Michael T. Baniukiewicz).
Given the need for an
exemption for clinic employees, the “scope of their employment”
qualification simply ensures that the exemption is limited to its
purpose of allowing the employees to do their jobs. It performs the
same function as the identical “scope of their employment”
restriction on the exemption for “law enforcement, ambulance,
fire-fighting, construction, utilities, public works and other
municipal agents.” §120E½(b)(3). Contrary to the suggestion of
Justice Scalia, post, at 11–12, there is little reason to suppose
that the Massachusetts Legislature intended to incorporate a common
law doctrine developed for determining vicarious liability in tort
when it used the phrase “scope of their employment” for the wholly
different purpose of defining the scope of an exemption to a
criminal statute. The limitation instead makes clear—with respect
to both clinic employees and municipal agents—that exempted
individuals are allowed inside the zones only to perform those acts
authorized by their employers. There is no suggestion in the record
that any of the clinics authorize their employees to speak about
abortion in the buffer zones. The “scope of their employment”
limitation thus seems designed to protect against exactly the sort
of conduct that petitioners and Justice Scalia fear.
Petitioners did testify
in this litigation about instances in which escorts at the Boston
clinic had expressed views about abortion to the women they were
accompanying, thwarted petitioners’ attempts to speak and hand
literature to the women, and disparaged petitioners in various
ways. See App. 165, 168–169, 177–178, 189–190. It is unclear from
petitioners’ testimony whether these alleged incidents occurred
within the buffer zones. There is no viewpoint discrimination
problem if the incidents occurred outside the zones because
petitioners are equally free to say whatever they would like in
that area.
Even assuming the
incidents occurred inside the zones, the record does not suggest
that they involved speech within the scope of the escorts’
employment. If the speech was beyond the scope of their employment,
then each of the alleged incidents would violate the Act’s express
terms. Petitioners’ complaint would then be that the police were
failing to enforce the Act equally against clinic escorts. Cf. Hoye
v. City of Oakland, 653 F. 3d 835, 849–852 (CA9 2011) (finding
selective enforcement of a similar ordinance in Oakland,
California). While such allegations might state a claim of official
viewpoint discrimination, that would not go to the validity of the
Act. In any event, petitioners nowhere allege selective
enforcement.
It would be a very
different question if it turned out that a clinic authorized
escorts to speak about abortion inside the buffer zones. See post,
at 1–2 (Alito, J., concurring in judgment). In that case, the
escorts would not seem to be violating the Act because the speech
would be within the scope of their employment.[
3] The Act’s exemption for clinic employees would
then facilitate speech on only one side of the abortion debate—a
clear form of viewpoint discrimination that would support an
as-applied challenge to the buffer zone at that clinic. But the
record before us contains insufficient evidence to show that the
exemption operates in this way at any of the clinics, perhaps
because the clinics do not want to doom the Act by allowing their
employees to speak about abortion within the buffer zones.[
4]
We thus conclude that
the Act is neither content nor viewpoint based and therefore need
not be analyzed under strict scrutiny.
IV
Even though the Act
is content neutral, it still must be “narrowly tailored to serve a
significant governmental interest.” Ward, 491 U. S., at 796
(internal quotation marks omitted). The tailoring requirement does
not sim-ply guard against an impermissible desire to censor. The
government may attempt to suppress speech not only because it
disagrees with the message being expressed, but also for mere
convenience. Where certain speech is associated with particular
problems, silencing the speech is sometimes the path of least
resistance. But by demanding a close fit between ends and means,
the tailoring requirement prevents the government from too readily
“sacrific[ing] speech for efficiency.” Riley v. National Federation
of Blind of N. C., Inc., 487 U. S. 781, 795 (1988) .
For a content-neutral
time, place, or manner regulation to be narrowly tailored, it must
not “burden substantially more speech than is necessary to further
the government’s legitimate interests.” Ward, 491 U. S., at
799. Such a regulation, unlike a content-based restriction of
speech, “need not be the least restrictive or least intrusive means
of” serving the government’s interests. Id., at 798. But the
government still “may not regulate expression in such a manner that
a substantial portion of the burden on speech does not serve to
advance its goals.” Id., at 799.
A
As noted, respondents
claim that the Act promotes “public safety, patient access to
healthcare, and the unobstructed use of public sidewalks and
roadways.” Brief for Respondents 27. Petitioners do not dispute the
significance of these interests. We have, moreover, previously
recognized the legitimacy of the government’s interests in
“ensuring public safety and order, promoting the free flow of
traffic on streets and sidewalks, protecting property rights, and
protecting a woman’s freedom to seek pregnancy-related services.”
Schenck v. Pro-Choice Network ofWestern N. Y., 519 U. S. 357,
376 (1997) . See also Madsen v. Women’s Health Center, Inc., 512
U. S. 753 –768 (1994). The buffer zones clearly serve these
interests.
At the same time, the
buffer zones impose serious burdens on petitioners’ speech. At each
of the three Planned Parenthood clinics where petitioners attempt
to counsel patients, the zones carve out a significant portion of
the adjacent public sidewalks, pushing petitioners well back from
the clinics’ entrances and driveways. The zones thereby compromise
petitioners’ ability to initiate the close, personal conversations
that they view as essential to “sidewalk counseling.”
For example, in
uncontradicted testimony, McCullen explained that she often cannot
distinguish patients from passersby outside the Boston clinic in
time to initiate a conversation before they enter the buffer zone.
App. 135. And even when she does manage to begin a discussion
outside the zone, she must stop abruptly at its painted border,
which she believes causes her to appear “untrustworthy” or
“suspicious.” Id., at 135, 152. Given these limitations, McCullen
is often reduced to raising her voice at patients from outside the
zone—a mode of communication sharply at odds with the compassionate
message she wishes to convey. Id., at 133, 152–153. Clark gave
similar testimony about her experience at the Worcester clinic.
Id., at 243–244.
These burdens on
petitioners’ speech have clearly taken their toll. Although
McCullen claims that she has persuaded about 80 women not to
terminate their pregnancies since the 2007 amendment, App. to Pet.
for Cert. 42a, she also says that she reaches “far fewer people”
than she did before the amendment, App. 137. Zarrella reports an
even more precipitous decline in her success rate: She estimated
having about 100 successful interactions over the years before the
2007 amendment, but not a single one since. Id., at 180. And as for
the Worcester clinic, Clark testified that “only one woman out of
100 will make the effort to walk across [the street] to speak with
[her].” Id., at 217.
The buffer zones have
also made it substantially more difficult for petitioners to
distribute literature to arriving patients. As explained, because
petitioners in Boston cannot readily identify patients before they
enter the zone, they often cannot approach them in time to place
literature near their hands—the most effective means of getting the
patients to accept it. Id., at 179. In Worcester and Springfield,
the zones have pushed petitioners so far back from the clinics’
driveways that they can no longer even attempt to offer literature
as drivers turn into the parking lots. Id., at 213, 218, 252–253.
In short, the Act operates to deprive petitioners of their two
primary methods of communicating with patients.
The Court of Appeals
and respondents are wrong to downplay these burdens on petitioners’
speech. As the Court of Appeals saw it, the Constitution does not
accord “special protection” to close conversations or
“handbilling.” 571 F. 3d, at 180. But while the First
Amendment does not guarantee a speaker the right to any particular
form of expression, some forms—such as normal conversation and
leafletting on a public sidewalk—have historically been more
closely associated with the transmission of ideas than others.
In the context of
petition campaigns, we have observed that “one-on-one
communication” is “the most effective, fundamental, and perhaps
economical avenue of political discourse.” Meyer v. Grant, 486
U. S. 414, 424 (1988) . See also Schenck, supra, at 377
(invalidating a “floating” buffer zone around people entering an
abortion clinic partly on the ground that it prevented protestors
“from communicating a message from a normal conversational distance
or handing leaflets to people entering or leaving the clinics who
are walking on the public sidewalks”). And “handing out leaflets in
the advocacy of a politically controversial viewpoint
. . . is the essence of First Amendment expression”;
“[n]o form of speech is entitled to greater constitutional
protection.” McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Comm’n, 514 U. S. 334,
347 (1995) . See also Schenck, supra, at 377 (“Leafletting and
commenting on matters of public concern are classic forms of speech
that lie at the heart of the First Amendment”). When the government
makes it more difficult to engage in these modes of communication,
it imposes an especially significant First Amendment
burden.[
5]
Respondents also
emphasize that the Act does not prevent petitioners from engaging
in various forms of “protest”—such as chanting slogans and
displaying signs—outside the buffer zones. Brief for Respondents
50–54. That misses the point. Petitioners are not protestors. They
seek not merely to express their opposition to abortion, but to
inform women of various alternatives and to provide help in
pursuing them. Petitioners believe that they can accomplish this
objective only through personal, caring, consensual conversations.
And for good reason: It is easier to ignore a strained voice or a
waving hand than a direct greeting or an outstretched arm. While
the record indicates that petitioners have been able to have a
number of quiet conversations outside the buffer zones, respondents
have not refuted petitioners’ testimony that the conversations have
been far less frequent and far less successful since the buffer
zones were instituted. It is thus no answer to say that petitioners
can still be “seen and heard” by women within the buffer zones.
Id., at 51–53. If all that the women can see and hear are
vociferous opponents of abortion, then the buffer zones have
effectively stifled petitioners’ message.
Finally, respondents
suggest that, at the Worcester and Springfield clinics, petitioners
are prevented from communicating with patients not by the buffer
zones but by the fact that most patients arrive by car and park in
the clinics’ private lots. Id., at 52. It is true that the layout
of the two clinics would prevent petitioners from approaching the
clinics’ doorways, even without the buffer zones. But petitioners
do not claim a right to trespass on the clinics’ property. They
instead claim a right to stand on the public sidewalks by the
driveway as cars turn into the parking lot. Before the buffer
zones, they could do so. Now they must stand a substantial distance
away. The Act alone is responsible for that restriction on their
ability to convey their message.
B
1
The buffer zones
burden substantially more speech than necessary to achieve the
Commonwealth’s asserted interests. At the outset, we note that the
Act is truly exceptional: Respondents and their amici identify no
other State with a law that creates fixed buffer zones around
abortion clinics.[
6] That of
course does not mean that the law is invalid. It does, however,
raise concern that the Commonwealth has too readily forgone options
that could serve its interests just as well, without substantially
burdening the kind of speech in which petitioners wish to
engage.
That is the case here.
The Commonwealth’s interests include ensuring public safety outside
abortion clinics, preventing harassment and intimidation of
patients and clinic staff, and combating deliberate obstruction of
clinic entrances. The Act itself contains a separate provision,
subsection (e)—unchallenged by petitioners—that prohibits much of
this conduct. That provision subjects to criminal punishment “[a]ny
person who knowingly obstructs, detains, hinders, impedes or blocks
another person’s entry to or exit from a reproductive health care
facility.” Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 266, §120E½(e).[
7] If Massachusetts determines that broader
prohibitions along the same lines are necessary, it could enact
legislation similar to the federal Freedom of Access to Clinic
Entrances Act of 1994 (FACE Act), 18 U. S. C. §248(a)(1),
which subjects to both criminal and civil penalties anyone who “by
force or threat of force or by physical obstruction, intentionally
injures, intimidates or interferes with or attempts to injure,
intimidate or interfere with any person because that person is or
has been, or in order to intimidate such person or any other person
or any class of persons from, obtaining or providing reproductive
health services.” Some dozen other States have done so. See Brief
for State of New York et al. as Amici Curiae 13, and
n. 6. If the Commonwealth is particularly concerned about
harassment, it could also consider an ordinance such as the one
adopted in New York City that not only prohibits obstructing access
to a clinic, but also makes it a crime “to follow and harass
another person within 15 feet of the premises of a reproductive
health care facility.” N. Y. C. Admin. Code §8–803(a)(3)
(2014).[
8]
The Commonwealth points
to a substantial public safety risk created when protestors
obstruct driveways leading to the clinics. See App. 18, 41, 51,
88–89, 99, 118–119. That is, however, an example of its failure to
look to less intrusive means of addressing its concerns. Any such
obstruction can readily be addressed through existing local
ordinances. See, e.g., Worcester, Mass., Revised Ordinances of
2008, ch. 12, §25(b) (“No person shall stand, or place any
obstruction of any kind, upon any street, sidewalk or crosswalk in
such a manner as to obstruct a free passage for travelers
thereon”); Boston, Mass., Municipal Code, ch. 16–41.2(d) (2013)
(“No person shall solicit while walking on, standing on or going
into any street or highway used for motor vehicle travel, or any
area appurtenant thereto (including medians, shoulder areas,
bicycle lanes, ramps and exit ramps)”).
All of the foregoing
measures are, of course, in addition to available generic criminal
statutes forbidding assault, breach of the peace, trespass,
vandalism, and the like.
In addition, subsection
(e) of the Act, the FACE Act, and the New York City anti-harassment
ordinance are all enforceable not only through criminal
prosecutions but also through public and private civil actions for
injunctions and other equitable relief. See Mass. Gen. Laws
§120E½(f); 18 U. S. C. §248(c)(1); N. Y. C.
Admin. Code §§8–804, 8–805. We have previously noted the First
Amendment virtues of targeted injunctions as alternatives to broad,
prophylactic measures. Such an injunction “regulates the
activities, and perhaps the speech, of a group,” but only “because
of the group’s past actions in the context of a specific dispute
between real parties.” Madsen, 512 U. S., at 762 (emphasis
added). Moreover, given the equitable nature of injunctive relief,
courts can tailor a remedy to ensure that it restricts no more
speech than necessary. See, e.g., id., at 770; Schenck, 519
U. S., at 380–381. In short, injunctive relief focuses on the
precise individuals and the precise conduct causing a particular
problem. The Act, by contrast, categorically excludes non-exempt
individuals from the buffer zones, unnecessarily sweeping in
innocent individuals and their speech.
The Commonwealth also
asserts an interest in preventing congestion in front of abortion
clinics. According to respondents, even when individuals do not
deliberately obstruct access to clinics, they can inadvertently do
so simply by gathering in large numbers. But the Commonwealth could
address that problem through more targeted means. Some localities,
for example, have ordinances that require crowds blocking a clinic
entrance to disperse when ordered to do so by the police, and that
forbid the individuals to reassemble within a certain distance of
the clinic for a certain period. See Brief for State of New York
et al. as Amici Curiae 14–15, and n. 10. We upheld a
similar law forbidding three or more people “ ‘to congregate
within 500 feet of [a foreign embassy], and refuse to disperse
after having been ordered so to do by the police,’ ” Boos, 485
U. S., at 316 (quoting D. C. Code §22–1115 (1938))—an
order the police could give only when they “ ‘reasonably
believe[d] that a threat to the security or peace of the embassy
[was] present,’ ” 485 U. S., at 330 (quoting Finzer v.
Barry, 798 F. 2d 1450, 1471 (CADC 1986)).
And to the extent the
Commonwealth argues that even these types of laws are ineffective,
it has another problem. The portions of the record that respondents
cite to support the anticongestion interest pertain mainly to one
place at one time: the Boston Planned Parenthood clinic on Saturday
mornings. App. 69–71, 88–89, 96, 123. Respondents point us to no
evidence that individuals regularly gather at other clinics, or at
other times in Boston, in sufficiently large groups to obstruct
access. For a problem shown to arise only once a week in one city
at one clinic, creating 35-foot buffer zones at every clinic across
the Commonwealth is hardly a narrowly tailored solution.
The point is not that
Massachusetts must enact all or even any of the proposed measures
discussed above. The point is instead that the Commonwealth has
available to it a variety of approaches that appear capable of
serving its interests, without excluding individuals from areas
historically open for speech and debate.
2
Respondents have but
one reply: “We have tried other approaches, but they do not work.”
Respondents emphasize the history in Massachusetts of obstruction
at abortion clinics, and the Commonwealth’s allegedly failed
attempts to combat such obstruction with injunctions and individual
prosecutions. They also point to the Commonwealth’s experience
under the 2000 version of the Act, during which the police found it
difficult to enforce the six-foot no-approach zones given the
“frenetic” activity in front of clinic entrances. Brief for
Respondents 43. According to respondents, this history shows that
Massachusetts has tried less restrictive alternatives to the buffer
zones, to no avail.
We cannot accept that
contention. Although respondents claim that Massachusetts “tried
other laws already on the books,” id., at 41, they identify not a
single prosecution brought under those laws within at least the
last 17 years. And while they also claim that the Commonwealth
“tried injunctions,” ibid., the last injunctions they cite date to
the 1990s, see id., at 42 (citing Planned Parenthood League of
Mass., Inc. v. Bell, 424 Mass. 573, 677 N. E. 2d 204 (1997);
Planned Parenthood League of Mass., Inc. v. Operation Rescue, 406
Mass. 701, 550 N. E. 2d 1361 (1990)). In short, the
Commonwealth has not shown that it seriously undertook to address
the problem with less intrusive tools readily available to it. Nor
has it shown that it considered different methods that other
jurisdictions have found effective.
Respondents contend
that the alternatives we have discussed suffer from two defects:
First, given the “widespread” nature of the problem, it is simply
not “practicable” to rely on individual prosecutions and
injunctions. Brief for Respondents 45. But far from being
“widespread,” the problem appears from the record to be limited
principally to the Boston clinic on Saturday mornings. Moreover, by
their own account, the police appear per-fectly capable of singling
out lawbreakers. The legislative testimony preceding the 2007 Act
revealed substantial police and video monitoring at the clinics,
especially when large gatherings were anticipated. Captain Evans
testified that his officers are so familiar with the scene outside
the Boston clinic that they “know all the players down there.” App.
69. And Attorney General Coakley relied on video surveillance to
show legislators conduct she thought was “clearly against the law.”
Id., at 78. If Commonwealth officials can compile an extensive
record of obstruction and harassment to support their preferred
legislation, we do not see why they cannot do the same to support
injunctions and prosecutions against those who might deliberately
flout the law.
The second supposed
defect in the alternatives we have identified is that laws like
subsection (e) of the Act and the federal FACE Act require a
showing of intentional or deliberate obstruction, intimidation, or
harassment, which is often difficult to prove. Brief for
Respondents 45–47. As Captain Evans predicted in his legislative
testimony, fixed buffer zones would “make our job so much easier.”
App. 68.
Of course they would.
But that is not enough to satisfy the First Amendment. To meet the
requirement of narrow tailoring, the government must demonstrate
that alternative measures that burden substantially less speech
would fail to achieve the government’s interests, not simply that
the chosen route is easier. A painted line on the sidewalk is easy
to enforce, but the prime objective of the First Amendment is not
efficiency. In any case, we do not think that showing intentional
obstruction is nearly so difficult in this context as respondents
suggest. To determine whether a protestor intends to block access
to a clinic, a police officer need only order him to move. If he
refuses, then there is no question that his continued conduct is
knowing or intentional.
For similar reasons,
respondents’ reliance on our decision in Burson v. Freeman is
misplaced. There, we upheld a state statute that established
100-foot buffer zones outside polling places on election day within
which no one could display or distribute campaign materials or
solicit votes. 504 U. S., at 193–194. We approved the buffer
zones as a valid prophylactic measure, noting that existing
“[i]ntimidation and interference laws fall short of serving a
State’s compelling interests because they ‘deal with only the most
blatant and specific attempts’ to impede elections.” Id., at
206–207 (quoting Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S. 1, 28 (1976) (per
curiam)). Such laws were insufficient because “[v]oter intimidation
and election fraud are . . . difficult to detect.”
Burson, 504 U. S., at 208. Obstruction of abortion clinics and
harassment of patients, by contrast, are anything but subtle.
We also noted in Burson
that under state law, “law enforcement officers generally are
barred from the vicinity of the polls to avoid any appearance of
coercion in the electoral process,” with the result that “many acts
of interference would go undetected.” Id., at 207. Not so here.
Again, the police maintain a significant presence outside
Massachusetts abortion clinics. The buffer zones in Burson were
justified because less restrictive measures were inadequate.
Respondents have not shown that to be the case here.
Given the vital First
Amendment interests at stake, it is not enough for Massachusetts
simply to say that other approaches have not worked.[
9]
* * *
Petitioners wish to
converse with their fellow citizens about an important subject on
the public streets and sidewalks—sites that have hosted discussions
about the issues of the day throughout history. Respondents assert
undeniably significant interests in maintaining public safety on
those same streets and sidewalks, as well as in preserving access
to adjacent healthcare facilities. But here the Commonwealth has
pursued those interests by the extreme step of closing a
substantial portion of a traditional public forum to all speakers.
It has done so without seriously addressing the problem through
alternatives that leave the forum open for its time-honored
purposes. The Commonwealth may not do that consistent with the
First Amendment.
The judgment of the
Court of Appeals for the First Circuit is reversed, and the case is
remanded for further proceedings consistent with this opinion.
It is so ordered.